Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-m8qmq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T13:54:12.039Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

How Do Natural Selection and Random Drift Interact?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

One controversy about the existence of so called evolutionary forces such as natural selection and random genetic drift concerns the sense in which such “forces” can be said to interact. In this paper I explain how natural selection and random drift can interact. In particular, I show how population-level probabilities can be derived from individual-level probabilities, and explain the sense in which natural selection and drift are embodied in these population-level probabilities. I argue that whatever causal character the individual-level probabilities have is then shared by the population-level probabilities, and that natural selection and random drift then have that same causal character. Moreover, natural selection and drift can then be viewed as two aspects of probability distributions over frequencies in populations of organisms. My characterization of population-level probabilities is largely neutral about what interpretation of probability is required, allowing my approach to support various positions on biological probabilities, including those which give biological probabilities one or another sort of causal character.

Type
Philosophy of Biology
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

This paper has benefited from feedback on and discussions of this and earlier work. I want to thank André Ariew, Matt Barker, Lindley Darden, Patrick Forber, Nancy Hall, Mohan Matthen, Samir Okasha, Jeremy Pober, Robert Richardson, Alex Rosenberg, Eric Seidel, Denis Walsh, and Bill Wimsatt.

References

Abrams, Marshall (2005), “The Causal Structure of Biological Fitness”, manuscript. Birmingham: University of Alabama.Google Scholar
Abrams, Marshall (2007), “Fitness and Propensity’s Annulment?”, Fitness and Propensity’s Annulment? 22:115130.Google Scholar
Ariew, André, and Lewontin, Richard C. (2004), “The Confusions of Fitness”, The Confusions of Fitness 55:347363.Google Scholar
Beatty, John (1992), “Random Drift”, in Keller, Evelyn Fox and Lloyd, Elisabeth A. (eds.), Keywords in Evolutionary Biology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 273281.Google Scholar
Beatty, John, and Finsen, Susan (1989), “Rethinking the Propensity Interpretation: A Peek inside Pandora’s Box”, in Ruse, Michael (ed.), What the Philosophy of Biology Is. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1730.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bharucha-Reid, A. T. ([1960] 1996), Elements of the Theory of Markov Processes and Their Applications. New York: Dover.Google Scholar
Bouchard, Frederic, and Rosenberg, Alex (2004), “Fitness, Probability, and the Principles of Natural Selection”, Fitness, Probability, and the Principles of Natural Selection 55:693712.Google Scholar
Brandon, Robert N. (1978), “Adaptation and Evolutionary Theory”, Adaptation and Evolutionary Theory 9:181206.Google Scholar
Brandon, Robert N. (1990), Adaptation and Environment. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brandon, Robert N., and Ramsey, Grant (2007), “What’s Wrong with the Emergentist Statistical Interpretation of Natural Selection and Random Drift?”, in Hull, David and Ruse, Michael (eds.), Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 6684.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burian, Richard M. (1983), “Adaptation”, in Grene, Marjorie (ed.), Dimensions of Darwinism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 286314.Google Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy (1983), “Do the Laws of Physics State the Facts?”, in How the Laws of Physics Lie. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 5473.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Corben, H. C., and Stehle, P. (1994), Classical Mechanics. 2nd ed. New York: Dover.Google Scholar
Eagle, Antony (2004), “Twenty-one Arguments against Propensity Analyses of Probability”, Twenty-one Arguments against Propensity Analyses of Probability 60:371416.Google Scholar
Gillespie, John H. (1998), Population Genetics: A Concise Guide. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Graves, Leslie, Horan, Barbara L., and Rosenberg, Alex (1999), “Is Indeterminism the Source of the Statistical Character of Evolutionary Theory?”, Is Indeterminism the Source of the Statistical Character of Evolutionary Theory? 66:140157.Google Scholar
Grimmett, G. R., and Stirzacker, D. R. (1992), Probability and Random Processes. 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Grimmett, G. R, and Welsh, D. J. A. (1986), Probability: An Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Krimbas, Costas B. (2004). “On Fitness”, Biology and Philosophy 19:185203.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Matthen, Mohan, and Ariew, André (2002), “Two Ways of Thinking about Fitness and Natural Selection”, Two Ways of Thinking about Fitness and Natural Selection 99:5583.Google Scholar
Matthen, Mohan, and Ariew, André (2005), “How to Understand Causal Relations in Natural Selection: A Reply to Rosenberg and Bouchard”, How to Understand Causal Relations in Natural Selection: A Reply to Rosenberg and Bouchard 20:355364.Google Scholar
Millikan, Ruth Garrett (2000), “What Has Natural Information to Do with Intentional Representation?”, in On Clear and Confused Ideas. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 217237.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mills, Susan, and Beatty, John (1979), “The Propensity Interpretation of Fitness”, The Propensity Interpretation of Fitness 46:263286.Google Scholar
Millstein, Roberta L. (2003), “Interpretations of Probability in Evolutionary Theory”, Interpretations of Probability in Evolutionary Theory 70:13171328.Google Scholar
Millstein, Roberta L. (2006), “Natural Selection as a Population-Level Causal Process”, Natural Selection as a Population-Level Causal Process 57:627653.Google Scholar
Plutynski, Anya (2005), “The Levels of Drift Debate”, presentation at the 2005 meeting of the International Society for the History, Philosophy, and Social Studies of Biology.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. (1959), “The Propensity Interpretation of Probability”, The Propensity Interpretation of Probability 10:2542.Google Scholar
Reisman, Kenneth, and Forber, Patrick (2005), “Manipulation and the Causes of Evolution”, Manipulation and the Causes of Evolution 72:11131123.Google Scholar
Richardson, Robert C., and Burian, Richard M. (1992), “A Defense of Propensity Interpretations of Fitness”, in Forbes, Mickey (ed.), PSA 1992, Vol. 1. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association, 349362.Google Scholar
Rosenberg, Alex (2001), “Indeterminism, Probability, and Randomness in Evolutionary Theory”, Indeterminism, Probability, and Randomness in Evolutionary Theory 68:536544.Google Scholar
Rosenberg, Alex, and Bouchard, Frederic (2005), “Matthen and Ariew’s Obituary for Fitness: Reports of Its Death Have Been Greatly Exaggerated”, Matthen and Ariew’s Obituary for Fitness: Reports of Its Death Have Been Greatly Exaggerated 20:343353.Google Scholar
Roughgarden, Jonathan (1979), Theory of Population Genetics and Evolutionary Ecology: An Introduction. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Shapiro, L., and Sober, E. (2007), “Epiphenomenalism—the Do’s and the Don’ts”, in Wolters, Gereon and Machamer, Peter (eds.), Studies in Causality: Historical and Contemporary. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 235264.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliott (1984), The Nature of Selection. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliott (2000), Philosophy of Biology. 2nd ed. Boulder, CO: Westview.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliott (2001), “The Two Faces of Fitness”, in Singh, R. S., Krimbas, C. B., Paul, D. B., and Beatty, J. (eds.), Thinking about Evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 309321.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliott (2007), “Evolutionary Theory and the Reality of Macro Probabilities”, in Eells, Ellery and Fetzer, James (eds.), Probability in Science. LaSalle, IL: Open Court, forthcoming.Google Scholar
Stephens, Christopher (2005), “Selection, Drift, and the ‘Forces’ of Evolution”, Selection, Drift, and the ‘Forces’ of Evolution 71:550570.Google Scholar
Walsh, Denis M. (2000), “Chasing Shadows: Natural Selection and Adaptation”, Chasing Shadows: Natural Selection and Adaptation 31:135153.Google Scholar
Walsh, Denis M., Lewens, Tim, and Ariew, André (2002), “The Trials of Life: Natural Selection and Random Drift”, The Trials of Life: Natural Selection and Random Drift 69:452473.Google Scholar
Weber, Marcel (2001), “Determinism, Realism, and Probability in Evolutionary Theory: The Pitfalls, and How to Avoid Them”, Determinism, Realism, and Probability in Evolutionary Theory: The Pitfalls, and How to Avoid Them 68:S213S224.Google Scholar
Woodward, James (2003), Making Things Happen. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar