Skip to main content
Log in

Novel Predictions and the No Miracle Argument

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Predictivists use the no miracle argument to argue that “novel” predictions are decisive evidence for theories, while mere accommodation of “old” data cannot confirm to a significant degree. But deductivists claim that since confirmation is a logical theory-data relationship, predicted data cannot confirm more than merely deduced data, and cite historical cases in which known data confirmed theories quite strongly. On the other hand, the advantage of prediction over accommodation is needed by scientific realists to resist Laudan’s criticisms of the no miracle argument. So, if the deductivists are right, the most powerful argument for realism collapses. There seems to be an inescapable contradiction between these prima facie plausible arguments of predictivists and deductivists; but this puzzle can be solved by understanding what exactly counts as novelty, if novel predictions must support the no miracle argument, i.e., if they must be explainable only by the truth of theories. Taking my cues from the use-novelty tradition, I argue that (1) the predicted data must not be used essentially in building the theory or choosing the auxiliary assumptions. This is possible if the theory and its auxiliary assumptions are plausible independently of the predicted data, and I analyze the consequences of this requirement in terms of best explanation of diverse bodies of data. Moreover, the predicted data must be (2) a priori improbable, and (3) heterogeneous to the essentially used data. My proposed notion of novelty, therefore, is not historical, but functional. Hence, deductivists are right that confirmation is independent of time and of historical contingencies such as if the theorist knew a datum, used it, or intended to accommodate it. Predictivists, however, are right that not all consequences confirm equally, and confirmation is not purely a logical theory-data relation, as it crucially involves background epistemic conditions and the notion of best explanation. Conditions (1)–(3) make the difference between prediction and accommodation, and account for the confirming power of theoretical virtues such as non ad-hocness, non-fudging, non-overfitting, independence and consilience. I thus show that functional novelty (a) avoids the deductivist objections to predictivism, (b) is a gradual notion, in accordance with the common intuition that confirmation comes in degrees, and (c) supports the no miracle argument, so vindicating scientific realism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Lyons (2002) has countered that even particular claims which were essential in deriving novel predictions have been shown to false. For a discussion and a reply see (Alai 2013).

  2. The predictivism–deductivism debate has been sketched in Lakatos (1970, 123–124), Musgrave (1974, 1–3), Lipton (1991, ch. 10), Barnes (2008, ch. 1), etc.

  3. In fact, what is commonly called deductivism should be called more precisely ‘consequentialism’, for consequences can be both deductive and inductive (as was brought to my attention by an anonymous reviewer for this Journal). This sense of ‘deductivism’ is altogether different from two others: (1) Alan Musgrave’s idea that induction is really a form of deduction with an implicit epistemic premise (its opposite being inductivism), and (2) Popper’s theory of empirical control (see Grunbaum, Salmon (eds.) 1988). I owe this distinction to Howard Sankey.

  4. The presupposition of earlier theories by the theorist or by her method does not launch an infinite regress, since the earliest, “take-off” theories were introduced without relying on previous theories or on theory-dependent methods (Barnes 2008, 146–155).

  5. Musgrave (1974, § 2) and Barnes (2008) speak of a “paradox”, and Lipton (1991) of a “puzzle”.

  6. See Gardner (1982, 1-ff), Leplin (1997, Chaps. 2, 3), Barnes (2008, Chap. 1).

  7. Zahar (1973 §1.1). See Gardner (1982, p. 2), Maher (1993, p. 339).

  8. Tacitly and perhaps unconsciously: see Gardner (1982, p. 3), Leplin (1997, p. 50).

  9. So long as e was not used in constructing … theory T, then … there is no question of any reduction of support …” Worrall 2005, 818; see also ibid., 819, etc.); “… the crucial difference is that in cases of little or no support, certain aspects of the theory were fixed precisely to yield the phenomenon at issue” (Scerri and Worrall 2001, 423); predictions give little support when “the fact was both known and used in the construction of the theory” (ibid., 424; also 426, etc.).

  10. I owe this suggestion to Vincenzo Fano.

  11. For this distinction and the related problems, see Lipton (1991, 177–183).

  12. This solution of the twin scientists paradox is similar, although standing on a more complete basis, to that proposed by Lipton himself: (1991, 182).

  13. As conceded by Scerri and Worrall (2001, 423); see also Worrall (1978, 50–51, 68).

  14. Scerri and Worrall (2001, 440). Instead Leplin (1997) ignores the role of auxiliary assumptions.

  15. Like the melting point of a metal in future occasions is extrapolated from the same value in observed occasions.

  16. It might be suggested that given the holistic nature of confirmation, this regress will eventually involve all the available empirical data. I don’t know if this must necessarily be the case.

  17. As Worrall suggests in (2006, 39).

  18. Whewell (1858, 86–88). This was brought to my attention by an anonymous reviewer for this Journal.

  19. One juror, Poisson, wrote: “The theory of emission and that of waves both encounter great difficulties; time and the future work of physicists and mathematicians will perhaps end by settling these doubts …” (cited in Worrall 1989b, 140).

  20. The gap between the objective support of d to T, and our subjective assessment of it has been discussed by Lipton (1991, 177–183).

References

  • Alai, M. (2013). Defending deployment realism against alleged counterexamples. In G. Bonino, J. Cumpa & G. Jesson (Eds.) Defending Realism. Ontological and epistemological investigations. Frankfurt a.M.: Ontos Verlag.

  • Barnes, E. C. (2005). On Mendeleev’s predictions: Comment on Scerri and Worrall. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 36, 817–826.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, E. C. (2008). The paradox of predictivism. Cambridge etc.: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1981). Scientific realism and naturalistic epistemology PSA 1980 Vol. 2 (pp. 612–662). East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brush, S. G. (1994). Dynamics of theory change: The role of predictions. In D. L. Hull, M. Forbes, & R. M. Burian (Eds.), PSA 1994 (Vol. 1, pp. 133–145). Philosophy of Science Association: East Lansing, MI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brush, S. G. (1996). The reception of Mendeleev’s periodic law in America and Britain. Isis, 87, 595–628.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brush, S. G. (2007). Predictivism and the periodic table. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 38, 256–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, S., & Lyons, T. D. (Eds.). (2002). Recent themes in the philosophy of science. Scientific Realism and Commonsense. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  • Doppelt, G. (2005). Empirical success or explanatory success: What does current scientific realism need to explain? Philosophy of Science, 72, 1076–1087.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J., & Glymour, C. (1978). Einstein and Hilbert: Two months on the history of general relativity. Archive for History of Exact Sciences, 19, 291–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1983). Foundations of space–time theories. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, M. (1982). Predicting novel facts. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 33(1), 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grunbaum, A., & Salmon, W. (Eds.). (1988). The limits of deductivism. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcok, C., & Sober, E. (2004). Prediction vs. accommodation and the risk of overfitting. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 55, 1–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hudson, G. R. (2007). What’s really at issue with novel predictions? Synthese, 155(1), 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutchison, K. (2002). Rankine’s thermodynamics. In Clarke, S., Lyons, T.D. (Eds.), 91–120.

  • Keynes, J. M. (1921/2007). A treatise on probabilities. London: Macmillan & co. (New York, N.Y. Cosimo).

  • Kitcher, P. (1993). The advancement of science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kosso, P. (1992). Reading the book of nature. An introduction to philosophy of science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. (2002). Understanding philosophy of science. London, New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1968). Changes in the problem of inductive logic. In I. Lakatos (Ed.), The problem of inductive logic (pp. 315–417). Amsterdam: North Holland Pub. Co.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1970). Falsificationism and the methodology of scientific research programmes. In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge (pp. 91–195). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1981) A Confutation of Convergent Realism. Philosophy of Science, 48, 19–49. Reprint.in D.Papineau, (ed.), The Philosophy of Science. Oxford: University Press 1996 (pp. 107–138)

  • Laudan, L. (1996). Beyond positivism and relativism. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leplin, J. (1997). A novel defence of scientific realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (1991). Inference to the best explanation, London: Routledge (20042).

  • Lipton, P. (1994). Truth, existence, and the best explanation. In A. A. Derkson (Ed.), The scientific realism of Rom Harré. Tilburg: University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, T. D. (2002). The Pessimistic Meta-Modus Tollens. In Clarke, S. & Lyons, T.D. (Eds.), 63–90.

  • Maher, P. (1988). Prediction, accommodation and the logic of discovery. PSA, 1, 273–285.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maher, P. (1993). Howson and Franklin on prediction. Philosophy of Science, 60(2), 329–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McIntyre L.C. (2001). Accommodation, prediction, confirmation. Perspectives on Science 9 no. 3, 308–323.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musgrave, A. (1974). Logical vs. historical theories of confirmation. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 25, 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Musgrave, A. (1985). Realism versus Constructive Empiricism. In P. M. Churchland & C. A. Hooker (Eds.), Images of science (pp. 197–221). Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musgrave, A. (1988). The ultimate argument for scientific realism. In R. Nola (Ed.), Realism and relativism in science (pp. 229–252). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (1999). Critical scientific realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1965). Conjectures and Refutations. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1979). Die beiden grundprobleme der erkenntnistheorie. Mohr-Siebeck: Tübingen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific realism. How science tracks truth. London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). Mathematics, matter and method: Philosophical papers vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sankey, H. (2001). Scientific realism: An elaboration and a defense. Theoria, 98, 35–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scerri, E. R., & Worrall, J. (2001). Prediction and the periodic table. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 32, 407–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlick, M. (1931). Die Kausalität in der gegenwärtigen Physik. Die Naturwissenschaften, 19, 145–162.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smart, J. J. C. (1968). Between science and philosophy. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, K. J. (2000). An antirealist explanation of the success of science. Philosophy of Science, 67, 266–284.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Whewell, W. (1847). The philosophy of inductive sciences (2nd ed., p. 1967). London: John W. Parker, repr. Johnson Reprint Corp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whewell, W. (1858). Novum organon renovatum. London: John W. Parker.

    Google Scholar 

  • White, R. (2003). The epistemic advantage of prediction over accommodation. Mind, 112(448), 653–683.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J. (1978). The ways in which the methodology of scientific research programmes improves on Popper’s methodology. In G. Radnitzky & G. Anderson (Eds.), Progress and rationality in science, Boston studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. 58, pp. 45–70). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J. (1985). Scientific discovery and theory-confirmation. In J. Pitt (Ed.), Change and progress in modern science. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J. (1989a). Structural realism: The best of both worlds?” Dialectica 43, 99–124. Repr. in D. Papineau (Ed.), Philosophy of science. Oxford: Oxford University Press 1996.

    Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J. (1989b). Fresnel, Poisson and the white spot: The role of successful predictions in the acceptation of scientific theories. In D. Gooding, T. Pinch, & S. Schaffer (Eds.), The use of experiment: Studies in the natural Sciences (pp. 135–157). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J. (2005). Prediction and the ‘periodic law’: A rejoinder to Barnes. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 36, 817–826.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J. (2006). Theory-confirmation and history. In C. Cheyne & J. Worrall (Eds.), Rationality and reality: Conversations with Alan Musgrave (pp. 31–61). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, J. (2002). Some surprising phenomena and some unsatisfactory explanations of them. In S. Clarke & T.D. Lyons, (Eds.), 139–153.

  • Zahar, E. (1973). “Why did Einstein’s programme supersede Lorentz’s?” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 24, 95–123 (I), 223–262 (II).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I have greatly benefited from comments and suggestions by Anjan Chakravartty, Vincenzo Crupi, Dennis Dieks, Michel Ghins, F.A. Muller, Howard Sankey and two Referees for this Journal. I am particularly grateful to my colleagues Vincenzo Fano and Gino Tarozzi for frequent discussions and useful advices.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mario Alai.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Alai, M. Novel Predictions and the No Miracle Argument. Erkenn 79, 297–326 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-013-9495-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-013-9495-7

Keywords

Navigation