Skip to main content
Log in

Colour Physicalism, Naïve Realism, and the Argument from Structure

  • Published:
Minds and Machines Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Colours appear to instantiate a number of structural properties: for instance, they stand in distinctive relations of similarity and difference, and admit of a fundamental distinction into unique and binary. Accounting for these structural properties is often taken to present a serious problem for physicalist theories of colour. This paper argues that a prominent attempt by Byrne and Hilbert (Behav Brain Sci 26:3–21, 2003) to account for the structural properties of the colours, consistent with the claim that colours are types of surface spectral reflectance, is unsuccessful. Instead, it is suggested that a better account of the structural properties of the colours is provided by a form of non-reductive physicalism about colour: a naïve realist theory of colour, according to which colours are superficial mind-independent properties.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The claim that the structural properties are necessary properties of the colours is not always sharply distinguished from the claim that they are essential properties. But necessary and essential properties are not obvious identical: as Fine (1994) argues, Socrates is plausibly necessarily, but not essentially, a member of the singleton set {Socrates}. The essentialist claim seems to me to better capture the content of the relevant intuition, although I will not argue for this here. Note that the weaker claim that the structural properties are necessary properties of the colours is sufficient to set non-trivial constraints on what the colours could be.

  2. The claim that the structural properties of the colours are essential properties of the colours is consistent with treating colours as kinds, assuming that kinds have certain properties essentially. However, it is does not necessarily imply that colours are natural kinds, if this means that colours are properties with a complex physical or micro-physical essence. According to the naïve realist theory of colour defended below, colours can be thought of as superficial kinds.

  3. Some versions of the Argument from Structure do not rely on the claim that colours are necessary or essential properties of the colours. The version of the argument presented here is more controversial in this respect, but stronger as a result. The distinction between non-modal and modal versions of the argument is noted by Cohen (2003); see below for some discussion.

  4. Related argument with epistemic premisses are presented by Boghossian and Velleman (1991) and Johnston (1992). Johnston, for instance, argues that if colours are physical properties, then their structural properties could only be discovered by empirical investigation. But this violates a what he takes to be core common sense belief about the colours, Availability, that ‘Justified belief about the canary yellowness of external things is available simply on the basis of visual perception’ (1992: 138). The advantage of the present argument is that it does not appeal to this principle, which it would be open to physicalists to reject.

  5. An alternative way of developing this general line of response is to argue that the structural properties are properties of experience that are falsely attributed to the colours (e.g. Churchland 2007). This is problematic for broadly the same reasons as the view considered in the text. A more radical response is to deny that the structural properties of the colours are essential properties of anything at all, as opposed to being artefacts of our linguistic representations (e.g. Saunders and van Brakel 1997; Mizrahi 2009). I will not address this form of relativism here, but for some relevant discussion see Jraissati (2014).

  6. The phenomenological claim that colours appear to be mind-independent properties of things in the environment—rather than, say, mind-dependent dispositional or relational properties—is sometimes denied (e.g. Cohen 2009; Chirimuuta 2011). However, for defences of this claim, see e.g. Allen 2007; Roberts et al. (2014).

  7. On the ‘inheritance’ metaphor and its relationship to the transparency intuition, see e.g. Campbell (1993); Shoemaker (2003); Kalderon (2011).

  8. For more detailed discussion of problems with versions of this approach, see e.g. Byrne (2003); Pautz (2006); Cohen (2009); Davies (2014).

  9. Davies (2014) defends a view of this kind, comparing this response to ‘type-B’ physicalist accounts of the mental. Davies’s defence of this approach is programmatic, noting that colour physicalists can adapt whatever turns out to be the best type-B physicalist account of the mental. Assuming that a viable type-B physicalism about the mental is forthcoming, it would still need to be shown that this approach can be adapted to allow for experience to provide knowledge of essential structural properties of the colours without collapsing into a form of a dual aspect theory. Type-B physicalists often appeal to phenomenal concepts to explain the different mode of access to physical properties that experience provides. However, phenomenal concepts are often taken to provide only a ‘thin’, demonstrative, characterization of their referents, in which case it is difficult to see how they could provide substantive knowledge of the essential structural properties of the colours. Alternatively, if phenomenal concepts provide more substantive characterisations of their referents that allow for knowledge of their structural properties not provided by physical concepts (as e.g. Schroer 2010 suggests), then it begins to sound as though colours are properties whose essential nature is not fully physical.

  10. Or to account for coloured light sources, types of productance more generally (e.g. Byrne and Hilbert 2003). However, I will focus on SSR’s here.

  11. The microphysical properties of objects with which some physicalists identify colours appear even less plausible candidates for instantiating the relevant structural properties.

  12. It was initially thought that opponent cells in the laternal geniculate nucleus (LGN) discovered in the 1960s were the neural realisers of the psychophysical opponent channels hypothesised by Hering to explain (amongst other things) the unique-binary structure of the hues. However, it now seems that experiences of the unique hues cannot be explained solely by the activity of opponent cells in the LGN firing in response to signals from the retinal receptors, and a third stage of processing has been hypothesised, the neural basis for which has yet to be identified (e.g. De Valois and De Valois 1993; Abramov 1997; for discussion, see e.g. Jameson and D’Andrade 1997; Jraissati 2014; Degenaar and Myin 2014).

  13. Even if you reject the Lockean simplicity intuition, it is further question whether colour experience exhibits precisely the kind of complexity that Byrne and Hilbert ascribe to it. See Sundström (2013) for discussion of two different ways colours might appear to be complex, only one of which corresponds the complexity attributed by Byrne and Hilbert.

  14. For instance, Shamey et al. (2011) found that the majority of subjects agreed with the physical sample that the NCS describes as unique red, they mostly agreed with NCS unique green, but a majority disagreed with the samples described by the NCS as unique blue and yellow. In each case, the mean samples picked as representing unique hues varied between subjects.

  15. According to Koenderink ‘I fail to see red and blue in a pure purple, just as I fail to see red and green in a pure yellow (2010: 579). He argues further that the six basic hue model captures alterations of brightness amongst the hues (that yellow, cyan, and magenta are relatively bright, and red, green, and blue relatively dark), and allows for the basic hues to be equally spaced around the colour circle.

  16. Compare Shamey et al. (2011) who conclude that ‘The above finding supports that uHs [unique hues] are a well established concept in the minds of subjects that have not had extensive exposure to the idea’. Describing these ‘cognitive references’ as ‘built-in’ suggests that they are innate; a slight variation on this would be to hold that they are learnt through experience.

  17. Compare Mizrahi (2009). Mizrahi defends a form of conventionalism about the unique/binary distinction. However, the view that perceiving similarities between the colours involves a form of ‘seeing as’ does not entail conventionalism, if certain ways of seeing colours are privileged.

  18. As Sivik remarks describing the decision to arrange the hues ordered by the NCS around a circle, rather than a square: ‘since the hue circle is such a well established concept, everybody yielded to this convention. One should, however, be aware of the fact that the hue circle is conceptually not one scale but four’ (Sivik 1997: 176).

  19. This is noted as a potential problem by Byrne (2003: 661, n. 40) but no attempt is made to address it.

  20. Primitivism is sometimes characterised as a view that comes in realist and eliminativist forms, depending on whether colours are primitive properties that physical objects (actually) instantiate (e.g. Pautz 2006). As I understand it, naïve realism is not neutral in this respect. For further discussion, see e.g. Allen (2011).

  21. Naïve realist theories of colour have become increasingly popular in recent years. Proponents include Campbell (1993), Yablo (1995), Watkins (2010), and Dorsch (2010). For discussion, see Byrne and Hilbert (2007).

  22. Compare Dorsch (2010). Pautz (2006) uses the Argument from Structure to motivate a form of eliminativist primitivism. However, Pautz’s eliminativism does not sit easily with the ‘Relational View’ of colour experience that he uses to motivate primitivism, according to which ‘the structural properties of colours are simply inherited from (or amount to) the structural properties of the colours that we are sensorily related to in having those colour experiences’ (2006: 543). The most natural interpretation of the Relational View is that the properties of objects that we are sensorily related to in perception are actually instantiated by those objects. In denying this, Pautz appears to accept an error theory of the general kind that he is otherwise keen to avoid.

  23. A different line of objection focuses on the claim that colours are mind-independent, which represents common ground between the naïve realist and the reductive physicalist. I consider attempts to undermine this claim by appealing to variations in perceptual experience elsewhere (Allen 2009, 2010).

References

  • Abramov, I. (1997). Physiological mechanisms of color vision. In C. L. Hardin & L. Maffi (Eds.), Color categories in thought and language (pp. 89–117). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Allen, K. (2007). The mind-independence of colour. European Journal of Philosophy 15(2), 137–158.

  • Allen, K. (2009). Inter-species variation in colour perception. Philosophical Studies 142(2), 197–220.

  • Allen, K. (2010). Locating the unique hues. Rivista di Estetica 43, 13–28.

  • Allen, K. (2011). Revelation and the nature of colour. dialectica 65(2), 153–176.

  • Berkeley, G. (1713/1734). Three dialogues between Hylas and Philonous. In M. Ayers (ed) Philosophical works. London: Everyman.

  • Boghossian, P., & Velleman, D. (1991). Physicalist theories of colour. Philosophical Review, 100, 67–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brewer, B. (2011). Perception and its objects. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A. (2003). Color and similarity. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 66(3), 641–665.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A., & Hilbert, D. (1997). Colors and reflectances. In A. Byrne & D. Hilbert (Eds.), Readings on color: The philosophy of color (pp. 263–288). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A., & Hilbert, D. (2003). Color realism and color science. Behavioural and Brain Sciences, 26, 3–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A., & Hilbert, D. (2007). Color primitivism. Erkenntnis, 66, 73–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. (1993). A simple view of colour. In J. Haldane & C. Wright (Eds.), Reality, representation, and projection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chirimuuta, M. (2011). Touchy-feely colour. In C. P. Biggam, C. A. Hough, & D. R. Simmons (Eds.), New directions in colour studies. John Benjamins: Amsterdam and Philadelphia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. (2007). On the reality (and diversity) of objective colors: How color-qualia space is a map of reflectance-profile space. Philosophy of Science, 74, 119–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J. (2003). On the structural properties of the colors. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 81(1), 78–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J. (2009). The red and the real. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davies, W. (2014). The inscrutability of colour similarity. Philosophical Studies, 171(2), 289–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Valois, R. L., & De Valois, K. K. (1993). A multi-stage color model. Vision Research, 33(8), 1053–1065.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Degenaar, J., & Myin, E. (2014). The structure of color experience and the existence of surface colors. Philosophical Psychology, 27(3), 384–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dorsch, F. (2010). Colour realism and colour resemblance. Rivista di Estetica, 43, 85–108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1982). Varieties of reference. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (1994). Essence and modality. Philosophical Perspectives, 8, 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuld, K., Werner, J., & Wooten, B. (1983). The possible elemental nature of brown. Vision Research, 23, 631–637.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hård, A., Sivik, L., & Tonnquist, G. (1996). NCS, Natural Color System—From concept to research and applications, parts 1 and 2. Color Research and Application, 21, 180–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hardin, C. L. (1993). Color for philosophers. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hering, E. (1920). Outlines of a theory of the light sense (L. M. Hurvich, & D. Jameson, Trans.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Hilbert, D. (1987). Color and color perception. Stanford: Center for the Study of Language and Information.

  • Hume, D. (1739–1740). A treatise of human nature. In D. F. Norton & M. J. Norton (Eds.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Indow, T. (1988). Multidimensional studies of Munsell solid. Psychological Review, 95(4), 456–470.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1996). The primary quality view of color. Philosophical Perspectives, 10, 199–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jameson, K., & D’Andrade, R. G. (1997). Its not really red, green, yellow, blue: An inquiry into perceptual color space. In C. L. Hardin & L. Maffi (Eds.), Color categories in thought and language (pp. 295–319). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, M. (1992). How to speak of the colors. Philosophical Studies, 68, 221–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jraissati, Y. (2014). Proving universalism wrong does not prove relativism right: Considerations on the ongoing color categorization debate. Philosophical Psychology, 27(3), 401–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kalderon, M. (2011). The multiply qualitative. Mind, 120, 239–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koenderink, J. (2010). Color for the sciences. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuehni, R. (2005). Focal color variability and unique hue stimulus variability. Journal of Cognition and Culture, 5(387), 407.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1997). Naming the colors. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 75(3), 325–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1975). An essay concerning human understanding. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, M. (2005). Seeing, doing, and knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Maund, B. (1995). Colours: Their nature and representation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, B. (2003). Color, consciousness, and color consciousness. In Q. Smith & A. Jokic (Eds.), Consciousness: New philosophical perspectives (pp. 97–154). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mizrahi, V. (2009). Is colour composition phenomenal? In D. Skusevich & P. Matikas (Eds.), Color perception: Physiology, processes and analysis (pp. 185–202). New York: Nova Science Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pautz, A. (2006). Can the physicalist explain colour structure in terms of colour experience? Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 84(4), 535–564.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, P., Andow, J., & Schmidtke, K. (2014). Colour relationalism and the real deliverances of introspection. Erkenntnis, 79(5), 1173–1189

  • Saunders, B., & van Brakel, J. (1997). Are there non-trivial constraints on color categorisation? Behavioural and Brain Sciences, 20, 167–232.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroer, R. (2010). Where’s the beef? Phenomenal concepts as both demonstrative and substantial. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 88(3), 505–522.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shamey, R., Sedito, M., & Kuehni, R. (2010). Comparison of unique hue stimuli determined by two different methods using Munsell color chips. Color Research and Application, 35(6), 419–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shamey, R., Shepherd, S., Abed, M., Chargualaf, M., Garner, N., Dippel, N., et al. (2011). How well are color components of samples of the Natural Color System estimated? Journal of the Optical Society of America A, 28(10), 1962–1969.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (2003). Content, character, and color. Philosophical Issues, 13, 253–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sivik, L. (1997). Color systems for cognitive research. In C. L. Hardin & L. Maffi (Eds.), Color categories in thought and language (pp. 163–193). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Stroud, B. (2000). The quest for reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sundström, P. (2013). Are colours visually complex? In C. Svennerlind, J. Almäng, & R. Ingthorsson (Eds.), Johanssonian investigations: Essays in honour of Ingvar Johansson on his seventieth birthday (pp. 627–639). Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (1995). Colour vision: A study in cognitive science and the philosophy of perception. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2000). Consciousness, color, and content. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watkins, M. (2010). A posteriori primitivism. Philosophical Studies, 150(1), 123–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (1995). Singling out properties. Philosophical Perspectives, 9, 477–502.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Mazviita Chirimuuta and an anonymous referee for Minds and Machines for extremely helpful comments. Earlier versions of this material were presented at Durham and York's Mind and Reason group. Thanks to everyone for their comments and questions on these occasions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Keith Allen.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Allen, K. Colour Physicalism, Naïve Realism, and the Argument from Structure. Minds & Machines 25, 193–212 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-014-9353-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-014-9353-7

Keywords

Navigation