Skip to main content
Log in

Superdupersizing the mind: extended cognition and the persistence of cognitive bloat

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The hypothesis of extended cognition (EC) contends that parts of the world outside of the head partly comprise the vehicles of representation and mind. I consider and reject recent efforts to defend EC from the problem of “cognitive bloat.”

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. As noted by Rupert (2004), EC should be assessed as the claim that some mental vehicles are realized by extended states in the actual world, since even many critics of EC will agree that extended mental vehicles are metaphysically possible, such as Searle’s (1980) Chinese Room.

  2. Rupert (2004) points out that EC is logically independent of semantic externalism (the view that mental contents depend on “wide” factors). A rough summary of his reasoning is this: duplicate vehicles, narrowly individuated, might differ in their semantic content (given thought experiments about Twin-Earth) so semantic externalism does not entail vehicle externalism. Alternatively, duplicate vehicles, individuated widely (e.g. doppelgangers with duplicate notebooks) could have identical semantic contents, despite differences in their respective environments (e.g. suppose for each party “water” means “colorless, odorless, liquid, etc.…” regardless of whether it is H2O or XYZ that fills the local lakes and rivers).

  3. Giere (2006, p. 318) takes it as a reductio of EC that it implies telescopes are parts of cognitive systems. Rowlands (2009, p. 15) concedes that the telescope would be part of the astronomer’s perceptual processes save for the fact that it is not integrated within consciousness.

  4. For instance, Broad (1925, p. 376).

  5. Adams and Aizawa (2001, 2005, 2009) and Rupert (2004) have drawn attention to EC’s limitations when it comes to causal explanatory kinds.

  6. Rupert (2004, p. 424, no. 58) raises the issue of panpsychism in his discussion of Donald’s (1991) theorizing about extended memory.

  7. This is an application of Clark and Chalmers’ (1998) Parity Principle:

    If, as we confront some task, a part of the world functions as a process which, were it to go on in the head, we would have no hesitation in accepting as part of the cognitive process, then that part of the world is (for that time) part of the cognitive process (Clark and Chalmers 1998, p. 644).

    The Parity Principle immediately invites worries about bloat, as does Clark and Chalmers’ attempted distinction between extended processes, which are genuinely “epistemic,” versus “pragmatic” actions, which merely bring about some desired change in the world (Clark and Chalmers 1998, p. 644, Clark 2008, p. 211).

  8. As in imagining a notebook is magically shrunk and integrated in Otto’s nervous system playing a memory-like role.

  9. See Dretske (1995, pp.149–150). for a dissenting opinion, and more recently, Millikan (2010, pp. 76–79), though she ignores the issue of consciousness.

  10. Adams and Aizawa (2001, p. 68, 2009, p. 80) suggest that in addition to fitting a cognitive model, a genuine vehicle must also have non-derived content. In any case, although they think there are brain specific psychological and psychophysical laws (2001, 2005, 2009, p. 87) they doubt there are intercranial laws awaiting discovery.

  11. Hence, Fodor could at one time hold that a belief about XYZ on Twin-Earth is still a belief about water, though this view is later abandoned (see Fodor 1995).

  12. Methodological Individualism, despite its name, does not automatically assume that mental states are in the head, since their causal powers might depend on wide states. It is not to be confused with Methodological Solipsism, which is incompatible with Semantic Externalism.

  13. Could some of the objections to TEC be answered by switching to a non-historical account of proper function, or, perhaps, non-genetic selection processes (involving neuron populations, memes, or whatever) as a way to individuate genuine content-carrying cognitive vehicles? I have my doubts. The first suggestion will encounter problems when it comes to some of the previously discussed counterexamples, while the second continues to advance a historical criterion that is irrelevant for the purposes of causal explanation.

References

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2001). The bounds of cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 14(1), 43–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2005). Defending nonderived content. Philosophical Psychology, 18, 661–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2008). The bounds of cognition. Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2009). Why the mind is still in the head. In P. Robbins & M. Aydede (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook on situated cognition (pp. 78–95). Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Akmajian, A. (2001). Linguistics: An introduction to language and communication. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ayers, M. (1981). Locke versus Aristotle on natural kinds. The Journal of Philosophy, 78(5), 247–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broad, C. D. (1925). The mind and its place in nature. London: Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A. (2007). Asking what’s inside the head: Neurophilosophy meets the extended mind. Minds and Machines, 17(3), 345–351.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M., & Churchland, P. S. (1983). Stalking the wild epistemic engine. In W. Lycan (Ed.), Mind and cognition: A reader, 1990 (pp. 300–311). Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2005). Memento’s revenge: The extended mind, extended. In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind: The very idea (pp. 18–44). Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2007). Curing Cognitive Hiccups: A defense of the extended mind. Journal of Philosophy, 104(4), 163–192.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58, 643–651.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1987). Knowing one’s own mind. In Subjective, intersubjective, objective, 2001 (pp. 15–38). New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Dawkins, R. (2004). Extended phenotype—But not too extended. A reply to Laland, Turner and Jablonka. Biology and Philosophy, 19(3), 377–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donald, M. (1991). Origins of the modern mind: Three stages in the evolution of culture and cognition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1995). Naturalizing the mind. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (2002). Is ‘Natural Kind’ a natural kind term? The Monist, 85(1), 29–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1987). Psychosemantics. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1995). The Elm and the expert. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (2006). The role of agency in distributed cognitive systems. Philosophy of Science, 73(5), 710–719.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heil, J., & Mele, A. (1993). Mental content. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khalidi, M. A. (1998). Natural kinds and crosscutting categories. The Journal of Philosophy, 95(1), 33–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (1984). Language, thought, and other biological categories: New foundations for realism. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (1993). White queen psychology and other essays for Alice. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (2010). On knowing the meaning; With a coda on Swampman. Mind, 119(473), 43–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orwell, G. (1946/2005). Politics and the English language. In Why I write. New York: Penguin, pp. 102–120.

  • Rowlands, M. (2009). Extended cognition and the mark of the mental. Philosophical Psychology, 22(1), 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rupert, R. (2004). Challenges to the hypothesis of extended cognition. Journal of Philosophy, 101(8), 389–428.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seager, W. (1999). Theories of consciousness: An introduction and assessment. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1980). Minds, brains, and programs. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3, 417–457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. A. (1969). The sciences of the artificial. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1998). Philosophy of biology (2nd ed.). Boulder, CO: Westview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, L. (1973). Functions. Philosophical Review, 82(2), 139–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The author is grateful for discussions of this paper’s ancestors with Murray Clarke, Brian J. Garrett, Robert Rupert, audiences at the American Philosophical Association, McMaster University, Concordia University, and the Society for Philosophy and Psychology. I also received thoughtful criticisms from Benjamin Baez and the anonymous referees at Philosophical Studies.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sean Allen-Hermanson.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Allen-Hermanson, S. Superdupersizing the mind: extended cognition and the persistence of cognitive bloat. Philos Stud 164, 791–806 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-9914-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-9914-7

Keywords

Navigation