Skip to main content
Log in

An Argument for Shape Internalism

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper is a defense of an internalist view of the perception of shapes. A basic assumption of the paper is that perceptual experiences have certain parts which account both for the phenomenal character associated with perceiving shapes—phenomenal shapes—and for the intentional content presenting shapes—intentional shapes. Internalism about perceptions of shapes is defined as the claim that phenomenal shapes determine the intentional shapes. Externalism is defined as the claim that perceptual experiences represent whatever shape the phenomenal shape reliably tracks. The argument against externalism proceeds in three steps. First, it is argued that phenomenal shapes are modality specific, such that a phenomenal shape that features in a visual perceptual experience cannot feature in a haptic perceptual experience, and vice versa. Second, it is argued that intentional shapes are amodal. Third, it is argued that externalism is incompatible with the fact that phenomenal shapes are modality specific and intentional shapes amodal.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I should note from the beginning that I do not have the space to in this paper to discuss various positive attempts to construe twin earth experiments where identical experiences represent different shapes (cf Hurley 1998; Thompson 2010). Refuting the conclusions of these attempts requires an entirely different paper with a long detour through the metaphysics of space.

  2. This objection was suggested by a referee.

  3. An opponent could possibly retort that phenomenal shapes depend on either phenomenal colours or phenomenal solidity. Such a move would however be completely ad hoc and would introduce a very problematic notion of disjunctive dependence.

  4. It might be thought that the present topic relates to Molyneux’s question, namely the question whether a person who was born blind could immediately recognize by sight shapes previously only encountered by touch if he was granted sight. Several studies indicate that this would not be the case. Yet this does not refute Amodality. As has been pointed out by Smith, the neural structures subserving vision are normally damaged when someone’s visual senses are not stimulated for a prolonged period. So the capacity that these subjects have when they are granted sight is presumably an impaired capacity. (Smith 2000: 496f) As a result, studies pertaining to capacities of Molyneux’s subjects presumably do not refute Amodality.

  5. Campbell actually used two criteria, but the second does not seem applicable in this context.

  6. The famous experiments by Meltzoff and Moore are also relevant to the present case. Meltzoff and Moore (1983) found that neonates as young as 42 min old were able to imitate facial expressions. Strictly speaking, this is not a case of visual-haptic identification, however, it does indicate an innate capacity for intermodal recognition of shapes; though in this case it is more with respect to proprioception and vision than to touch and vision.

  7. I am here assuming that perceptual systems are informationally encapsulated in the sense that they are not sensitive to the beliefs and conceptual capacities of the perceiver. Thus, whereas perceptual content is normally available for cognition, the prior beliefs of the perceiver do not determine in any sense the content of the perceptual experience. Perceptual experiences are in this sense cognitively impenetrable. For a powerful defense of this claim, see Fodor (1983).

  8. It is to be noted that whereas Sharon and Twin Sharon may have identical phenomenal lives, they presumably may differ with respect to internal physical states. Since we have defined the controversy between externalism and internalism in terms of whether the phenomenal character of the perceptual experience (rather than internal physical state) determines the intentional content of the experience, this difference is of no importance in this context.

  9. The exact nature of the relationship between the phenomenal shape and the intentional shape is not something that we need to consider further in this paper. Clearly, several options are available to the internalist. The internalist may for example argue that phenomenal facts ground intentional facts. Or the internalist may argue that phenomenal shapes and intentional shapes are different properties of the perceptual experience which are related to each other in specific ways.

  10. Thanks are due to Kristoffer Sundberg and two anonymous referees for many valuable comments on a previous draft. Genie Perdin helped correct my English in a previous draft. I bear sole responsibility for any errors in the final draft. The writing of this paper was funded by The Swedish Research Council (Research Grant 421-2011-1587).

References

  • Bayne, T. (2010). The unity of consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (1990). Inverted earth. Philosophical Perspectives, 4, 53–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (1986). Individualism and psychology. The Philosophical Review, 1986, 3–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (2010). Origins of objectivity. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. (1987). Is sense transparent? Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 88, 273–292.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2006). Perception and the fall from Eden. In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual experience (pp. 49–125). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (2003). The intentional structure of consciousness. In Q. Smith & A. Jokic (Eds.), Consciousness. New philosophical perspectives. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1985). Collected papers. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farkas, K. (2003). What is externalism? Philosophical Studies, 112, 187–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farkas, K. (2008). The subject’s point of view. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1983). The modularity of the mind. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1933). Adaptation, after-effect and contrast in the perception of curved lines. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 16, 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1990). The intrinsic quality of experience. Philosophical Perspectives, 4, 31–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heller, M. (1983). A haptic dominance in form perception with blurred vision. Perception, 12, 607–613.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S. (1998). Consciousness in action. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1901). Logische Untersuchungen. Zweiter Band. In U. Panzer (ed.), As repr. in Husserliana, vol. XIX/1 and XIX/2. The Hague: Nijhoff, 1975/1984.

  • Martin, M. (2004). The limits of self-awareness. Philosophical Studies, 120, 37–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff, A. N., & Borton, R. W. (1979). Intermodal matching by human neonates. Nature, 282, 403–404.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, K. (1983). Newborn infants imitate adult facial gestures. Child Development, 54, 702–709.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1973). Meaning and reference. The Journal of Philosophy, 70, 699–711.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rock, I., & Victor, J. (1964). Vision and touch. An experimentally created conflict between the two senses. Science, 143, 594–596.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. D. (2000). Space and sight. Mind, 109, 481–518.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. D. (2002). The problem of perception. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snowdon, P. (2005). The formulation of disjunctivism. A response to fish. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 105, 129–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Streri, A., & Gentaz, E. (2003). Cross-modal recognition of shape from hand to eyes in human newborns. Somatosensory and Motor Research, 20, 13–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, B. (2010). The spatial content of experience. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81, 146–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2002). Representationalism and the transparency of experience. Noûs, 36, 137–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Welch, R. B., & Warren, D. H. (1980). Immediate perceptual response to intersensory discrepancy. Psychological Bulletin, 88, 638–667.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jan Almäng.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Almäng, J. An Argument for Shape Internalism. Erkenn 82, 819–836 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-016-9845-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-016-9845-3

Keywords

Navigation