Skip to main content

No Excuses: Performance Mistakes in Morality

  • Reference work entry
  • First Online:
Handbook of Neuroethics

Abstract

Philosophical accounts of moral responsibility are standardly framed by two platitudes. According to them, blame requires the presence of a moral defect in the agent and the absence of excuses. In this chapter, this kind of approach is challenged. It is argued that (a) people sometimes violate moral norms due to performance mistakes, (b) it often appears reasonable to hold them responsible for it, and (c) their mistakes cannot be traced to their moral qualities or to the presence of excuses. In the end, the implications for discussions of moral responsibility are discussed.

Associated Press report Posted: 01/25/2013 08:18:46 AM MSTCOLONIE, N.Y. (AP) – Authorities say a New York man who left his 1-year-old son in his car for eight hours in frigid weather only realized his mistake after a call from his wife. Police in the Albany suburb of Colonie say the man forgot to drop off his son at day care and left the child strapped in the backseat of the car when he parked outside his office Thursday morning.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 999.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 999.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The positive condition takes a variety of forms: Humeans require bad character (Brandt 1958; Nozick 1981), Kantians require a deficient will, (Wolff 1990; Wallace 1994), and followers of Frankfurt require motivations with origins in the “real self” (Scanlon 1998; Smith 2005). For an account of the condition that is meant to be neutral between the moral psychological pictures underlying these views, see McKenna (2012).

  2. 2.

    If anything, the second platitude is even more of a platitude than the first. For examples, refer to the references given in parenthesis (Austin 1962; Wallace 1994; Baron 2007; Franklin 2011; McKenna 2012) The standard excuses are sometimes referred to as “Aristotelian conditions,” after Aristotle’s discussion in Nichomachean Ethics III.

  3. 3.

    Hence, Chomsky proposed a division of labor between theories of competence in linguistics and theories of performance (1965, pp. 3–4; 1964, pp. 9–10).

  4. 4.

    See Vargas (2013a) for an in-depth treatment of moral responsibility from this Strawsonian perspective. Not everyone agrees with this general approach. There are, for instance, retributivist accounts that define responsibility for wrongdoing in terms of deserved suffering (Strawson 2000; Levy 2011). As it will become clear below, we contend that there are several notions in the “responsibility neighborhood,” not all of which are essentially linked to punishment or reward.

  5. 5.

    Examples of this trend can be found in the references given in parenthesis (Adams 1985; Scanlon 1998; Smith 2005). An exception is Sher (2006).

  6. 6.

    It might be objected that the attitudes that are fitting in these cases are similar, but not identical, with the reactive attitudes associated with responsibility and blame. For instance, one could argue that the fitting response in the case of child neglect is not genuine guilt but, instead, what Williams (1976) has called “agent-regret.” There are complicated issues concerning the individuation of these attitudes and their relation to moral blame, which are beyond the present discussion. But if, as Williams intends, agent-regret is understood as a form of evaluation that is distinctively retrospective, agent-regret is not the attitude that fits this kind of case. At the time the parent had enough information to see that his behavior was inappropriate; in the light of it, what he did was obviously wrong. The case is, thus, unlike the examples discussed by Williams (e.g. Gaugin, the lorry driver), where the agent’s decisions are regrettable or not precisely in the light of information that the agent does not have at the time, namely, information concerning their outcome. For discussion of the retrospective nature of agent-regret, refer to the references given in parenthesis (Williams 1976: esp. 126–128; Rosebury 1995, pp. 505–506).

  7. 7.

    There are, of course, ways in which a moral defect can be implicated but not in the way required for responsibility and blame: if one inadvertently leaves one’s child in the car on the way to do some evil work at the office. The idea that responsibility requires exercising certain rational competences is meant to exclude, in part, this kind of cases by defining what the right (i.e., non-fortuitous) relation is between wrongdoing and a moral defect. It can most perspicuously be found in so-called Reason-accounts of Kantian inspiration (Wolff 1990; Nelkin 2011). But it is also present in Frankfurtians, for whom the motivations of a real self are those whose influence in behavior the agent rationally endorses, and in Humeans, for whom the character traits implicated in responsible conduct are those that provide the agent with reasons.

  8. 8.

    For an insightful review of the account in Fischer and Ravizza, see McKenna (2001). Among others, McKenna discusses the asymmetry between receptivity and reactivity that we discuss below, concluding that Fischer and Ravizza’s requirement of weak reactivity is too weak. Here, we set aside these worries, as a strengthening of the requirement will only make our argument more straightforward.

  9. 9.

    More precisely, Fischer and Ravizza require that the agent exercise a suitable degree of reasons-recognition, which obtains, on their view, whenever the action is brought about by a certain kind of mechanism in the agent. Thus, their account not only requires that the agent has the capacity to respond to reasons but also that such capacity be displayed to a certain degree (or “be operative” as they sometimes put it) in the workings of certain mechanisms. For an explicit statement of the view, refer to the references given in parenthesis (Fischer and Ravizza 1998, p. 53; Fischer 2006, p. 242).

  10. 10.

    For reviews and discussion of the situationist evidence, refer to the references given in parenthesis (Ross and Nisbett 1991; Doris 2002; Miller 2003; Nahmias 2007; Merrit et al. 2010; Miller 2013; Alfano and Fairweather 2013). Elsewhere, one of us has systematically explored how this evidence raises generalized skepticism in relation to traditional notions of character and agency (Doris 2002, 2009, 2014). For discussion of how situationist evidence affects traditional accounts of responsibility, refer to the references given in parenthesis (Nelkin 2005; Vargas 2013b; Brink 2013).

  11. 11.

    (Mathews and Canon 1975, pp. 575–576). Refer to the references given in parenthesis for review of other studies (Cohen and Spacapan 1984, pp. 222–226).

  12. 12.

    For discussion of the extent to which situational factors, in general, can actually impede pro-social behavior, refer to the references given in parenthesis (Doris 2002, pp. 128–153; Nelkin 2005, pp. 193–194; Vargas 2013; Brink 2013).

  13. 13.

    For data of noise level in NYC transportation system, refer to the references given in parenthesis (Neizel et al. 2009). Díaz and Pedrero (2006) measured sound exposure in different locations in Madrid, several of which presented averaged continuous sound levels over 85db: nightclub, soccer pitch, musical theater, primary school (exit door), and carwash.

  14. 14.

    Sher (2009) discusses a hypothetical case, “hot dog,” that looks like the performance mistake exemplified by these hyperthermia cases. However, as he constructs his example (and other cases he discusses), the mistake is meant to illustrate a different kind of failure—one in which the mistake reflects psychological states constitutive of the agent’s individual character. Even if Sher’s interpretation of his hypothetical case is accepted, it is not clear that it applies generally to the real cases discussed here.

  15. 15.

    For a discussion of possible pitfalls in diary studies and self-reports of slips, refer to the references given in parenthesis (Morris 1984; Reason 1993). For a review of more recent studies and discussion of Reason’s original results, refer to the references given in parenthesis (Sellen 1990; Jónsdóttir et al. 2007).

  16. 16.

    In fact, even though in the US system, judges are generally moved by the parents suffering to give lenient sentences, there are a significant number of cases in which parents receive extremely harsh punishments: 15 years to life prison sentences or spending one day in jail on the child’s birthday for 7 years. For an empirical study of the treatment of hyperthermia cases in the US judicial system from 1998 to 2003, see Collins (2006).

  17. 17.

    Unfortunately, in some cases, the slip does result in the person having a false belief. Having spent all day at work, some parents drive to the day care in the afternoon to pick up their child, not having realized their slip. But as an explanation of how the mistake first came about, attributing the false belief clearly gets the order of things wrong.

  18. 18.

    Here we refer to the kind of luck that is normally described as resultant luck (Nagel 1979; Nelkin 2013). Some philosophical accounts of luck, formulated in terms of chanciness, might seem applicable here: Roughly, a chancy event is one that fails to occur in a large enough number of possible worlds obtainable by making a small change in the actual world (Pritchard 2005; Coffman 2007, p. 390). Even assuming the correctness of this kind of approach to common instances of luck (see Lackey 2008 for discussion), it is questionable whether chanciness thus understood excuses. An agent might introduce small changes in counterfactual scenarios and that may very well mean the difference between the agent being or not being blameworthy. The parent, for instance, could put his briefcase in the backseat, which will “remind” him that his child is still in the car before anything happens to her. Of course, things might be different in relation to other kinds or accounts of luck. Levy (2011), for instance, argues that it is a matter of (constitutive) luck whether and what kind of moral considerations cross your mind at the time of any action. But notice that he advances this claim to defend his general skepticism about human beings ever being responsible.

  19. 19.

    For a pluralistic approach to moral responsibility, refer to the references given in parenthesis (Doris et al 2007; Doris 2014).

  20. 20.

    We would like to thank Neil Levy and Michael McKenna for insightful comments, as well as audiences at the University of Lund, University of Texas, El Paso, and the Berlin School of Mind and Brain for helpful criticisms and suggestions.

References

  • Adams, R. (1985). Involuntary sins. Philosophical Review, 94, 3–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alfano, M., & Fairweather, A. (2013). Situationism and virtue theory. Oxford Bibliographies in Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Amaya, S. (2013). Slips. Noûs, 47(3), 559–576.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amaya, S. (in preparation). Without belief. Manuscript in preparation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. L. (1962). A plea for excuses. In J. O. Urmson & G. J. Warnock (Eds.), Austin, philosophical papers (3rd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baron, M. (2007). Excuses, excuses. Criminal Law and Philosophy, 1, 21–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baumeister, R. (1984). Choking under pressure: selfconsciousness and paradoxical effects of incentiveson skillful performance. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 46, pp. 610–620.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beilock, S. (2007). Choking under pressure. In R. Baumesiter & K. Vohs. (Eds.), Encyclopedia of Social Psychology, Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications, pp. 140–141.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brand, R. (1958). Blameworthiness and obligation. In A. I. Melden (Ed.), Essays in moral philosophy (pp. 3–39). Seattle: University of Washington Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brink. D. (2013). Situationism, responsibility, and fair opportunity. Social Philosophy and Policy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broadbent, D. E. (1958). Perception and communication. New York: Pergamon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Broadbent, D. E., Broadbent, M., & Jones, L. (1986). Correlates of cognitive failure. British Journal of Clinical Psychology, 21, 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cherry, E. C. (1953). Some experiments on the recognition of speech, with one and with two ears. Journal of the Acoustical Society of America, 25, 975–979.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1959). Review of B.F. Skinner’s verbal behavior. Language, 35(l), 26–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1964). Current issues in linguistic theory. The Hague: Mouton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1965). Aspects of the theory of syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coffman, E. J. (2007). Thinking about luck. Synthese, 158, 385–398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (1978). Environmental load and the allocation of attention. In A. Baum, J. Singer, & S. Vain (Eds.), Advances in environmental psychology. Hillsdale: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S., & Spacapan, S. (1984). The social psychology of noise. In D. M. Jones & A. J. Chapman (Eds.), Noise and society (pp. 221–245). New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, J. (2006). Crime and parenthood: The uneasy case of prosecuting negligent parents. Northwestern University School of Law, 100, 807–856.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darley, J. M., & Batson, C. D. (1973). From Jerusalem to Jericho: A study of situational and dispositional variables in helping behavior. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 27, 100–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Díaz, C., & Pedrero, A. (2006). Sound exposure during daily activities. Applied Acoustics, 67, 271–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doris, J. M. (2002). Lack of character: Personality and moral behavior. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Doris, J. M. (2005). Replies: Evidence and sensibility. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 71, 656–677.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doris, J. M. (2009). Skepticism about persons. Philosophical Issues, 19, 57–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doris, J. M. (2014). Talking to ourselves. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doris, J. M., Knobe, J., & Woolfolk, R. (2007). Variantism about responsibility. Philosophical Perspectives, 27, 183–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doris, J. M., & Murphy, D. (2007). From my lai to Abu Grahib: the moral psychology of atrocity. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 31(1), 25–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, H. (2006). My way: Essays on moral responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J., & Ravizza, M. (1998). Responsibility and control. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Franklin, C. (2011). A theory of the normative force of pleas. Philosophical Studies. doi:10.1007/s11098-011-9826-y.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1999). Moral philosophy and linguistics. In K. Brinkman (Ed.), Proceedings of the 20th world congress of philosophy (pp. 107–115). Bowling Green: Philosophy Documentation Center.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jónsdóttir, M., Adólfsdóttir, S., Cortez, R. D., Gunnarsdóttir, M., & Gústafsdóttir, H. (2007). A diary study of action slips in healthy individuals. The Clinical Neuropsychologist, 21, 875–883.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lackey, J. (2008). What luck is not. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 86, 255–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lashley, K. (1951). The problem of serial order in behavior. In L. Jeffress (Ed.), Cerebral mechanisms in behavior. The Hixon symposium (pp. 112–136). New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latané, B., & Darley, J. (1970). The Unresponsive bystander: Why doesn’t he help? New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latané, B., & Rodin, J. (1969). A lady in distress: Inhibiting effects of friends and strangers on bystander information. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 5, 189–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, N. (2011). Hard luck: How luck undermines free will and responsibility. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mallon, R. (2008). Reviving Rawls’s linguistic analogy inside and out. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology (Vol. 2, pp. 145–156). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, K., & Cannon, L. (1975). Environmental noise level as a determinant of helping behavior. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 32, 571–577.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. (2001). Review of “Responsibility and control: A theory of moral responsibility”. Journal of Philosophy, 98, 93–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. (2012). Conversation and responsibility. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McLaren, C., Null, J., & Quinn, J. (2005). Heat stress from enclosed vehicles: Moderate ambient temperatures cause significant temperature rise in enclosed vehicles. Pediatrics, 116, e109–e112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merrit, M., Doris, J. M., & Harman, G. (2010). Character. In J. M. Doris & The Moral Psychology Groups (Eds.), Moral psychology handbook (pp. 354–400). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mikhail, J. (2010). Elements of moral cognition: Rawls’ linguistic analogy and the cognitive science of moral and legal judgment. Cambridge: Cambridge University press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, C. (2003). Social psychology and virtue ethics. The Journal of Ethics, 7, 365–392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, C. (2013). Moral character: An empirical theory. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moray, N. (1959). Attention in dichotic listening: Affective cues and the influence of instructions. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 11, 56–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morris, P. E. (1984). The validity of subjective reports. In J. Harris & P. Morris (Eds.), Everyday memory, actions, and absent-mindedness (pp. 173–190). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1976). Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 50, 137–151.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1986). The view from nowhere. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nahmias, E. (2007). Autonomous agency and social psychology. In M. Maraffa, M. De Caro, & F. Ferretti (Eds.), Cartographies of the mind (pp. 169–185). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Neizel, R., Gershon, R., Zeltser, M., Canton, A., & Akram, M. (2009). Noise levels associated with New York City’s mass transit systems. American Journal of Public Health, 99, 1393–1399.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelkin, D. (2005). Freedom, responsibility, and the challenge of situationism. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 29, 181–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelkin, D. (2011). Making sense of freedom and responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelkin, D. (2013). Moral luck. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.). Retrieved from The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2013 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2013/entries/moral-luck/

  • Norman, D. (1981). Categorization of action slips. Psychological Review, 88, 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical explorations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2005). Epistemic luck. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (2010). Being in the world. Ratio, 23, 433–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reason, J. (1984). Lapses of attention in everyday life. In R. Parasuraman & D. Davies (Eds.), Varieties of attention (pp. 515–549). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reason, J. (1988). Stress and cognitive failure. In S. Fisher & J. Reason (Eds.), Handbook of life stress, cognition, and health (pp. 405–421). New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reason, J. (1990). Human error. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reason, J. (1993). Self-report questionnaires in cognitive psychology: Have they delivered the goods? In A. Baddeley & L. Weiskrantz (Eds.), Attention: selection, awareness, and control (pp. 406–424). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reason, J., & Mycielska, K. (1982). Absent-mindedness? Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roedder, E., & Harman, G. (2010). Linguistics and moral theory. In J. M. Doris (Ed.), The moral psychology handbook (pp. 273–296). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rosebury, B. (1995). Moral responsibility and “moral luck”. The Philosophical Review, 104, 499–524.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, L., & Nisbett, R. E. (1991). The person and the situation: Perspectives of social psychology. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. (1998). What we owe to each other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellen, A. J. (1990). Mechanisms of human error and human error detection. Ph.D. thesis, University of California, San Diego.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sher, G. (2006). In praise of blame. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sher, G. (2009). Who knew? Responsibility without awareness. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, D. (2011). Attributability, answerability, and accountability: Toward a wider theory of moral responsibility. Ethics, 121, 602–632.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. (2005). Responsibility for attitudes: Activity and passivity in mental Life. Ethics, 115(2), 236–271.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1962/1982). Freedom and resentment. In G. Watson (Ed.), Free will. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (2000). The unhelpfulness of determinism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 60, 149–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vargas, M. (2013a). Building better beings: A theory of moral responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vargas, M. (2013b). Situationism and responsibility: Free will in fragments. In T. Vierkant, J. Kiverstein, & A. Clark (Eds.), Decomposing the will (pp. 400–416). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, R. J. (1994). Responsibility and the moral sentiments. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson, G. (1996). Two faces of responsibility. Philosophical Topics, 24, 227–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weingarten, G. (2009). Fatal distraction. The Washington Post, March 08, 2009. http://www.washingtonpost.com/wpdyn/content/article/2009/02/27/AR2009022701549.html. Retrieved 1 Feb 2010.

  • Williams, B. (1976). Moral Luck. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 50, 115–135.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolff, S. (1990). Freedom within reason. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood, N. L., & Cowan, N. (1995). The cocktail party phenomenon re- visited: Attention and memory in the classic selective listening procedure of Cherry (1953). Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, & Cognition, 21, 255–260.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Santiago Amaya .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this entry

Cite this entry

Amaya, S., Doris, J.M. (2015). No Excuses: Performance Mistakes in Morality. In: Clausen, J., Levy, N. (eds) Handbook of Neuroethics. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-4707-4_120

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-4707-4_120

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-007-4706-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-007-4707-4

  • eBook Packages: Humanities, Social Sciences and Law

Publish with us

Policies and ethics