Skip to main content

ON THE INEXTRICABILITY OF THE CONTEXT OF DISCOVERY AND THE CONTEXT OF JUSTIFICATION

  • Chapter
Revisiting Discovery and Justification

Part of the book series: Archimedes ((ARIM,volume 14))

Abstract

Before the historicist turn in philosophy of science, it was generally regarded that scientific activity takes place within two distinct contexts, the context of discovery and the context of justification. The former consists in the processes of generation of scientific hypotheses and theories; the latter in their testing and validation. According to Reichenbach, who codified the distinction, the context of discovery was the province of historians, psychologists, and sociologists and was not susceptible to logical analysis: “The act of discovery escapes logical analysis; there are no logical rules in terms of which a “discovery machine” could be constructed that would take over the creative function of the genius” (Reichenbach 1951, p. 231). On the other hand, the context of justification was an area which could be rigorously explored and formalized and thus fell within the province of logic and philosophy.2 Popper introduced a very similar distinction in The Logic of Scientific Discovery (Popper 1968, p. 31). His notion of discovery, however, was different from Reichenbach’s (see note 12).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

REFERENCES

  • Achinstein, P. (1980), “Discovery and Rule-Books,” in T. Nickles (ed.), Scientific Discovery, Logic, and Rationality (Dordrecht: Reidel), pp. 117–132.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arabatzis, T. (1992), “The Discovery of the Zeeman Effect: A Case Study of the Interplay between Theory and Experiment,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 23, 365–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arabatzis, T. (1996), “Rethinking the ‘Discovery’ of the Electron,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 27, 405–435.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arabatzis, T. (2001), “Can a Historian of Science be a Scientific Realist?” Philosophy of Science 68 (Proceedings), S531–S541.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arabatzis, T. (2006), Representing Electrons: A Biographical Approach to Theoretical Entities (Chicago: University of Chicago Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Brannigan, A. (1981), The Social Basis of Scientific Discoveries (New York: Cambridge University Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Burian, R. (1980), “Why Philosophers Should not Despair of Understanding Scientific Discovery,” in T. Nickles (ed.), Scientific Discovery, Logic, and Rationality (Dordrecht: Reidel), pp. 317–336.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caneva, K. L. (2001), The Form and Function of Scientific Discoveries, Dibner Library Lecture Series (Washington, DC: Smithsonian Institution Libraries).

    Google Scholar 

  • Conant, J. B. (1957), “The Overthrow of the Phlogiston Theory,” in J. B. Conant & L. K. Nash (eds.), Case Histories in Experimental Science (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Curd, M. V. (1980), “The Logic of Discovery: an Analysis of Three Approaches,” in T. Nickles (ed.), Scientific Discovery, Logic, and Rationality (Dordrecht: Reidel), pp. 201–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Falconer, I. (1987), “Corpuscles, Electrons and Cathode Rays: J. J. Thomson and the ‘Discovery of the Electron’,” British Journal for the History of Science 20, 241–276.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, A. (1986), The Shaky Game: Einstein Realism and the Quantum Theory (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Franklin, A. (1989), “The Epistemology of Experiment,” in D. Gooding et al. (eds.), The Uses of Experiment: Studies in the Natural Sciences (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 437–460.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gutting, G. (1980), “Science as Discovery,” Revue Internationale de Philosophie 131–132, 26–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1983), Representing and Intervening (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoyningen-Huene, P. (1987), “Context of Discovery and Context of Justification,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 18, 501–515.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1992), “The Naturalists Return,” The Philosophical Review 101, 53–114.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koertge, N. (1982), “Explaining Scientific Discovery,” in P. D. Asquith and T. Nickles (eds.), PSA 1982. Proceedings of the 1982 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association (East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association), Vol. 1,pp. 14–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kordig, C. R. (1978), “Discovery and Justification,” Philosophy of Science 45, 110–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1970), The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd ed. (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1977), The Essential Tension (Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Langley, P., H. A. Simon, G. L. Bradshaw, and J. M. Zytkow (1987), Scientific Discovery: Computational Explorations of the Creative Process (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1980), “Why Was the Logic of Discovery Abandoned?” in T. Nickles (ed.), Scientific Discovery, Logic, and Rationality (Dordrecht: Reidel), pp. 173–183.

    Google Scholar 

  • McMullin, E. (1980), Contribution to “(Panel Discussion) The Rational Explanation of Historical Discoveries,” in T. Nickles (ed.), Scientific Discovery: Case Studies (Dordrecht: Reidel), pp. 28–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian, N. J. (1992), “How Do Scientists Think? Capturing the Dynamics of Conceptual Change in Science,” in R. N. Giere (ed.), Cognitive Models of Science (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press), pp. 3–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian, N. J. (1993), “Opening the Black Box: Cognitive Science and History of Science,” Cognitive Science Laboratory Report 53 (Princeton University).

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (1980a), “Introductory Essay: Scientific Discovery and the Future of Philosophy of Science,” in T. Nickles (ed.), Scientific Discovery, Logic, and Rationality (Dordrecht: Reidel), pp. 1–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (1980b), “Can Scientific Constraints Be Violated Rationally?” in T. Nickles (ed.), Scientific Discovery, Logic, and Rationality (Dordrecht: Reidel), pp. 285–315.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (1984), “Positive Science and Discoverability,” in P. D. Asquith and P. Kitcher (eds.), PSA 1984. Proceedings of the 1984 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association (East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association), Vol. 1, pp. 13–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (1985), “Beyond Divorce: Current Status of the Discovery Debate,” Philosophy of Science 52, 177–206.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (1987), “Twixt Method and Madness,” in N. J. Nersessian (ed.), The Process of Science (Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff), pp. 41–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (1988), “Truth or Consequences? Generative Versus Consequential Justification in Science,” in A. Fine and J. Leplin (eds.), PSA 1988. Proceedings of the 1988 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association (East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association), Vol. 2, pp. 393–105.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (1989a), “Heuristic Appraisal: a proposal,” Social Epistemology 3, 175–188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (1989b), “Justification and Experiment,” in D. Gooding, T. Pinch, and S. Schaffer (eds.), The Uses of Experiment (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), pp. 299–333.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (1990), “Discovery,” in R. C. Olby et al. (eds.), Companion to the History of Modern Science (London and New York: Routledge), pp. 148–165.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1968), The Logic of Scientific Discovery (New York: Harper & Row).

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1991), “The ‘Corroboration’ of Theories,” in R. Boyd et al. (eds.), The Philosophy of Science (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), pp. 121–137.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1938), Experience and Prediction (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1951), The Rise of Scientific Philosophy (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1949), The Concept of Mind (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1949).

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, S. (1986), “Scientific Discoveries and the End of Natural Philosophy,” Social Studies of Science 16,387–420.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, C. (1999), The Science of Energy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Stachel, J. (1994), “Scientific Discoveries as Historical Artifacts,” in K. Gavroglu et al. (eds.), Trends in the Historiography of Science (Dordrecht: Kluwer), pp. 139–148.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1980), The Scientific Image (New York: Oxford University Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Zeeman, P. (1986), “On the Influence of Magnetism on the Nature of the Light Emitted by a Substance (Part I),” Communications from the Physical Laboratory at the University of Leiden 33, 1–8.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2006 Springer

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

ARABATZIS, T. (2006). ON THE INEXTRICABILITY OF THE CONTEXT OF DISCOVERY AND THE CONTEXT OF JUSTIFICATION. In: SCHICKORE, J., STEINLE, F. (eds) Revisiting Discovery and Justification. Archimedes, vol 14. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/1-4020-4251-5_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics