Skip to main content
Log in

Some Remarks on “Hearing-as” and its Role in the Aesthetics of Music

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Starting from the context in which Wittgenstein thinks of the concepts of “seeing-as” and “hearing-as”, the basic relation is clarified between the question of representation, musical understanding, and the theory of musical expressiveness. The points of views of Wollheim, Scruton, Levinson, and Ridley are discussed, in a re-consideration of the notions of hearing and understanding within Wittgenstein’s “last philosophy”.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Scruton (1998, pp. 174–187); Scruton (1997, Chapt. 2 and 8).

  2. Ridley (2004, pp. 47–69); Levinson (1995, pp. 90–125); Levinson (2006, pp. 91–108).

  3. Wittgenstein (1980b, § 1, p. 2).

  4. See also Wittgenstein (1997, II, XI, p. 212): “Do I really see something different each time, or do I only interpret what I see in a different way? I am inclined to say the former. But why?––To interpret is to think, to do something; seeing is a state”.

  5. Wittgenstein (1980a, b, § 1036, p. 180).

  6. Schæffer (1966, pp. 103–110).

  7. If we want to imagine a melody, we have to “sing it inwardly;” and this will be called an activity, according to Wittgenstein, “just as much as calculating in the head”; Wittgenstein (1980a, §81, p. 16).

  8. Schæffer (1966, p. 103) (my translation).

  9. In French this expression can be understood both in the sense of an intellectual act and of a perceptive synthesis. “Ouïr comme”––close to the German “hören wie,” the English “to hear as,” the Italian “udire come,” and the Spanish “oír como”––refers explicitly to perception but is less common. The French “sentir comme,” while interesting, rather designates the sentimental value of the experience (as in English “to feel” or in Spanish “sentir,” while the Italian “sentire” is more versatile and has inter alia the meaning of “to hear”).

  10. As stressed by Schæffer (1966, p. 104).

  11. See Vicario (2003, p. 134).

  12. Both the perceptual and the metaphysical side of this question have been discussed at considerable length by Scruton (1997, pp. 6–13).

  13. See Bozzi (1993, pp. 71–74).

  14. Among the most celebrated works, we can mention those of Stockhausen, Scelsi and the composers of L’Itinéraire.

  15. See Scruton (1997, pp. 13–15).

  16. Casati and Dokic (1994, p. 5).

  17. See Fontaine (2001, p. 159).

  18. See the thesis about the articulation in a musical sentence sketched in Wittgenstein (1961, § 3.141).

  19. Scruton (1998, p. 99).

  20. Wittgenstein (1980a, b, § 1036, p. 180).

  21. Scruton (1998, pp. 94–97).

  22. Scruton (1998, p. 101).

  23. Scruton (1998, p. 178).

  24. Scruton (1998, pp. 177–178).

  25. Scruton (1998, p. 90).

  26. Scruton (1997, p. 44).

  27. Cumming (1994, p. 18).

  28. Among the most pertinent observations are those of Budd (1999) and Cumming (1994). According to Budd, the idea of applying a capacity of metaphorical transfer is not only unnecessary, but exposes speech to a contradiction: for all metaphor requires interpretation, which takes the form of a “injection” (and not of an “extraction”) of meanings––yet Scruton’s thesis seems precisely to show the superfluous nature of such an interpretation. Cumming, for her part, has highlighted that the distinction between a specific “intentional” nature of the musical object and the “material” nature of objects of scientific knowledge advanced by Scruton involves basically a positivist conception of the metaphor, unsatisfactory when considering carefully the status of descriptions of physical objects.

  29. According to Cumming’s criticism (1994, p. 9 and p. 11).

  30. Cumming (1994, p. 12).

  31. Cumming (1994, pp. 22–23).

  32. It is in a similar way that Nicholas Cook (1990), suggests conceiving the meaning of music’s theories and analytical projects.

  33. We sketched this topic in Arbo (2007).

  34. These metaphors are widely employed in order to describe musical sounds in the writings of Hugues Dufourt (1991), Gérard Grisey (2008) and Tristan Murail (2005).

  35. See Cometti et al. (Cometti et al. 2000, p. 78).

  36. Levinson (2006, p. 95).

  37. More precisely (and, in our opinion, convincingly), Levinson makes a reply to three remarks made by Wollheim in order to support his view of “seeing-in.” About the observation that “see-in” would lend itself better to illustrate states of affairs than the “seeing-as,” he said that in the case of music, we already hear processes or events normally. About the objection that “seeing-as” does not apply to a whole picture but only to a part of it, he says that we normally hear a whole passage of music as expressive of a certain emotion. The third (and widest) of Wollheim’s remarks concerns the fact that with the “seeing-in” we are conscious of both the means of representation and the represented objects. But Levinson observes that the conscience of this duality is not really necessary in the case of music: in short, there is no need to share our attention between, on the one hand, emerging and expressive properties, and, on the other one, the musical characters which create it. See Levinson (1995, pp. 110–112).

  38. Levinson (1995, p. 116).

  39. Levinson (1995, p. 117).

  40. More recent resemblance-based views of musical expressiveness are discussed in Levinson (2006, pp. 96–100).

  41. Ridley (2004, p. 65).

  42. Ridley (2004, p. 67).

  43. Wittgenstein (1980a, b, § 1036, p. 180).

  44. Wittgenstein (1982) discusses this question in §451, p. 60: “Seeing an aspect is a voluntary act. We can tell someone: Now look at it like this. Try again to see the similarity. Listen to the theme this way, etc. But does that make seeing a voluntary act? Isn’t it rather the way you look at something that causes this seeing?”.

  45. Levy (1995, pp. 156–160).

  46. Wittgenstein (1982, § 612, p. 78).

  47. Wittgenstein (1982, § 677, p. 86).

  48. Cf. Scruton (1997, p. 94; 1998, pp. 100–101).

  49. See Benoist (2006, p. 249).

  50. Wittgenstein (1997, p. 197).

  51. By this term we mean a particular system of (musical) relationships about which there was reached some agreement in a human context or relationship. A “music game” could correspond to what it is often called a “style,” but this concept should mainly serve to emphasize how important it is to take into account the factors of context when it comes to explaining the “meaning” of an identifiable musical fragment (whether an interval or a harmonic situation, a sentence, etc.).

References

  • Arbo A (2007) Ton ou son? Réfléchir sur la musique (d’)aujourd’hui. Dissonance/Dissonanz 97: 24–27

    Google Scholar 

  • Benoist J (2006) Voir comme quoi. In: Laugier S, et Chauviré C (eds) Lire les Recherches philosophiques de Wittgenstein. Vrin, Paris, pp 237–253

    Google Scholar 

  • Bozzi P (1993) Experimenta in visu. Ricerche sulla percezione. Guerini, Milano

    Google Scholar 

  • Budd M (1999) Understanding music. In: Kemal S, Gaskell I (eds) Performance and authenticity in the arts. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 114–128

    Google Scholar 

  • Casati R, Dokic J (1994) La philosophie du son. Éditions Jacqueline Chambon, Nîmes

    Google Scholar 

  • Cometti JP, Morizot J, Pouivet R (2000) Questions d’esthétique. P.U.F, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Cook N (1990) Music, imagination and culture. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Cumming N (1994) Metaphor in Roger Scruton’s aesthetics of music. In: Pople A (ed) Theory analysis and meaning in music. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 3–28

    Google Scholar 

  • Dufourt H (1991) Musique, pouvoir, écriture. Christian Bourgois, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Fontaine O (2001) Le “voir comme”, entre voir et penser? Remarques sur “l’espace grammatical” de la saisie d’aspects. In: Chauviré C, Laugier S, Rosat J-J (eds) Wittgenstein: les mots de l’esprit. Vrin, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Grisey G (2008) Écrits ou l’invention de la musique spectrale (eds: Lelong G, Réby AM). Éditions MF, Paris

  • Husserl E (1964) The phenomenology of internal time-consciousness (ed: Heidegger M, trans: Churchill JS). Indiana University Press, The Hague

  • Levinson J (1995) The pleasures of aesthetics. Philosophical essays. Cornell University Press, Ithaca and London

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson J (2006) Contemplating art. Essays in aesthetics. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy JM (1995) Beginning-ending ambiguity: consequences of performance choices. In: Rink John (ed) The practice of performance. Studies in musical interpretation. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 150–169

    Google Scholar 

  • Murail T (2005) Models & artifice. The collected writings of Tristan Murail. Fineberg J, Michel P (eds) Contemporary music review 24 (2–3) edn. Routledge, London

  • Ridley A (2004) The philosophy of music. Theme and variations. Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Schæffer P (1966) Traité des objets musicaux: essai interdisciplines. Seuil, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Scruton R (1974) Art and imagination. A study in the philosophy of mind. St. Augustin’s Press, South Bend/Indiana (Originally published: Methuen, London)

    Google Scholar 

  • Scruton R (1997) The aesthetics of music. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Scruton R (1998) The aesthetic understanding. Essays in the philosophy of art and culture. St. Augustine’s Press, South Bend, Indian (Originally published: Methuen, New York, 1983)

  • Vicario GB (2003) La nozione di durata in Husserl. Rivista di estetica 24(3):134–153

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein L (1961) Tractatus logico-philosophicus. (trans: Pears DF, McGuiness BF). Roultledge and Kegan Paul/Humanities Press, London/New York

  • Wittgenstein L (1980a) Bemerkungen über die Philosophie der Psychologie/Remarks on the Philosophy of Phychology, vol 1 (eds: Anscombe GEM, von Wright GH, trans: Anscombe GEH). Basil Blackwell, Oxford

  • Wittgenstein L (1980b) Bemerkungen über die Philosophie der Psychologie/Remarks on the philosophy of phychology, vol 2 (eds: von Wright GH, Nyman H, trans: Luckhardt CG, Aue MA). Basil Blackwell, Oxford

  • Wittgenstein L (1982) Letzte Schriften über die Philosophie der Psychologie/Last writings on the philosophy of psychology, vol 1 (eds: von Wright GH, Nyman H, trans: Luckhardt CG, Aue MA). Basil Blackwell, Oxford

  • Wittgenstein L (1997) Philosophische Untersuchungen. Zweite Auflage/Philosophical investigations, 2nd edn (trans: Anscombe GEM). Blackwell Publishers, Oxford (Originally published: Blackwell, Oxford, 1953 and 1958)

  • Wollheim R (1980) Art and its objects. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am very grateful to Amanda Hascher and Jerrold Levinson for their helpful comments in correcting and improving this article.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alessandro Arbo.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Arbo, A. Some Remarks on “Hearing-as” and its Role in the Aesthetics of Music. Topoi 28, 97–107 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-009-9053-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-009-9053-8

Keywords

Navigation