Skip to main content
Log in

Do desires provide reasons? An argument against the cognitivist strategy

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

According to the cognitivist strategy, the desire to bring about P provides reasons for intending to bring about P in a way analogous to how perceiving that P provides reasons for believing that P. However, while perceiving P provides reasons for believing P by representing P as true, desiring to bring about P provides reasons for intending to bring about P by representing P as good. This paper offers an argument against this view. My argument proceeds via an appeal to what I call the non-substitutability of perception, the thesis that, given that there is no independent evidence for P, one cannot substitute something that fails to provide reasons with respect to P for the perceptual experience that P, without altering the rational permissibility of believing that P. By contrast, I argue that it is always possible to substitute something that fails to provide reasons for a desire without altering the rational permissibility of an intention based on said desire. I take this to show that a desire does not provide reasons in a way analogous to perceptual experience.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Henceforth, whenever I talk of reasons I should be understood to mean justificatory reasons.

  2. The locus classicus of this type of approach is Davidson (1980). See and Cf.: Quinn (1994).

  3. Cognitivism, with respect to desires, is typically defined as the thesis that a desire represents its object as good. This need not entail the claim that desires provide reasons. For example, one may hold that a desire represents its object as good as a pretext for claiming that the good is the formal end of practical reasoning, without also being committed to the claim that desires provide reasons. [For an in-depth discussion and defence of a position along these lines, see Tenenbaum 2007).] In fact, the main arguments of this paper, though aimed at impugning the claim that desires provide reasons, are consistent with both the claim that desires represent their objects as good and the claim that the good is the formal end of practical reasoning. Nevertheless, cognitivism is commonly discussed in the context of the claim that desires provide reasons [see, for example, Velleman (1992)].

  4. Velleman (1992). See and Cf. Setiya (2007, 2010).

  5. For a recent discussion of “guise of the good” approaches, see Tenenbaum (2010).

  6. Velleman (1992: 6–7).

  7. See, for example, Johnston (2001: 189), Oddie (2005), Tenenbaum (2007), Hawkins (2008), and Schafer (2013).

  8. John McDowell (1998a) was an early defender of the notion of evaluative perceptions (of a specifically moral character). However, there has been a resurgence of interest in the possibility of evaluative perceptions in aesthetics, ethics, and normativity theory. Examples of theorists who discuss evaluative perceptions in the context of aesthetics include: Lopes (1996, 2005), Hopkins (1998), and Pettersson (2011). Examples of theorists who discuss evaluative perceptions in moral contexts include: Blum (1991), Fortenbaugh (1964), Harman (1977), Holland (1998), Jacobson (2006), McDowell (1998a, b), Nussbaum (2001), and Starkey (2006). This renewed interest in evaluative perception is in large part due to the emergence of the high-level view of the content of perception (e.g., Siegel (2006)) which has given credence to the idea that sophisticated forms of perception may be possible.

  9. While I do not wish to take a stand on whether it is possible to have such evaluative perceptions, it seems to me that the analogy from evaluative perception just adumbrated is the most plausible way of understanding the cognitivist strategy. To be clear, the present suggestion is not that desires are themselves perceptual experiences. Rather, the suggestion is that desires and perceptual experiences share something important, which they do not share with beliefs: namely, both desire and perception do not involve the kind of commitment that entails irrationality in cases of logically inconsistent contents.

  10. Hawkins (2008: 247).

  11. Velleman (1992: 7).

  12. Velleman (1992: 22, note 12).

  13. A similar view is defended by Price (1989) and Humberstone (1987).

  14. See, for example: Davidson (1980: 102).

  15. The suggestion that the desires of an agent equipped with the relevant concepts may play a justificatory role that the desires of an infant cannot is not as strange or novel as it may initially seem. It is widely held that the perceptual appearances of an agent equipped with the appropriate concepts may provide her with justification that could not be had by someone who lacked the concepts in question. For example, an agent who is equipped with the appropriate concepts may come to justifiably believe that there is a fire truck nearby after hearing a blaring siren even though an infant or animal (that lacked the appropriate concepts) could not come to have the same justified belief under similar circumstances. If there were a theory of perception that aimed to explain how the perceptual experiences of an agent equipped with the appropriate concepts could provide her with justification for adopting certain beliefs, it would be no objection to such an account to argue that it failed to apply to agents who lacked the ability to conceive of reasons as such. A similar argument may be advanced on behalf of the cognitivist strategy.

References

  • Blum, L. (1991). Moral perception and particularity. Ethics, 101, 701–725.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, R. (2006). Can desires provide reasons for action? In R. J. Wallace, P. Pettit, et al. (Eds.), Reason and value: Themes from the moral philosophy of Joseph Raz (pp. 56–90). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1980). Intending. In Essays on actions and events (pp. 83–102). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Fortenbaugh, W. (1964). Aristotle’s conception of moral virtue and its perceptive role. Transactions of the American Philological Association, 95, 77–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1977). The nature of morality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawkins, J. (2008). Desiring the bad under the guise of the good. The Philosophical Quarterly, 58(231), 244–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holland, M. (1998). Touching the weights: Moral perception and attention. International Philosophical Quarterly, 38, 299–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins, R. (1998). Picture, image, and experience: A philosophical inquiry. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Humberstone, L. (1987). Wanting as believing. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 17(1), 49–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacobson, D. (2006). Seeing by feeling: Virtues, skills, and moral perception. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 8(4), 387–409.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, M. (2001). The authority of affect. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 63(1), 181–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lopes, D. (1996). Understanding pictures. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lopes, D. (2005). Sight and sensibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1998a). Virtue and reason. In Mind, value, and reality (pp. 50–73). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (The original article was published in 1979 in The Monist, 62: 331–350.)

  • McDowell, J. (1998b). Values and secondary qualities. In Mind, value, and reality (pp. 131–150). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Nussbaum, M. (2001). Upheavals of thought. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Oddie, G. (2005). Value, reality, and desire. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pettersson, M. (2011). Seeing what is not there: Pictorial experience, imagination and non-localization. British Journal of Aesthetics, 51(3), 279–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Price, H. (1989). Defending desire-as-belief. Mind, 98(389), 119–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quinn, W. (1994). Morality and action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schafer, K. (2013). Perception and the rational force of desire. Journal of Philosophy, 110(5), 258–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Setiya, K. (2007). Reasons without rationalism. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Setiya, K. (2010). Sympathy for the devil. In Desire, practical reason, and the good (pp. 82–110). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Siegel, S. (2006). Which properties are represented in perception? In T. S. Gendler, & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual experience (pp. 481–503). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Starkey, Charles. (2006). On the category of moral perception. Social Theory & Practice, 32(1), 45–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tenenbaum, S. (2007). Appearances of the good. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tenenbaum, S. (2010). Desire, practical reason, and the good. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Velleman, D. (1992). The guise of the good. Noûs, 26(1), 3–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I will like to thank audiences at the Eight European Congress of Analytic Philosophy, held at the University of Bucharest, Romania, and the 50th Annual Meeting of the Western Canadian Philosophical Association, held in Winnipeg, Canada, for their valuable feedback on earlier versions of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Avery Archer.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Archer, A. Do desires provide reasons? An argument against the cognitivist strategy. Philos Stud 173, 2011–2027 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0594-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0594-y

Keywords

Navigation