Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Retooling Techno-Moral Scenarios. A Revisited Technique for Exploring Alternative Regimes of Responsibility for Human Enhancement

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
NanoEthics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The techno-moral scenarios (TMS) approach has been developed to explore the interplay between technology, society and morality. Focused on new and emerging sciences and technologies, techno-moral scenarios can be used to inform and enhance public deliberation on the desirability of socio-technical trajectories. The article presents an attempt to hybridise this scenario tool, complementing the focus on ethics with an explicit acknowledgement of the multiple meanings of responsibility and of the plurality of its regimes, i.e. the institutional arrangements presiding over the assumption and assignment of responsibilities. We call this integrated technique ‘rTMS’ to stress the continuity with the original technique and, at the same time, to highlight the additional element we aim to develop: responsibility. The article describes this approach and illustrates a loosely standardised procedure that can be used to organise and conduct public engagement workshops based on rTMS.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Boenink, Swierstra and Stemerding define morality as “the set of values and norms that a specific community considers very important, because they refer to legitimate interests, mutual obligations and/or views of the good life. Although the precise boundaries of this set may be contested, morality largely exists in the form of implicit beliefs, routines and practices”. Morality is different from ethics, which is “the reflection and debate on the relevance and status of (parts of) morality; ethics, that is, is reflexive morality. […] [A]nyone questioning or debating moral values and /or norms engages in ethical activity” ( [11], 3).

  2. There is a second, narrower connection between responsibility and the TMS literature. Stemerding [14] and Douglas and Stemerding [15] use TMS in the framework of responsible research and innovation (RRI). RRI is an approach to science and innovation governance developed mainly in the European Union (EU) policy environment, which pursues the alignment of research and innovation activities with societal goals and needs by way of participatory approaches fostering the mutual responsibilisation of science and innovation actors ( [16, 17]). In this context, TMS are used to foster the moral imagination of researchers as a preliminary step to begin a dialogue with societal stakeholders to explore the social and needs priorities that can be responded to by research.

  3. “It should be stressed that the distinction between hard and soft impacts is not neutral or descriptive. Instead, it is a largely rhetorical distinction brought into play by one group of powerful players (policymakers and technology actors) for practical – or strategic – purposes” ( [13], 7).

  4. We follow Gorgoni in naming these four responsibility paradigms. However, this author has argued that the features of RRI reflect a broader understanding of responsibility that is rooted in a specific political-economic framework, namely neoliberalism [30]. The term ‘responsibilisation’ has been used to describe the definition of responsibility typical of this political-economic context and might well be used to label the fourth paradigm identified by Gorgoni [37].

  5. For a general appraisal of vignettes in social science research, see Hughes and Huby [42].

  6. For an example of a video scenario, see, for example: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=xGQ6Cp1dC4c (accessed September 15, 2018).

  7. To conduct a rTMS exercise, the facilitator can use material aids and tools, such as cards and a ‘game’ board, that can prompt and support the conversation among the workshop participants. In this article, we do not present these details for the sake of clarity and due to limited space.

  8. The distinction is based on the work of Talcott Parsons [43]. Socialisation refers to the incorporation of values and norms in the psychological structure of individuals; institutionalisation refers to the incorporation of select normative models in the social system of incentives and sanctions.

  9. Personas are built upon research data on users and, more generally, social groups and strata. Due to the mock nature of the scenario presented in this article, which was used for testing the procedure with students, the features of the persona who is the scenario protagonist were arbitrarily decided by the author.

  10. This scenario is based on the work of the students of the Galilean School of Advanced Studies of Padova University (Italy), in which rTMS were first tested in may 2017. The classroom discussion and the scenario moved from the mission of Elon Musk’s start-up ‘Neuralink’. The company plans to build a ‘neural lace’, a brain-computer interface technology enabling bi-directional communication between the human brain and computers. The goal of Musk’s venture is to allow humans to run external digital devices and fast download and upload information and data from/to computers to improve their cognitive performance in areas such as memory and information processing. There are many news articles describing Neuralink’s goals (e.g., [46]) and critiquing the feasibility of Musk’s ideas (e.g., [47]).

  11. This distinction has the same pragmatic logic as the differentiation of cooperative/competitive social relations in Step 1.

  12. While this article applies rTMS to HE, the application perimeter of this technique is not limited to this subject and covers the ‘soft impacts’ of new and emerging technologies in general, rather than of specific domains.

References

  1. Sauter A, Gerlinger K (2014) The pharmacologically improved human: performance-enhancing substances as a social Challenge BoD - Books on Demand, Norderstedt

  2. Kass LR (2003) Ageless bodies, happy souls: biotechnology and the pursuit of perfection. The New Atlantis 1:9–28

    Google Scholar 

  3. Sandel MJ (2009) The case against perfection: ethics in the age of genetic engineering. The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  4. Garcia T, Sandler R (2008) Enhancing justice? NanoEthics 2:277–287. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11569-008-0048-5

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. McVeigh J, Evans-Brown M, Bellis MA (2012) Human enhancement drugs and the pursuit of perfection. Adicciones 24:185–190

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Fukuyama F (2003) Our posthuman future: consequences of the biotechnology revolution. Profile Books, London

  7. Harris J (2011) Enhancing evolution: the ethical case for making better people. Princeton University Press, Princeton

  8. Savulescu J, Sandberg A, Kahane G (2014) Well-being and enhancement. In: Savulescu J, Meulen RHJ ter, Kahane G (eds) Enhancing human capacities. Wiley-Blackwell, Chichester, p 1–18

    Google Scholar 

  9. Bostrom N, Roache R (2011) Smart policy: cognitive enhancement in the public interest. In: Savulescu J, Meulen RHJ ter, Kahane G (eds) Enhancing human capacities. Wiley-Blackwell, Chichester, p 138–149

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  10. Meacham D (2015) The subject of enhancement: augmented capacities, extended cognition, and delicate ecologies of the mind. The New Bioethics 21:5–19. https://doi.org/10.1179/2050287715Z.00000000063

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Boenink M, Swierstra T, Stemerding D (2010) Anticipating the interaction between technology and morality: a scenario study of experimenting with humans in bionanotechnology. Studies in Ethics, Law, and Technology 4. https://doi.org/10.2202/1941-6008.1098

  12. Swierstra T, Stemerding D, Boenink M (2009) Exploring techno-moral change: the case of the ObesityPill. In: Sollie P, Düwell M (eds) Evaluating new technologies. Springer Netherlands, Dordrecht, pp 119–138

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  13. Swierstra T (2015) Identifying the normative challenges posed by technology’s ‘soft’ impacts. Etikk i praksis - Nordic Journal of Applied Ethics 9. https://doi.org/10.5324/eip.v9i1.1838

  14. Stemerding D (2015) iGEM as laboratory in responsible research and innovation. Journal of Responsible Innovation 2:140–142. https://doi.org/10.1080/23299460.2014.1002171

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Douglas CM, Stemerding D (2014) Challenges for the European governance of synthetic biology for human health. Life Sciences, Society and Policy 10:6. https://doi.org/10.1186/s40504-014-0006-7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. von Schomberg R (2013) A vision of responsible research and innovation. In: Owen R, Bessant J, Heintz M (eds) Responsible Innovation. John Wiley & Sons, Ltd, Chichester, pp 51–74

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  17. Stilgoe J, Owen R, Macnaghten P (2013) Developing a framework for responsible innovation. Res Policy 42:1568–1580. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.respol.2013.05.008

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Wack P (1985) Scenarios: shooting the rapids. Harv Bus Rev:139–150

  19. Amer M, Daim TU, Jetter A (2013) A review of scenario planning. Futures 46:23–40. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.futures.2012.10.003

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Börjeson L, Höjer M, Dreborg K-H, Ekvall T, Finnveden G (2006) Scenario types and techniques: towards a user’s guide. Futures 38:723–739. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.futures.2005.12.002

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Roubelat F (2000) Scenario planning as a networking process. Technol Forecast Soc Chang 65:99–112. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0040-1625(99)00125-0

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Masini EB, Vasquez JM (2000) Scenarios as seen from a human and social perspective. Technol Forecast Soc Chang 65:49–66. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0040-1625(99)00127-4

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Barbieri Masini E (1993) Why futures studies? Grey Seal, London

    Google Scholar 

  24. Palm E, Hansson SO (2006) The case for ethical technology assessment (eTA). Technol Forecast Soc Chang 73:543–558. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.techfore.2005.06.002

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Est R van, Rerimassie V, Keulen I van, et al (2014) Intimate technology: the battle for our body and behaviour. Rathenau Institute, The Hague

  26. Luhmann N (2005) Risk: a sociological theory. Aldine Transaction, New Brunswick

    Google Scholar 

  27. Nordmann A (2007) If and then: a critique of speculative nanoethics. NanoEthics 1:31–46. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11569-007-0007-6

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. Nordmann A, Rip A (2009) Mind the gap revisited. Nat Nanotechnol 4:273–274. https://doi.org/10.1038/nnano.2009.26

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Boenink M (2010) Imagining the future: how vignettes and scenarios might improve ethical reflection on synthetic biology for health purposes. In: Szebik I. (ed) Ethics and clinical applications of synthetic biology: an interdisciplinary dialogue. SYBHEL project, Bilbao, p 55–64

  30. Arnaldi S, Gorgoni G (2016) Turning the tide or surfing the wave? Responsible research and innovation, fundamental rights and neoliberal virtues. Life Sciences, Society and Policy 12:6. https://doi.org/10.1186/s40504-016-0038-2

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Gorgoni G (2018) Responsible research and innovation and the governance of human enhancement. NanoEthics 12(3). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11569-018-0326-9

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Vincent NA (2011) A structured taxonomy of responsibility concepts. In: Vincent NA, van de Poel I, van den Hoven J (eds) Moral responsibility. Springer, Dordrecht, p 15–35

  33. Hart HLA (2008) Punishment and responsibility: essays in the philosophy of law. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  34. Davis M (2012) “Ain’t no one here but us social forces”: constructing the professional responsibility of engineers. Sci Eng Ethics 18:13–34. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-010-9225-3

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. van de Poel I, Nihlén Fahlquist J, Doorn N, Zwart S, Royakkers L (2012) The problem of many hands: climate change as an example. Sci Eng Ethics 18:49–67. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-011-9276-0

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. Forsberg E-M, Quaglio G, O’Kane H et al (2015) Assessment of science and technologies: advising for and with responsibility. Technol Soc 42:21–27. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.techsoc.2014.12.004

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. Shamir R (2008) The age of responsibilization: on market-embedded morality. Econ Soc 37:1–19. https://doi.org/10.1080/03085140701760833

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Arnaldi S, Bianchi L (2016) Responsibility in science and technology. Elements of a social theory. Springer VS, Wiesbaden

    Book  Google Scholar 

  39. Finch J (1987) The vignette technique in survey research. Sociology 21:105–114. https://doi.org/10.1177/0038038587021001008

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. Alexander CS, Becker HJ (1978) The use of vignettes in survey research. Public Opinion Quarterly 42:93. https://doi.org/10.1086/268432

    Article  Google Scholar 

  41. Wilks T (2004) The use of vignettes in qualitative research into social work values. Qualitative Social Work: Research and Practice 3:78–87. https://doi.org/10.1177/1473325004041133

    Article  Google Scholar 

  42. Hughes R, Huby M (2004) The construction and interpretation of vignettes in social research. Soc Work Soc Sci Rev 11:36–51. https://doi.org/10.1921/17466105.11.1.36

    Article  Google Scholar 

  43. Parsons T (1991) The social system. Free Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  44. Madsen S, Nielsen L (2010) Exploring persona-scenarios - using storytelling to create design ideas. In: Katre D, Orngreen R, Yammiyavar P, Clemmensen T (eds) Human work interaction design: usability in social, cultural and organizational contexts. Springer, Berlin, pp 57–66

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  45. Milne S (2009) Scenarios and personas: towards a methodology for portraying the carbon intensity of UK lifestyles to 2030, Scott Milne, RESOLVE working paper 06–09. University of Surrey

  46. Fourtané S (2018) Neuralink: how the human brain will download directly from a computer. https://interestingengineering.com/neuralink-how-the-human-brain-will-download-directly-from-a-computer. Accessed 29 Sep 2018

  47. Regalado A (2017) With Neuralink, Elon Musk promises human-to-human telepathy. Don’t believe it. https://www.technologyreview.com/s/604254/with-neuralink-elon-musk-promises-human-to-human-telepathy-dont-believe-it/. Accessed 29 Sep 2018

  48. Swierstra T, Rip A (2007) Nano-ethics as NEST-ethics: patterns of moral argumentation about new and emerging science and technology. NanoEthics 1:3–20. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11569-007-0005-8

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author would like to thank two anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments. I wish to thank the participants in the mutual learning workshop on “Responsibility and human enhancement” held in Padova, Italy, on May 22, 2017, for their precious comments and suggestions on the first draft of this article. In particular, we would like to express our gratitude to Tsjalling Swierstra who acted as the discussant of this paper during the workshop. Finally, I gratefully acknowledge the funding from the Independent Social Research Foundation (ISRF), Flexible Grants for Small Research Groups program, which made it possible to conduct this research as part of the project “Responsibility and Human Enhancement. Concepts, implications and assessments”.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Simone Arnaldi.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Arnaldi, S. Retooling Techno-Moral Scenarios. A Revisited Technique for Exploring Alternative Regimes of Responsibility for Human Enhancement. Nanoethics 12, 283–300 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11569-018-0329-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11569-018-0329-6

Keywords

Navigation