Skip to main content
Log in

Signaling without cooperation

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Ethological theories usually attribute semantic content to animal signals. To account for this fact, many biologists and philosophers appeal to some version of teleosemantics. However, this picture has recently came under attack: while mainstream teleosemantics assumes that representational systems must cooperate, some biologists and philosophers argue that in certain cases signaling can evolve within systems lacking common interest. In this paper I defend the standard view from this objection.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. It is important to notice that a sender–receiver structure can be instantiated within a single organism or in different organisms.

  2. Of course, this sender-receiver model is supposed to apply at the level of types. Teleosemantics does not require that every representation (token) is consumed by another system. A particular alarm call can be a representation even if it is not heard by any fellow. It suffices if these activities are performed often enough in consumer systems of that type. We will come back to that issue later.

  3. Strictly speaking, Millikanian teleosemantics claims we should focus on the least detailed Normal explanation of how C has historically performed its function. Since these details are irrelevant for the discussion at hand, I will leave them aside.

  4. One can easily be misled here by the different uses of the expression 'common interest' that can be found in the literature. For instance, Maynard Smith and Harper (2003, p. 27) define cases of ‘common interest’ as involving two organisms that 'place the possible outcomes of the interaction in the same rank order of preference'. This is a stronger notion from the one I am using here (and the one that is required for teleosemantics). In the sense intended here, there can be common interest between two organisms even if there is partial competition or even if signaling involves some partial cost that could be avoided by the organisms involved. This is why, prima facie, phenomena like the ‘handicap principle’ (Zahavi and Zahavi 1997) do not threaten teleosemantics.

  5. Nonetheless, a rejection of the cooperation requirement, the sender-receiver model and condition 1a of teleosemantics is still compatible with some versions of teleosemantics. Indeed, as I will argue later, one could keep condition 1b in order to develop a consumer-based teleosemantic account very similar to Millikans' own approach. I want to thank an anonymous referee for pressing on this issue.

  6. Mimicry is defined in terms of the Photuris versicolor and Photinus species, but notice that the problem pointed out here concerns (at least) any case of aggressive mimicry. This example is supposed to highlight a broad and significant set of cases that mainstream teleosemantics cannot account for.

  7. This qualification is required because it has been argued that, in some cases, predator and prey may have some common interest. For instance, according to the Perception Advertisement Hypothesis, some organisms inform their predators that they have been perceived, so that hunting per surprise becomes futile (Radner 1999, p. 129–130). Gazelles, for example, perform a set of controlled jumps (called 'stotting') so as to communicate to the predator that it has been detected (Sterelny and Griffiths 1999) or that it is a healthy exemplar (Maynard-Smith and Harper 2003, p. 61; Ruxton et al. 2004, ch. 6). Apparently, this sort of signs benefit both predator and prey; the former does not attempt an attack that will probably fail and the latter avoids a possible threat (Millikan 2004; Ruxton et al. 2004, ch. 6).

    Even if these examples exist, aggressive mimicry seems to be a different sort of case. It is extremely plausible that the light emitted by Predator in order to lure F-males only benefits the former.

  8. Here I think Stegmann (2009, p. 868) misdescribes what the mainstream teleosemanticists would say. He claims that, on this view, ‘the function of the predator’s producing device is to token [F-female-type] flashes that map the presence of the hungry predator’. If that were the case (and assuming mainstream teleosemantics) the flash would mean there is a hungry predator, and not there is an F-female willing to mate. However, that would constitute a denial of Mimicry (see also 3.3).

  9. Of course, assuming that the Predator’s flashings are real signals can also explain why F-males are mistaken. Nonetheless, that does not affect my main point; what I argue is that accepting that they are signals is not required in explanations of behavior and that rejecting mimicry has interesting advantages from a scientific point of view.

  10. Notice that, for our purposes, we only need to assume that this process of copy is a sufficient condition for a set of entities to constitute a biological kind. The idea is, I think, extremely plausible and it is a claim that many teleosemanticists have explicitly argued for (Millikan 1984, 2000; Neander 2002).

  11. Let me mention that kinds like heart or eye, which are sometimes suggested in the literature, are probably not reproductive kinds in the sense intended here. Eyes, for instance, have probably evolved independently several times (Nilsson 1996), so convergence rather than homology explains why they share many properties in common. Perhaps vertebrate eye or mammalian heart are more plausible examples of reproductive kinds. I want to thank an anonymous referee for this suggestion.

  12. Note that this argument is only supposed to defend Teleosemantics from a sensible objection. In particular, it does not provide a reason for favoring Teleosemantics over Stegmann’s view, because the latter can avoid the problem by simply denying that there is any sense in which the Predator’s mechanism is malfunctioning. I want to thank an anonymous referee for pressing me on this issue.

References

  • Boyd R (1988) How to be a moral realist. In: Sayre-McCord G (ed) Moral realism. Cornell University Press, Ithaca

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd R (1991) Realism, anti-foundationalism and the enthusiasm for natural kinds. Philos Stud 61(1–2):127–148

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd R (1999) Homeostasis, species, and higher taxa. In: Wilson R (ed) Species: new interdisciplinary essays. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 141–185

    Google Scholar 

  • Cao R (2012) A teleosemantic approach to information in the brain. Biol Philos 27:49–71

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R, Krebs JR (1978) Animal signals: information or manipulation. In: Krebs JR, Davies, NB (eds) Behavioural ecology: an evolutionary approach. Blalckwell Scientific Publications, Oxford

  • Eberhard WG (1977) Aggressive chemical mimicry by a bolas spider. Science 198:1173–1775

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • El-Hani Ch, Keiroz J, Stjenfelt F (2010) Firefly Femmes fatales: a case study in the semiotics of deception. Biosemiotics 3(1):33–55

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (1996) Complexity and the function of mind in nature. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2006) Mental representation, naturalism and teleosemantics. In: MacDonald, Papineau D (eds) Teleosemantics. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2009) Darwinian populations and natural selection. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths P (1999) Squaring the circle: natural kinds with historical essence. In: Wilson R (ed) Species: new interdisciplinary studies. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hafernik J, Saul-Gershenz L (2000) Beetle larvae cooperate to mimic bees. Nature 205(6782):35–36

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hollen L, Radford A (2009) The development of alarm call behavior in mammals and birds. Anim Behav 78:791–800

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krause J (1993) Transmission of fright reaction between different species of fish. Behaviour 127(½):37–48

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leavesley A, Magrath R (2004) Communicating about danger: urgency alarm calling in a bird. Anim Behav 70:365–373

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D (1969) Convention: a philosophical study. John Wiley and Sons, Hoboken

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis S, Cratsley Ch (2008) Flash signal evolution, mate choice, and predation in fireflies. Annu Rev Entomol 53:293–321

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd J (1975) Aggressive mimicry in photuris fireflies: signal repertoires by femmes fatales. Science 187(4175):452–453

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marshall DC, Hill KBR (2009) Versatile aggressive mimicry of cicadas by an Australian preadtory katydid. PLOS One 4:1

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mathis A, Smith J (1993) Fethead minnows, Pimphales prolemas, learn to recognize northern pike, Esox Lucius, as predators on the basis of chemical stimuli from minnows in the pike’s diet. Anim Behav 46:645–656

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mathis A, Chivers D, Smith R (1996) Cultural transmission of predator recognition in fishes: intraspecific and interspecific learning. Anim Behav 51(1):185–201

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard-Smith J, Harper D (2003) Animal signals. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Merilaita S (1998) Crypsis through disruptive coloration in an isopod. Proc R Soc Biol Sci 265(1401):1059–1064

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan RG (1984) Language, thought and other biological categories. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan RG (1993) White queen psychology and other essays for alice. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan RG (2000) On clear and confused ideas. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan RG (2004) Varieties of meaning. MIT Press, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan RG (2005) Language: a biological model. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Neander K (1991) Functions as selected effects: the conceptual analyst’s defense. Philos Sci 58(2):168–184

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander K (2002) Types of traits: the importance of functional homologues. In: Ariew A, Cummins R, Perlman M (eds) Functions: new readings in the philosophy of psychology and biology. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Neander K (2006) Content for cognitive science. In: MacDonald, Papineau D (eds) Teleosemantics. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 140–159

    Google Scholar 

  • Neander K (2012) Teleological theories of mental content. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2012 edn). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2012/entries/content-teleological/

  • Neander K (2013) Toward an informational teleosemantics. In: Ryder D, Kingsbury J, Williford K (eds) Millikan and her critics. Wiley-Blackwell, Oxford

  • Nilsson D (1996) Ols genes for new eyes. Curr Biol 6(1):39–42

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Papineau D (2003) Is representation rife? Ratio 16(2):107–123

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Radner D (1999) Mind and function in animal communication. Erkenntnis 51:129–144

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rendall D, Owren M, Ryan M (2009) What do animal signals mean? Anim Behav 78:233–240

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts JA, Taylorb PW, Uetzc GW (2007) Consequences of complex signaling: predator detection of multimodal cues. Behav Ecol 18(1):236–240

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruxton G, Sherratt T, Speed M (2004) Avoiding attack. The evolutionary ecology of crypsis, warning signals, and mimicry. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Sazima I, Nobre-Carvalho L, Pereira-Mendonça F, Zuanon J (2006) Fallen leaves on the water-bed: diurnal camouflage of three night active fish species in an Amazonian streamlet. Neotrop Ichthyol 4:1

    Google Scholar 

  • Schulte P (forthcoming) Perceptual representations: a teleosemantic answer to the breadth-of-application problem, Biology and Philosophy

  • Searcy W, Nowicki S (2005) The evolution of animal communication. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Seyfarth RM, Cheney D, Bergman T, Fischer J, Zuberbühler K, Hammerschmidt K (2010) The central importance of information in studies of animal communication. Anim Behav 80:3–8

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shea N (2007) Consumers need information: supplementing teleosemantics with an input condition. Philos Phenomenol Res 75(2):404–435

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms B (1996) Evolution of the social contract. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms B (2010) Signals: evolution, learning, and information. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1984) The nature of selection: evolutionary theory in philosophical focus. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Stegmann U (2005) John Maynard’s Smith notion of animal signals. Biol Philos 20:1011–1025

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stegmann U (2009) A consumer based teleosemantics for animal signals. Philos Sci 76:5

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K (1995) Basic minds. Philos Perspect 9:251–270

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K, Griffiths P (1999) Sex and death: an introduction to philosophy of biology. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Wickler W (1965) Mimicry and the evolution of animal communication. Nature 5010:519–521

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson R (1999) Realism, essence, and kind: resuscitating species essentialism? In: Wilson R (ed) Species: new interdisciplinary studies. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright L (1973) Functions. Philos Rev 82(2):139–168

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi A, Zahavi A (1997) The handicap principle. The missing piece of Darwin’s puzzle. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Alejandro Díaz, Manolo Martinez, David Pineda, an anonymous referee and the audience of the XV Taller d’Investigació en Filosofia (TIF) for very helpful comments, suggestions and criticisms.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marc Artiga.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Artiga, M. Signaling without cooperation. Biol Philos 29, 357–378 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-014-9436-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-014-9436-0

Keywords

Navigation