Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-jr42d Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-18T23:37:24.879Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Reasons, Explanation, and Saramago's Bell

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 March 2020

Abstract

In this essay, I suggest that significant insights of recent feminist philosophy lead, among other things, to the thought that it is not always better to choose than to be compelled to do what one might have done otherwise. However, few feminists, if any, would defend such a suggestion. I ask why it is difficult to consider certain ideas that, while challenging in theory, are, nonetheless, rather unproblematic in practice. I suggest that some questions are not pursued seriously enough by philosophers, because certain popular liberal conceptions of individuality and freedom are taken too much for granted.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 2005 by Hypatia, Inc.

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Achebe, Chinua. 1988. Anthills of the savannah. London: Picador.Google Scholar
Babbitt, Susan. 1996. Impossible dreams: Rationality, integrity, and moral imagination. Boulder, Colo.: Westview PressGoogle Scholar
Benson, Paul. 1999. Feeling crazy: Self‐worth and the social character of responsibility. In Relational autonomy, ed. MacKenzie, Catriona and Stoljar, Natalie. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Calhoun, Cheshire. 1999. Moral failure. In On feminist ethics and politics, ed. Card, Claudia. Lawrence: University Press of Kansas.Google Scholar
Dillon, Robin. 1997. Self‐respect: Emotional, moral, political. Ethics 107: 226–49.10.1086/233719CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fanon, Frantz. 1967. Black skin, white masks. New York: Grove Press.Google Scholar
Frye, Marilyn. 1983. The politics of reality. Trumansberg, N.Y.: Crossing Press.Google Scholar
Guevara, Ernesto. 1997. Socialism and man in Cuba. In The Che Guevara reader, ed. Deutschmann, David. Melbourne: Ocean Press, 197214.Google Scholar
Kymlicka, Will. 1991. Liberaiism, community, and culture. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
MacIntyre, Alisdair. 1999. Social structures and their threats to moral agency. Philosophy 74: 311–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martinez, Osvaldo. 2001. Posición de Cuba sobre el ALCA. Havana: Oficina de publicaciones del consejo de estado.Google Scholar
Miller, Richard W. 1987. Fact and method. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Mills, Claudia 1998. Choice and circumstance. Ethics 109: 154–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miná, Gianni. 2001. Un continente desaparecido. Havana: Casa Editorial Abril.Google Scholar
Toni, Morrison. 1992. Playing in the dark: Whiteness and the literary imagination. New York: Vintage Books.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1971. A theory of justice. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Styron, William. 1979. Sophie's choice. New York: Vintage Books.Google Scholar
Searle, John. 1995. The construction of social reality. New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
Saramago, Jose. 2002. From justice to democracy by way of the bells, World Social Forum, March 9, 2002, Puerto Alegre, Brazil. http://www.znet.org/content/VisionStrategy/Saramogobell.cfm (accessed July 2002).Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 1985. The standard of living. The Tanner lectures Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar