Skip to main content
Log in

Is There a Role for Adversariality in Teaching Critical Thinking?

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There has been considerable recent debate regarding the possible epistemic benefits versus the potential risks of adversariality in argumentation. Nonetheless, this debate has rarely found its way into work on critical thinking theory and instruction. This paper focuses on the implications of the adversariality debate for teaching critical thinking. Is there a way to incorporate the benefits of adversarial argumentation while mitigating the problems? Our response is an approach based on dialectical inquiry which focuses on a confrontation of opposing views within a collaborative framework.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. One work which does deal with the issue of adversariality in critical thinking instruction is Hundleby’s (2010) discussion of problems with the adversary paradigm in the teaching of fallacies.

  2. We acknowledge that there are many goals individuals may have for arguing other than the making of reasoned judgments. Our focus, however, is on argumentation as an epistemic practice and the debate over the value of adversarial argumentation as a means for epistemic improvement.

  3. Both Govier (2020) and Aikin (2017) have subsequently modified their positions to focus on adversariality in terms of roles rather than individuals (see Sects. 3.2.2 and 6.2).

  4. We subsequently adopt Stevens and Cohen’s (2019b) term “adversarial stance” (see Sect. 5.1).

  5. See our discussion in Sect. 5.1.

  6. The most favourable context for facilitating such interactive, group-oriented pedagogy is clearly in small classes, which are the ideal for any type of critical thinking instruction. Nonetheless there are ways to work towards this approach in larger classes, including having students work in smaller groups for particular projects and assignments both in and outside of class, using tutorials as a venue for group interaction, the use of interactive online forums, transforming the structure of lecture classes including the uses of techniques such as ‘think-pair-share’ (https://cft.vanderbilt.edu/guides-sub-pages/setting-up-and-facilitating-group-work-using-cooperative-learning-groups-effectively/), a ‘flipped classroom’( https://cft.vanderbilt.edu/guides-sub-pages/flipping-the-classroom/) or ‘just in time teaching’ (https://jittdl.physics.iupui.edu/jitt/). There are more specific suggestions offered in the Instructors’ Manual to our text, Reason in the Balance, as well as many ideas for changing the dynamics of large classes available on the web (e.g., https://cft.vanderbilt.edu/guides-sub-pages/lecturing/-interactive).

  7. A functioning community of inquiry is most easily established in smaller groups. But instructors can work at encouraging the inquiry orientation which underpins such a community through the atmosphere and expectations they establish and their own mode of interacting with students’ questions and challenges. They can, for example, engage students in a discussion about the nature of collaborative inquiry and ask them to come up with what would be appropriate expectations for students of other students, for students of themselves, for students of the instructor, and for the instructor of students engaging in collaborative inquiry. Another important aspect is instructor modelling of the appropriate virtues of inquiry such as open-mindedness, respect for students’ ideas, a willingness to follow ideas where they lead, and an openness to being mistaken and to altering their own view if warranted.

  8. Cf. Stevens and Cohen: “The attitude arguers have in an argument will impact their argumentative behavior. E.g., an arguer with a cooperative attitude will aim to act so that the arguers as a group will identify and correctly weigh reasons applicable to the issue. By contrast, an arguer with an adversarial attitude will behave in those ways she hopes will ultimately help her achieve her goal of winning.” (Stevens and Cohen 2019b).

  9. Aikin (2017) does acknowledge a collaborative dimension in the sense that these moves of critical probing which are necessary for minimal dialectical adversariality and which are oppositional in terms of their dialectical function are “in the service of a broader cooperative goal of dialectical testing of reasons and acceptability” (p. 16).

  10. Stevens (2020) makes a similar claim with respect to the principle of charity—that one ought to try to understand what one’s interlocutor is trying to say despite the fact that this task is “potentially so difficult that it can only ever remain an ideal goal, always pursued, never fully achieved” (p. 7).

  11. Two strategies adapted from those offered by Stevens (2020) might be helpful in such situations. One is trying to change the way an adversarial argument is starting to be structured by persisting in a collaborative inquiry role hoping the other arguer will “shift gears.” The other is to start a meta-dialogue, “asking, for example, why the arguer is so aggressive, or whether they could work together in their reasoning” (p. 17).

References

  • Aikin SF (2011) A defense of war and sports metaphors in argument. Philos Rhetoric 44(3):250–272

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aikin SF (2017) Fallacy theory, the negativity problem, and minimal dialectical adversariality. Cogency 9(1):7–19

    Google Scholar 

  • Ayim M (1991) Dominance and affiliation. Informal Logic 13(2):79–88

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bail C, Argyle L, Brown T, Bumpus J, Chen H, Hunzakeer F, Lee J, Mann M, Merhout F, Volfovsky A (2018) Exposure to opposing views can increase political polarization: evidence from a large-scale field experiment on social media. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1804840115

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bailin S, Battersby M (2007) Reason appreciation. In: Hansen HV, Pinto R (eds) Reason reclaimed. Vale Press, Newport News

    Google Scholar 

  • Bailin S, Battersby M (2009) Inquiry: a dialectical approach to teaching critical thinking. In: Ritola J (ed) Argument cultures, CD-ROM. OSSA, Windsor

    Google Scholar 

  • Bailin S, Battersby M (2015) Fostering the virtues of inquiry. Topoi 35(2):367–374

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bailin S, Battersby M (2016a) Reason in the balance: an inquiry approach to critical thinking, 2nd edn. Hackett, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Bailin S, Battersby M (2016b) DAMed if you do; DAMed if you don’t: Cohen’s ‘Missed Opportunities.’ In: Bondy P, Benaquista L (eds), Argumentation, objectivity, and bias: proceedings of the 11th International Conference of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation (OSSA) 18–21 May 201, (pp. 1–12), OSSA, Windsor

  • Baumtrog M (2017) Others and imagination in reasoning and argumentation: improving our critical creative capacity. Informal Logic 37(2):129–151

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Biro J, Siegel H (1997) Epistemic normativity, argumentation, and fallacies. Argumentation 11:277–292

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Biro J, Siegel H (2006) In defense of the objective epistemic approach to argumentation. Informal Logic 26(1):91–101

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blair JA (1987) Argumentation, inquiry and speech act theory. In: van Eemeren FH, Grootendorst R, Blair JA, Willard C (eds) Argumentation: across the lines of discipline. Foris Publications, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen DH (1995) Argument as war … and war is hell: philosophy, education, and metaphors for argumentation. Informal Logic 17(2):177–188

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen DH (2015) Missed opportunities in argument evaluation. In: van Eemeren FH, Garssen BJ (eds) Reflections on theoretical issues in argumentation theory. Springer, New York, pp 121–130

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen GL, Bastardi A, Sherman DK, McGoey M, Hsu L, Ross L (2007) Bridging the partisan divide: self-affirmation reduces ideological closed-mindedness and inflexibility in negotiation. J Pers Soc Psychol 93(3):415–430

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Finocchiaro M (1994) Two empirical approaches to the study of reasoning. Informal Logic 16(1):1–21

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Govier T (1999) The philosophy of argument. Vale Press, Newport News

    Google Scholar 

  • Govier T (2020) Opposition and polarization. In: Blair JA, Tindale C (eds) Rigour and reason: essays in honour of Hans Wilhelm Hansen. Windsor Studies in Argumentation, Windsor, pp 87–110

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt J (2012) The righteous mind: why good people are divided by politics and religion. Vintage Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Hundleby C (2010) The authority of the fallacies approach to argument evaluation. Informal Logic 30(3):279–308

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hundleby C (2013) Aggression, politeness, and abstract adversaries. Informal Logic 33(2):238–262

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Janis IL (1982) Groupthink, 2nd rev. Houghton Mifflin, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson DW, Johnson RT (1988) Critical thinking through structured controversy. Educ Leadersh 45(8):58–64

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson DW, Johnson RT (2009) Energizing learning: the instructional power of conflict. Educ Res 38(1):37–51

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahan DM (2013) Ideology, motivated reasoning, and cognitive reflection. Judgment Decis Making 8(4):407–424

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahan DM, Jenkins-Smith H, Braman D (2011) Cultural cognition of scientific consensus. J Risk Res 14(2):147–174

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn D (1991) The skills of argument. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn D, Crowell A (2011) Dialogic argumentation as a vehicle for developing young adolescents’ thinking. Psychol Sci 22(4):545–552

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff G, Johnson M (1980) Metaphors we live by. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Lombardi D, Nussbaum EM, Sinatra GM (2015) Plausibility judgments in conceptual change and epistemic cognition. Educ Psychol 51(1):35–56

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lord CG, Ross L, Lepper MR (1979) Biased assimilation and attitude polarization: the effects of prior theories on subsequently considered evidence. J Pers Soc Psychol 37(11):2098–2109

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lumer C (2005) The epistemological theory of argument—how and why? Informal Logic 25(3):213–243

    Google Scholar 

  • Mercier H (2016) The argumentative theory: predictions and empirical evidence. Trends Cogn Sci 20(9):689–700

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mercier H, Sperber D (2017) The enigma of reason. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Mercier H, Boudry M, Paglieri F, Trouche E (2017) Natural-born arguers: teaching how to make the best of our reasoning abilities. Educ Psychol 52(1):1–16

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moulton J (1989) A paradigm of philosophy: the adversary method. In: Harding S, Hintikka MB (eds) Discovering reality: feminist perspectives on epistemology, metaphysics, methodology, and philosophy of science. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 149–164

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum EM (2002) How introverts versus extroverts approach classroom argumentative discussions. Elementary Sch J 102:183–197

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perkins DN (1989) Reasoning as it is and as it could be: an empirical perspective. In: Topping DN, Crowell DC, Kobayashi VN (eds) Thinking across cultures: the third international conference on thinking. Lawrence Erlbaum, Hillsdale

    Google Scholar 

  • Perkins DN, Tishman S (2001) Dispositional aspects of intelligence. In: Messick S, Collis JM (eds) Intelligence and personality: bridging the gap in theory and measurement. Lawrence Erlbaum, Mahwah, pp 233–257

    Google Scholar 

  • Perkins DN, Allen R, Hafner J (1983) Difficulties in everyday reasoning. In: Maxwell W (ed) Thinking: the expanding frontier. The Franklin Institute Press, Philadelphia

    Google Scholar 

  • Perkins DN, Farady M, Bushey B (1991) Everyday reasoning and the roots of intelligence. In: Voss J, Perkins DN, Segal J (eds) Informal reasoning. Lawrence Erlbaum, Hillsdale, pp 83–105

    Google Scholar 

  • Rooney P (2010) Philosophy, adversarial argumentation, and embattled reason. Informal Logic 30(3):203–234

    Google Scholar 

  • Schulz-Hardt S, Frey D, Luthgens C, Moscovici S (2000) Biased information search in group decision making. J Pers Soc Psychol 78:655–669

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schulz-Hardt S, Jochims M, Frey D (2002) Productive conflict in group decision making: genuine and contrived dissent as strategies to counteract biased information seeking. Organ Behav Hum Decis Process 88:563–586

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schulz-Hardt S, Brodbeck F, Mojzisch A, Kerschreiter R, Frey D (2006) Group decision making in hidden profile situations: dissent as a facilitator for decision quality. J Pers Soc Psychol 91(6):1080–1093

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schweiger D, Sandberg W, Ragan J (1986) Group approaches for improving strategic decision-making: a comparative analysis of dialectical inquiry, devil’s advocacy, and consensus. Acad Manag J 29(1):51–71

    Google Scholar 

  • Sherman DK, Cohen GL (2002) Accepting threatening information: self-affirmation and the reduction of defensive biases. Curr Dir Psychol Sci 11(4):119–123

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siegel H (1988) Educating reason: rationality, critical thinking, and education. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Sloman S, Fernbach P (2017) The knowledge illusion: why we never think alone. Penguin, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanovich K (2011) Rationality and the reflective mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Stevens K (2016) The virtuous arguer: one person, four roles. Topoi 35(2):375–383

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stevens K (2020) Principle of charity as a moral requirement in non-institutionalized argumentation. Paper presented at OSSA 12, Windsor, 3–6 June 2020

  • Stevens K, Cohen D (2019) The attraction of the ideal has no traction on the real: on adversariality and roles in argument. Argumentation Advocacy 55(1):1–23

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stevens K, Cohen D (2019b) Why devil’s advocates are the angels of argumentation. Paper presented at 3rd European Conference on Argumentation, Groningen, The Netherlands, 24–27 June 2019

  • Sunstein CR, Hastie R (2015) Garbage in, garbage out? Some micro sources of macro errors. J Inst Econ 11(3):561–583

    Google Scholar 

  • Tannen D (1998) The argument culture: moving from debate to dialogue. Random House, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Tetlock PE (1992) The impact of accountability on judgment and choice: toward a social contingency model. In: Zanna M (ed) Advances in experimental social psychology, vol 25. Academic Press, San Diego, pp 331–37625

    Google Scholar 

  • van Bavel JJ, Pereira A (2018) The partisan brain: an identity-based model of political belief. Trends Cogn Sci 22(3):213–224

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zarefsky D (2012) A challenge and an opportunity for argumentation studies. Argumentation Advocacy 48(3):175–178

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank Monica Bhattacharjee for her helpful comments. We would also like to acknowledge the assistance of a Retirees’ Research Grant from the Faculty of Education, Simon Fraser University. An earlier version of this paper was presented at OSSA 12, Windsor, 2020.

Funding

This work was funded by a Retirees’ Research Grant from Simon Fraser University.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sharon Bailin.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

All authors declares that they have no conflict of interest.

Ethical Approval

This article does not contain any studies with human participants or animals performed by any of the authors.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bailin, S., Battersby, M. Is There a Role for Adversariality in Teaching Critical Thinking?. Topoi 40, 951–961 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-020-09713-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-020-09713-2

Keywords

Navigation