Elsevier

Cognition

Volume 96, Issue 2, June 2005, Pages 93-108
Cognition

Children's understanding of death as the cessation of agency: a test using sleep versus death

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2004.05.004Get rights and content

Abstract

An important problem faced by children is discriminating between entities capable of goal-directed action, i.e. intentional agents, and non-agents. In the case of discriminating between living and dead animals, including humans, this problem is particularly difficult, because of the large number of perceptual cues that living and dead animals share. However, there are potential costs of failing to discriminate between living and dead animals, including unnecessary vigilance and lost opportunities from failing to realize that an animal, such as an animal killed for food, is dead. This might have led to the evolution of mechanisms specifically for distinguishing between living and dead animals in terms of their ability to act. Here we test this hypothesis by examining patterns of inferences about sleeping and dead organisms by Shuar and German children between 3 and 5-years old. The results show that by age 4, causal cues to death block agency attributions to animals and people, whereas cues to sleep do not. The developmental trajectory of this pattern of inferences is identical across cultures, consistent with the hypothesis of a living/dead discrimination mechanism as a reliably developing part of core cognitive architecture.

Introduction

Nearly a century of research has documented that death is a concept that is difficult for children to grasp (Carey, 1985, Nagy, 1948, Piaget, 1929; Speece and Brent, 1984, Speece and Brent, 1996). That this is so should not, perhaps, be surprising, because death is an ontologically strange phenomenon that poses difficult perceptual and conceptual challenges (Boyer, 2001). Perceptually, the challenge lies in the vast number of cues that living and dead things share. The transition from life to death is momentary, and may be perceptually quite difficult to detect. Conceptually, the challenge lies in the fact that death is one of the few cases in which an object crosses a major ontological boundary: in this case, the boundary between living things and non-living things. Given these considerations, the data documenting children's struggle to grasp the ontological nuances of death, a struggle that lasts well into late childhood and perhaps into adulthood, make sense (for reviews, see Slaughter et al., 1999, Speece and Brent, 1984).

From a theoretical perspective, prolonged and individually variable trajectories of conceptual development are expected in domains for which there is no core architecture, i.e. for which there are no mechanisms dedicated to the development of a conceptual apparatus according to a reliable developmental schedule (Leslie, 1994, Leslie, 1988). In such cases, possession of the appropriate principles necessary for inference in the domain depends critically on acquisition of relevant knowledge (Johnson & Carey, 1998). This is often described in terms of “theory change” (Carey, 1985, Gopnik and Meltzoff, 1997). Carey and colleagues (Carey, 1985, Johnson and Carey, 1998, Slaughter et al., 1999) have proposed just such a theory change account of death understanding. Under this account, young children begin with no core architecture to provide them with the relevant inferential principles for understanding death. This is because children do not yet possess a folk biology, i.e. an understanding of the causal mechanisms, or biological functions, that sustain life.

There are a variety of studies consistent with the theory change view. For example, Johnson and Carey (1998) found that individuals with Williams syndrome, who are developmentally impaired in their acquisition of a mature folk biology, perform poorly relative to controls on measures of death understanding that rely on folk biology, including standard tests of understanding of the four classical components of the death concept (see Speece and Brent, 1984, Speece and Brent, 1996). Several other studies support the proposal that understanding biological processes as having a life-sustaining function is important for later-developing aspects of death understanding (Carey, 1985, Slaughter et al., 1999, Slaughter and Lyons, 2003; see also Inagaki & Hatano, 2002, for a discussion of the development of a “vitalist” folk biology).

The understanding of death has many facets. Here, we do not wish to dispute the proposal that acquisition of theory-like knowledge may be important for understanding death specifically as the cessation of the biological processes that sustain life. Rather, we wish to propose that at least one aspect of death understanding—the understanding of death as the cessation of agency—is subserved by early developing core architecture: namely, the agency system, an early-developing inference system dedicated to understanding and predicting the behavior of intentional agents (Johnson, 2000, Leslie, 1994). This proposal differs from previous proposals that have suggested that there is no core architecture specifically subserving death understanding (Carey, 1985). We suggest, on the contrary, that the agency detection system (Johnson, 2000, Leslie, 1994, Rakison and Poulin-Dubois, 2001, Scholl and Tremoulet, 2000) contains, as part of its proper domain, procedures for discriminating living animals (agents) from dead ones. Here we sketch the principle features of this proposal, and offer an empirical test of some of its key predictions.

Section snippets

The cessation of agency hypothesis

The concept of agency has been discussed widely in the cognitive development literature (Csibra et al., 2003, Gergely et al., 1995, Johnson, 2000, Leslie, 1994). Agents, for our purposes, are objects capable of acting in a goal-directed fashion (Leslie, 1994). From an adaptationist perspective, the concept of agency, and a system of inferential principles in which this concept plays a role, are of crucial importance to survival, and to successful interaction with the animate world, from

Information-processing features of the living/dead discrimination system

The hypothesized features of the living/dead discrimination subroutine of the agency system are summarized in Fig. 1.

The sleep/death distinction as a test

In the study reported here, we used the sleep/death distinction as a test of the cessation of agency hypothesis. Our goal was to determine whether children do, in fact, cease to license inferences about agency to objects that were once alive, but about which sufficient causal information has been provided to infer that they are dead. To do this, we used two experimental conditions: one in which a causal scenario is provided that leads to an animal's or a human's death, and another in which the

Subjects

Children from two different populations participated in this study: 3-, 4-, and 5-year-old children from Berlin, Germany, and 3-, 4-, and 5-year-old Shuar children from the Amazon region of Ecuador. The Shuar are hunter-horticulturalists who are on the verge of the transition to a peasant, cash economy. Children live in a rural, forest environment where they have frequent encounters with live animals as well as animals being killed for food. Our German sample included city-dwelling children who

Data coding and analysis

In the analyses reported below we used percent correct measures, where percent correct for sleep questions is computed by dividing the number of “yes” responses by the total number of questions answered, and percent correct for death questions is computed by dividing the number of “no” responses by the total number of questions answered. Overall percent correct measures summed “yes” responses on sleep questions and “no” responses on death questions and divided by the total number of questions

Discussion

These results support the hypothesis that children understand death as the cessation of the ability to act by age 4. By this age, providing causal information about death significantly and systematically changes the pattern of inferences children make about an animal. Agency attributions to dead animals are blocked, whereas attributions to sleeping animals are not. On our task, we found a reliable developmental trajectory that is the same across populations and conditions. That the

Conclusion

The results of this study support the hypothesis that death understanding is subserved by reliably developing, evolved mechanisms that enable children to distinguish between objects that are capable of acting and objects that are not, and to make inferences about each. That such an inference system exists makes sense if one considers that in ancestral environments, children's survival is likely to have depended on their abilities to reason about the consequences of interacting with various

Acknowledgements

This paper is based in part on a presentation at the 2001 Meetings of the Cognitive Science Society, Edinburgh, Scotland. This research was funded in part by a travel grant from the Max Planck Institute for Human Development. Thanks to Martie Haselton, Rob Kurzban, members of the Center for Adaptive Behavior and Cognition at the Max Planck Institute for Human Development, the Max Planck Institute for Evolutionary Anthropology, the UCLA Center for Behavior, Evolution, and Culture, and the UCLA

References (31)

  • S.B. Brent et al.

    The development of the concept of death among Chinese and U.S. children from 3–17 years of age: From binary to fuzzy concepts?

    Omega

    (1996)
  • S. Carey

    Conceptual change in childhood

    (1985)
  • K.G. Dolgin et al.

    Children's knowledge about animates and inanimates

    Child Development

    (1984)
  • Gelman, S. A., & Opfer, J. E. (2002). Development of the animate–inanimate distinction. In: U. Goswami (Ed.), Handbook...
  • A. Gopnik et al.

    Words, thoughts, and theories

    (1997)
  • Cited by (80)

    • Responses to Death

      2019, Encyclopedia of Animal Behavior, Second Edition: Volume 1-5
    • Responses to death

      2019, Encyclopedia of Animal Behavior
    • Some consequences of normal aging for generating conceptual explanations: A case study of vitalist biology

      2017, Cognitive Psychology
      Citation Excerpt :

      When asked what it means to die, they often respond that it means to stop doing things or to become invisible or simply to go away. Some children understand death as the end of existence—but not the end of life (Barrett & Behne, 2005; Carey, 1985). Finally, and not surprisingly, young children know little about the workings of the body.

    View all citing articles on Scopus
    View full text