Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-9pm4c Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T17:37:31.924Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Semantic Eliminativism and the Theory-Theory of Linguistic Understanding

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Get access

Extract

Suppose, familiarly, that you and a friend have landed in an alien territory, amidst people who speak a language you do not know. Upon seeing you, one of them starts yelling, seemingly alarmed. You say to your friend, “She thinks we want to hurt her. She's scared. We must seem very strange to her.” Your friend, who is facing you, says, “No, I think she's actually trying to warn you: there's a snake right above your head, on that tree. You see the sling in her hand? I think she's going to try to shoot it down.“

On a prevalent view, much discussed in recent years, you and your friend have engaged in a mini-theoretical enterprise. Using certain observations of the alien's behaviour as your data, and deploying certain generalizations and principles concerning human behaviour, you advance hypotheses regarding the internal psychological states which issued in her observed behaviour.

Type
Part B: Language and Mind
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 2004

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bar-On, D. 1986. “Semantic Indeterminacy and Scientific Underdetermination.Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 67: 245-63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bar-On, D. 1990. “Scepticism: The External World and Meaning.Philosophical Studies 60: 207-31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bar-On, D. 1992a. “On the Possibility of a Solitary Language.Noûs 26:27-46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bar-On, D. 1992b. “Semantic Verificationism, Linguistic Behaviorism, and Translation.Philosophical Studies 66: 95119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bar-On, D. 1993. “Indeterminacy of Translation: Theory and Practice.Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53: 781810.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bar-On, D. 1996. “Anti-Realism and Speaker Knowledge.Synthèse 106: 139-66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bar-On, D. 1997. “'Natural’ Semantic Facts-Between Eliminativism and HyperRealism.“ In The Maribor Papers in Naturalized Semantics, ed. Jutronic, D.99117. Maribor: Pedagoska Faculteta Maribor.Google Scholar
Bar-On, D. and Risjord, M. 1992. “Is There Such a Thing as a Language?Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22: 163-90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barrett, R. and Gibson, R. eds. 1990. Perspectives on Quine. Oxford and Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Bennett, J. 1976. Linguistic Behavior. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Blackburn, S. 1995. “Theory, Observation, and Drama.” Reprinted in M. Davies and T. Stone 1995a, 274-90.Google Scholar
Burge, T. 1979. “Individualism and the Mental.Midwest Studies in Philosophy 4, 73-122 Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carruthers, P. and Smith, P. K. eds. 1996. Theories of Theories of Mind. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1957. Syntactic Structures. The Hague: Mouton.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1965. Aspects of the Theory of Syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1972. Language and Mind. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1975a. “Quine's Empirical Assumptions.” In Words and Objections, ed. Davidson and Harman, 5368. Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1975b. Reflections on Language. New York: Pantheon.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1980. Rules and Representations. New York: Columbia University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1982. The Generative Enterprise. Dordrecht: Foris.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1986. Knowledge of Language: Its Nature, Origin, and Use. New York: Praeger.Google Scholar
Paul, Churchland 1988. Matter and Consciousness (revised edition). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. 1986. A Nice Derangement of Epitaphs. In Truth and Interpretation, ed. Lepore, E.433-46. Oxford and Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. 1990. “The Structure and Content of Truth.The Journal of Philosophy 87: 279328.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davies, M. and Stone, T. eds. 1995a. Folk Psychology: The Theory of Mind Debate. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Davies, M. and Stone, T. eds. 1995b. Mental Simulation. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Devitt, M. 1991. Realism and Truth (2nd ed.). Oxford and Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Devitt, M. 1996. Coming to Our Senses. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Devitt, M. and Sterelny, K. 1989. “What is Wrong with ‘the Right View.“’ In Philosophical Perspectives 3, ed. Tomberlin, J.497581. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview.Google Scholar
Dummett, M. 1991. The Logical Basis of Metaphysics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. 1968. Psychological Explanation. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. 1975. The Language of Thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. 1994. The Elm and The Expert. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. 1998. Concepts: Where Cognitive Science Went Wrong. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. and Lepore, E. 1992. Holism. Oxford and Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Follesdal, D. 1990. Indeterminacy and Mental States. In Barrett and Gibson 1990, 98109.Google Scholar
George, A. ed. 1989. Reflections on Chomsky. Oxford and Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1966. “An Argument for the Identity Theory.The Journal of Philosophy 63: 1725.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mark, Platts 1979. The Ways of Meaning. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1975. “The Meaning of ‘Meaning'.” In Mind, Language and Reality, 215271. Cambridge MA: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W.V. 1960. Word and Object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Quine, W.V. 1969. Ontological Relativity and Other Essays. New York: Columbia University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W.V. 1970. “Philosophical Progress in Language Theory.Metaphilosophy 1: 219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W.V. 1974. The Roots of Reference. La Salle, Ill.: Open Court.Google Scholar
Quine, W.V. 1976. The Ways of Paradox and Other Essays (revised and enlarged edition). Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Quine, W.V. 1986. “Reply to Alston.” In The Philosophy of W. V. Quine, ed. Hahn, L.E. and Schilpp, P.A.7375. La Salle, Ill.: Open Court.Google Scholar
Quine, W.V. 1987. “Indeterminacy of Translation Again.Journal of Philosophy 84: 511.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W.V. 1990. Pursuit of Truth. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ramberg, B. 1989. Donald Davidson's Philosophy of Language. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Stich, S. 1983. From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science. Cambridge and London: A Bradford Book; MIT Press.Google Scholar
Stich, S. 1996. Deconstructing the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Stjernberg, F. 1991. The Public Nature of Meaning. Stockholm: Almqvist & Wiksell International (doctoral dissertation).Google Scholar