Skip to main content
Log in

The curious case of spacetime emergence

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Work in quantum gravity suggests that spacetime is not fundamental. Rather, spacetime emerges from an underlying, non-spatiotemporal reality. After clarifying the type of emergence at issue, I argue that standard conceptions of emergence available in metaphysics won’t work for the emergence of spacetime. I go on to consider spacetime functionalism as a way to make sense of spacetime emergence. I argue that a functionalist approach to spacetime modelled on mental state functionalism is not a viable alternative to the standard conception of emergence in metaphysics. I go on to consider an alternative: ‘partial’ functionalism, whereby certain aspects of spacetime are functionalised, rather than spacetime as a whole.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For discussion, see Anderson (2012), Bain (2013), Barbour (1999), Butterfield and Isham (1999), Kuchar (1992), Oriti (2014), Rovelli (2004).

  2. Wave-function realism interpretations of quantum mechanics also appear to lack spacetime. For discussion see Maudlin (2007), Ney (2015).

  3. Causation is usually thought to be a relation between events, which are individuated by their spatiotemporal locations. Baron and Miller (2014), Tallant (2018) argue that causation without time is possible. However, the resulting notion of causation may not be sufficient for observation [see Braddon-Mitchell and Miller (2019)].

  4. Braddon-Mitchell and Miller (2019), Healey (2002), Huggett and Wüthrich (2013) and Maudlin (2007), all raise a version of this problem, though aimed at different theories in each case.

  5. See, for example, Bain (2013), Butterfield and Isham (1999), Crowther (2016, 2017), Huggett and Wüthrich (2013), Rovelli (2004), Wüthrich (forthcoming).

  6. A number of philosophers suggest that there is a non-causal, mathematical style of explanation that plays a substantive role in scientific explanation. Gravitational explanations and geometric explanations are often cited as examples, see Colyvan (2001, pp. 50–52).

  7. It may be false for strong emergence, see Barnes (2012).

  8. One might argue that some approaches cannot be understood in compositional terms, such as Hu’s (1999) account of emergent gravity, and so we shouldn’t try to capture quantum gravity inside this framework. However, note that Hu appears to characterise his own emergent gravity program in compositional terms (of course we would need to look at the details):

    Something assumed to be ‘elementary’ at a lower energy or with a coarser resolution at one time will later be found to be a composite at a higher energy or under a finer resolution... Constructing the macroscopic structure and dynamics from known microscopic constituents is often easier, such as getting hydrodynamics from molecular dynamics. Going the other way, i.e., deducing molecular features from hydrodynamics, is more difficult. For spacetime structures, the former is the task of emergent gravity, the latter is the goal of quantum gravity. (Hu 2009, p. 3)

    Moreover, even if the compositional approach is a non-starter for Hu’s view, the causal sets approach and loop quantum gravity appear to posit physical entities at high energy scales that could potentially compose entities at low energies.

  9. Wüthrich (forthcoming), Lam and Wüthrich (2018) and Ney (2015) object to mereology as a basis for spacetime emergence.

  10. I am grateful to an anonymous referee for raising this issue.

  11. Braddon-Mitchell and Miller (2006, pp. 224–225) also argue that the concept of a part breaks down when STP is falsified.

  12. Le Bihan (2017) makes this suggestion.

  13. One option that has been suggested to me by a referee for this journal is to look more carefully at Causal Set Theory. Like LQG, Causal Set Theory, lacks fundamental spacetime (see Huggett and Wüthrich 2013). Nonetheless, the basic elements of Causal Set Theory do seem to be isomorphic to a part-whole structure of some kind. I lack the space to consider this option here, but I agree broadly that causal set theory provides a more natural basis for developing a notion of parthood* and a mereological conception of spacetime emergence.

  14. Ney (2015) briefly argues against the use of spacetime functionalism as the basis for emergence. The argument I will present goes beyond the cursory remarks that Ney makes, but is broadly similar in spirit.

  15. I am grateful to two anonymous referees for pressing me on this issue.

  16. For example, Bilson-Thompson’s (2005) braid model of particles, which has been combined with LQG and spin-foam theories (see Bilson-Thompson et al. 2012, 2009, 2007).

References

  • Anderson, E. (2012). Problem of time in quantum gravity. Annalen der Physik, 524, 757–786.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bain, J. (2013). The emergence of spacetime in condensed matter approaches to quantum gravity. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 44, 338–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barbour, J. (1999). The End of Time. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, E. (2012). Emergence and fundamentality. Mind, 121, 873–901.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron, S., & Miller, K. (2014). Causation in a timeless world. Synthese, 191, 2867–2886.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, J. A. (1999). The quantum mechanics of minds and worlds. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bilson-Thompson, S., Hackett, J., & Kauffman, L. (2009). Particle topology, braids and braided belts. Journal of Mathematical Physscs, 50, 113505.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bilson-Thompson, S., Hackett, J., Kauffman, L., & Wan, Y. (2012). Emergent braided matter of quantum geometry. SIGMA, 8, 14–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bilson-Thompson, S. O. (2005). A topological model of composite preons. https://arxiv.org/abs/hep-ph/0503213.

  • Bilson-Thompson, S. O., Markopolou, F., & Smolin, L. (2007). Quantum gravity and the standard model. Classical and Quantum Gravity, 24, 3975.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braddon-Mitchell, D., & Miller, K. (2006). The physics of extended simples. Analysis, 66, 222–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braddon-Mitchell, D., & Miller, K. (2019). Quantum gravity, timelessness and the contents of thought. Philosophical Studies, 179(7), 1807–1829.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butterfield, J., & Isham, C. (1999). On the emergence of time in quantum gravity. In The arguments of time (pp. 111–168). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Colyvan, M. (2001). The indispensability of mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Crowther, K. (2016). Effective spacetime: Understanding emergence in effective field theory and quantum gravity. Heidelberg: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Crowther, K. (2018). Inter-theory relations in quantum gravity: Correspondence, reduction, and emergence. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 63, 74–85.

  • de Haan, J. (2006). How emergence arises. Ecological Complexity, 3, 293–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, T. E. (2001). Why the mind is not a radically emergent feature of the brain. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8, 123–145.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilmore, C. (2018). Location and mereology. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.) Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/location-mereology/. Accessed 1 June 2019.

  • Healey, R. (2002). Can physics coherently deny the reality of time? In C. Callender (Ed.), Time, Reality & Experience (pp. 293–316). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hu, B.-L. (1999). Stochastic gravity. International Journal of Theoretical Physics, 38(11), 2987–3037.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hu, B.-L. (2009). Emergent/quantum gravity: Macro/micro structures of spacetime. Journal of Physics: Conference Series, 174, 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huggett, N., & Wüthrich, C. (2013). Emergent spacetime and empirical (in)coherence. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 44, 276–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys, P. (1997). How properties emerge. Philosophy of Science, 64, 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1999). Making sense of emergence. Philosophical Studies, 95, 3–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knox, E. (2017). Physical relativity from a functionalist perspective. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsb.2017.09.008.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuchar, K. V. (1992). Canonical quantum gravity. In R. J. Gleiser, C. N. Kozameh & O. M. Moreschi (Eds.), General relativity and gravitation 1992: Proceedings of the 13th international conference on general relativity and gravitation (pp. 119–150). Bristol: Institute of Physics Publishing.

  • Lam, V., & Esfeld, M. (2013). A dilemma for the emergence of spacetime in canonical quantum gravity. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 44, 286–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lam, V., & Wüthrich, C. (2018). Spacetime is as spacetime does. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 64, 39–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Le Bihan, B. (2017). Priority monism beyond spacetime. Metaphysica. https://doi.org/10.1515/mp-2018-0005.

  • Markosian, N. (2014). A spatial approach to mereology. In S. Kleinshmidt (Ed.), Mereology and Location. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin, T. (2007). Completeness, supervenience and ontology. Journal of Physics A: Mathematical and Theoretical, 40, 3151–3171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ney, A. (2015). Fundamental physical ontologies and the constraint of empirical coherence: A defense of wave function realism. Synthese, 192, 3105–3124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oriti, D. (2014). Disappearance and emergence of space and time in quantum gravity. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 46, 186–199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, J. (2007). Theories of location. In Oxford studies in metaphysics (Vol. 3, pp. 201–232). Oxford University Press.

  • Paul, L. A. (2002). Logical parts. Noûs, 36, 578–596.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paul, L. A. (2012). Building the world from its fundamental constituents. Philosophical Studies, 158, 221–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reuger, A. (2000). Physical emergence, diachronic and synchronic. Synthese, 124, 297–322.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rovelli, C. (2004). Quantum gravity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2007). Parthood. Philosophical Review, 116, 51–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tallant, J. (2018). Causation in a timeless world? Inquiry. https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174X.2018.1446051.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Cleve, J. (1990). Mind-dust or magic? Pansychism versus emergence. Philosophical Perspectives, 4, 215–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Gulick, R. (2001). Reduction, emergence and other recent options on the mind/body problem: A philosophic overview. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8, 1–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, J. (2016). Metaphysical emergence: Weak and strong. In T. Bigaj & C. Wüthrich (Eds.), Metaphysics in contemporary physics (pp. 345–402). Leiden: Brill.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wüthrich, C. (forthcoming). The emergence of space and time. In S. Gibb, R. F. Hendry & T. Lancaster (Eds.), Routledge handbook of emergence. Routledge.

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to two anonymous referees for their immensely helpful feedback on the paper. Earlier versions of this paper were presented at the CPT/FraMEPhys Workshop on Time and Explanation held at the University of Milan and the First International Workshop on Time held at Osaka City University. I am grateful to audiences at both workshops for their feedback on the paper, and am especially grateful to Alastair Wilson for hosting the Milan workshop and Takeshi Sakon for hosting the Osaka workshop. Work on this paper was funded by an Australian Research Council Discovery Early Career Researcher Award DE180100414 and a Discovery Project DP180100105.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sam Baron.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Baron, S. The curious case of spacetime emergence. Philos Stud 177, 2207–2226 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-019-01306-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-019-01306-z

Keywords

Navigation