Skip to main content
Log in

Horizontal Surgicality and Mechanistic Constitution

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

While ideal (surgical) interventions are acknowledged by many as valuable tools for the analysis of causation, recent discussions have shown that, since there are no ideal interventions on upper-level phenomena that non-reductively supervene on their underlying mechanisms, interventions cannot—contrary to a popular opinion—ground an informative analysis of constitution. This has led some to abandon the project of analyzing constitution in interventionist terms. By contrast, this paper defines the notion of a horizontally surgical intervention, and argues that, when combined with some innocuous metaphysical principles about the relation between upper and lower levels of mechanisms, that notion delivers a sufficient condition for constitution. This, in turn, strengthens the case for an interventionist analysis of constitution.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The terms “constitution” and “constitutive relevance” are sometimes used with differing meanings: single constituents are constitutively relevant to the phenomenon while only the whole lower-level mechanism constitutes it. For ease of expression, we use the terms synonymously here, meaning that “\(\Phi \) constitutes \(\Psi \)” is to be understood in terms of “\(\Phi \)is a constituent (among possibly many) of \(\Psi \)”.

  2. In a recent Stanford Encyclopedia entry, Craver (Craver and Tabery 2017, sect. 3.2) seems to acknowledge the difficulties in applying Woodward’s interventionism to mechanistic systems. However, in an even more recent online presentation (Craver 2018), Craver insists that the problems merely concern the formulation of MM in Craver (2007) and not the theory’s content.

  3. One author (BK) of this paper argues that MM may be saved if the phenomenon is represented by multiple variables standing for different temporal phases of the phenomenon (Krickel 2018).

  4. A cause I of X is a fat-handed intervention on X w.r.t. Y when it violates condition (I3) of Woodward’s (2003, p. 98) definition of an ideal intervention, such that I causes Yalong two (or more) different paths (cf. Scheines 2005, pp. 931–932). The contrast class of fat-handed interventions is the class of surgical interventions. Notice that the distinction between surgical and fat-handed interventions is orthogonal to that between structural and parametric interventions (Eberhardt and Scheines 2007, pp. 986–987), namely between interventions that, respectively, do and do not satisfy condition (I2).

  5. It is a common (often implicit) background assumption in the mechanistic literature that the relata of constitution are not gerrymandered behaviors, even though this assumption is not underwritten by an explicit criterion for gerrymanderedness (Franklin-Hall 2016, §5). We, too, assume that all analyzed variables represent non-gerrymandered behaviors and that it is pre-theoretically clear what gerrymanderedness amounts to.

  6. Note that this spatiotemporal notion of a level is merely instrumental for our ensuing argument; it is not intended as a contribution to the ongoing debate on levels in the mechanistic literature nor, in particular, as an alternative to Craver’s (2007, p. 189) or Bechtel’s (2008, p. 146) notions of a level.

  7. A similar point is made by Eronen and Brooks (2014), without the terminology of fat-handedness.

  8. Notice, however, that Woodward (2015) does not modify the notion of an intervention for the purpose of testing for constitution but rather for the purpose of testing for causation in variable sets including supervenience relations.

  9. The behaviors represented by \({\Phi }^k_i\) and \({\Phi }^h_j\) differ either because they involve different entities or different activities, that is, either because of \(i\ne j\) or because of \(h\ne k\).

  10. Relative to a different interpretation of the variables in the reductio, the resulting contradiction can, of course, also be resolved by rejecting (2) and upholding (1). If \({\Phi }^k_i\) is interpreted to stand for neural activity and not for oxygenation, \({\Phi }^k_i\) turns out to be a constituent of \({\Psi }\), meaning that assumption (2) has to go.

References

  • Baumgartner, M., & Casini, L. (2017). An abductive theory of constitution. Philosophy of Science, 84(2), 214–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baumgartner, M., & Gebharter, A. (2016). Constitutive relevance, mutual manipulability, and fat-handedness. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 67(3), 731–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2008). Mental mechanisms. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Couch, M. B. (2011). Mechanisms and constitutive relevance. Synthese, 183, 375–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2007). Explaining the brain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2018). Mutual manipulability redux [Video File]. Retrieved from https://youtu.be/PS-LSrIWeFo.

  • Craver, C. F., & Bechtel, W. (2007). Top-down causation without top-down causes. Biology and Philosophy, 22, 547–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F., & Tabery, J. (2017). Mechanisms in science. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2017 ed.). Stanford: Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eberhardt, F., & Scheines, R. (2007). Interventions and causal inference. Philosophy of Science, 74, 981–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eronen, M. I. (2011). Reduction in philosophy of mind: A pluralistic account. Frankfurt am Main: Ontos.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Eronen, M. I. (2013). No levels, no problems: Downward causation in neuroscience. Philosophy of Science, 80(5), 1042–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eronen, M. I., & Brooks, D. S. (2014). Interventionism and supervenience: A new problem and provisional solution. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 22(2), 185–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franklin-Hall, L. R. (2016). New mechanistic explanation and the need for explanatory constraints. In K. Aizawa & C. Gillett (Eds.), Scientific composition and metaphysical ground: New directions in the philosophy of science (Chap. 2). London: Springer.

  • Gebharter, A. (2017). Uncovering constitutive relevance relations in mechanisms. Philosophical Studies, 174, 2645–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. (1996). Mechanisms and the nature of causation. Erkenntnis, 44, 49–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harbecke, J. (2010). Mechanistic constitution in neurobiological explanations. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 24, 267–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harbecke, J. (2015). The regularity theory of mechanistic constitution and a methodology for constitutive inference. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 54, 10–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Irvine, E. (2013). Consciousness as a scientific concept. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. M. (2012). How to demarcate the boundaries of cognition. Biology and Philosophy, 27, 545–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krickel, B. (2018). Saving the mutual manipulability account of constitutive relevance. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 68, 58–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leuridan, B. (2012). Three problems for the mutual manipulability account of constitutive relevance in mechanisms. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 63, 399–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin, T. (2002). Quantum non-locality and relativity. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Romero, F. (2015). Why there isn’t inter-level causation in mechanisms. Synthese, 192(11), 3731–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheines, R. (2005). The similarity of causal inference in experimental and non-experimental studies. Philosophy of Science, 72(5), 927–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spirtes, P., Glymour, C., & Scheines, R. (2000). Causation, prediction, and search (2nd ed.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spohn, W. (2006). Causation: An alternative. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57, 93–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Eck, D., & de Jong, H. L. (2016). Mechanistic explanation, cognitive systems demarcation, and extended cognition. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 59, 11–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen. A theory of causal explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2015). Interventionism and causal exclusion. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 91, 303–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J., & Hausman, D. (1999). Independence, invariance and the causal Markov condition. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 50(4), 521–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zednik, C. (2015). Heuristics, descriptions, and the scope of mechanistic explanation. In C. Malaterre & P.-A. Braillard (Eds.), Explanation in biology: An enquiry into the diversity of explanatory patterns in the life sciences (pp. 295–318). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We thank the participants to the Biological Interest Group of the University of Geneva, 21 February 2017, and the audiences of BSPS, Edinburgh, 13 July 2017, and SMS, New York, 5 October 2017. This research was generously supported by the Swiss National Science Foundation, Grants Nos. 100017_169810 and 100012E_160866/1 for LC and Grant No. PP00P1_144736/1 for MB. MB is moreover indebted to the Toppforsk-programme of the Bergen Research Foundation and the University of Bergen, Grant No. 811886. BK was supported by the DFG-Graduiertenkolleg “Situated Cognition”, GRK-2185/1.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lorenzo Casini.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Baumgartner, M., Casini, L. & Krickel, B. Horizontal Surgicality and Mechanistic Constitution. Erkenn 85, 417–430 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-018-0033-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-018-0033-5

Navigation