Skip to main content
Log in

Physical Intentionality, Extrinsicness, and the Direction of Causation

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The Physical Intentionality Thesis claims that dispositions share the marks of psychological intentionality; therefore, intentionality is not exclusively a mental phenomenon. Beyond the standard five marks, Alexander Bird introduces two additional marks of intentionality that he argues dispositions do not satisfy: first, thoughts are extrinsic; second, the direction of causation is that objects cause thoughts, not vice versa. In response, this paper identifies two relevant conceptions of extrinsicness, arguing that dispositions show deep parallels to thoughts on both conceptions. Then, it shows that Bird’s discussion of direction of causation overlooks complexities of dispositionality and intentionality that problematize apparent differences between thoughts and dispositions. The paper ends with a discussion of why we find these parallels between thoughts and dispositions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Brentano (1874) initiated current discussion of intentionality, picking up the thread from medieval philosophers.

  2. These philosophers disagree over the degree to which physical and psychological phenomena compare in terms of intentionality, as well as over the implications of the Physical Intentionality Thesis—for instance, over whether it means that we need a new criterion to separate the psychological and the physical.

  3. The strong version of this thesis is that physical and psychological intentionality are identical, while the weak version is that they are strongly analogous. These two interpretations are found in Molnar (2003: 61, 81), who appears to hold the weaker version (Molnar 2003: 186). The authors mentioned above may disagree about which version of the thesis is accurate. The formulation here captures the idea that dispositions and thoughts share the essential marks of intentionality but stops short of claiming identity, as the former is sufficient for purposes here.

  4. First, these five marks were used by Martin and Pfeifer (1986) in arguing that intentionality is the mark of the dispositional, not the mental, to the effect that we need a different conception of intentionality that marks off the mental from the dispositional. By contrast, Place (1996) and Molnar (2003) argue that we should simply accept intentionality as the mark of the dispositional. Second, the marks are culled from a variety of sources, as Place (1996) clarifies, to include Anscombe (1965), Chisholm (1957), and Searle (1979). Third, the term “referential opacity” derives from Quine (1953), and Chisholm (1957) uses that phrase in employing it as a mark of intentionality. Fourth, the last two marks pertain to linguistic phenomena. Place (1996), for one, argues that the intensional (with an “s”) criteria are not relevant to the Physical Intentionality Thesis. Fifth, Bird (2007: 119) condenses these five marks into four, by incorporating Lack of Truth Import as a corollary of Intentional Inexistence.

  5. Bird (2007: 8) holds that the natural properties are universals; however, the natural/non-natural properties distinction is compatible with the claim that “natural properties are classes of perfectly resembling tropes” (2007: 9).

  6. Bird (2007: 45, footnote 40) notes that potencies are what some others, e.g., Molnar (2003), call “powers.” Bird prefers neither the term “disposition” nor “power” since these might refer to properties that do not have dispositional essences, i.e., “potencies”. Also, Bird (2013) argues that we should distinguish between powers and dispositions.

  7. Bird (2007: 29) affirms the claim of Lewis (1997: 148) that “If two things (actual or merely possible) are exact intrinsic duplicates (and if they are subject to the same laws of nature) then they are disposed alike.”

  8. Putnam (1973, 1975) forms the twin-earth thought experiment, and Davidson (1987) forms the swamp-man thought experiment. Although this paper assumes that externalism is true, and it remains more popular than internalism (Bourget and Chalmers 2014), it has faced recent substantial criticism (e.g., Mendola 2009).

  9. Bauer (2011: 82–86) distinguishes between a property being extrinsic and being extrinsically grounded (in a non-intentionality context), which is similar to the distinction being advanced here.

  10. These considerations are also relevant to the mark of Directedness, but that is not being evaluated here. Some of these considerations are also relevant to Direction, which is addressed in Section 4.

  11. This observation involves the phenomenon of Intentional Inexistence, one of the original five criteria of intentionality. It is assumed here, insofar as it is relevant to the relation picked out by Extrinsic, that dispositions plausibly share this mark in an analogous form with beliefs and thoughts.

  12. Priority monism contrasts with blobjectivism (Horgan and Potrč 2008), which holds that the whole world or the blobject is the only genuine concrete individual object. Derivatives such as stars, planets, organisms, and particles are objects in name only, ontologically mere confluences of properties of the blobject. If blobjectivism is true, it would appear that all properties are intrinsic, if properties are properly possessed only by objects.

  13. Interestingly, the plausibility that all parts of the world are unified may be enhanced by the dispositional view found in Martin (2008), which in turn meshes with the dispositional monism of Bird (2007) (although Bird is concerned only with sparse dispositions, as noted already, whereas Martin’s view concerns all dispositions). Martin (2008: 29) posits the existence of a network of interrelated dispositions: each disposition is “projective for endless manifestations with an infinity of present or absent, actual or nonactual alternative disposition partners.” Each disposition requires a partner to manifest on Martin’s view (e.g., to manifest in breaking, a vase’s fragility requires a triggering disposition, like a hammer’s hardness), but there are an infinite number of potential partners and ways of manifesting—a “complex line” (Martin 2008: 29) of dispositions, what Martin (1993) calls a “Power Net.” Given the array of dispositional partners, there is a network of dispositions connected by their possible interactions. So Martin’s Power Net implies interconnectedness between all dispositions, thus suggesting the unification afforded by Schaffer’s priority monism (it is not meant to be implied that Schaffer would accept any dispositionalist interpretation of unity and interconnectedness that supports priority monism).

  14. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for recommending these lines of reasoning for priority monism.

  15. For more information, visit the CERN page: http://home.web.cern.ch/topics/higgs-boson (accessed November 21, 2015).

  16. This conclusion applies to both inertial mass and rest mass, since these are physically equivalent according to Einstein’s equivalence principle.

  17. “Objects” could be “particles”; “intentions” or “intentional character” could be “aboutness” or “directedness”; and “properties” could be “sub-properties” if the various marks of intentionality are sub-properties of the intentional or dispositional state itself.

  18. The passage mentions “intentional character,” so the complete truth of the passage assumes that dispositions meet the other marks needed to have an intentional character.

  19. Supposing that thoughts should fit events or properties in the world, there is a direction to the fit. This refers to which side (mind or world) gets privileged. Beliefs have a mind-to-world direction of fit, wherein the belief should match the world: if the fit is good, the belief is true. By contrast, desires have a world-to-mind direction of fit, wherein the world should match the desire: if the fit is good, the desire is fulfilled. Some thoughts arguably have null fit, as Searle (2004: 169) explains: being “glad that the sun is shining” presupposes a direction of fit, and therefore, there is no question of whether the fit is good or bad. See Searle (1983, 2004) for further discussion.

  20. If the arguments in Section 3.3 show that sparse dispositions satisfy Extrinsic-G, then something extrinsic to the object bearing a sparse disposition grounds the disposition. This grounding relation is similar, but not identical, to something external causing the object to have a sparse disposition; Schaffer (2016) argues that the concept of grounding is strongly analogous to that of causation. Despite this similarity, in this case, it would still not be the manifestation, Y, causing the disposition, X, and thus, it would not fit the form of Direction. In the arguments in Section 3, the point of interest was the parallel between sparse dispositions and thoughts in which something extrinsic, not necessarily the object of the intentional state, grounds the intentional state (or disposition).

  21. There are many examples in which an intentional state and a dispositional state are closely associated, as in the chocolate example.

  22. The identity hypothesis, it is worth noting, does not beg the question against Bird’s view. Rather it is simply an alternative explanation of the relevant phenomenon.

  23. It is assumed that dispositions are causally relevant or can play causal roles in events. Martin (2008) defends the idea that all causes reduce to dispositions—a cause is just a disposition or set of intersecting disposition “lines”. McKitrick (2005) argues that dispositions are causally relevant. Mumford and Anjum (2011) extensively defend causal dispositionalism, the idea that effects are the products of manifesting powers.

  24. Bird actually gives three accounts of intentionality and explains how none of them entail that intentionality is compositional, evaluation of which is not the purpose of this paper.

References

  • Anscombe, G.E.M. (1965). The intentionality of sensation: a grammatical feature. In Ronald J. Butler (Ed.), Analytical Philosophy: Second Series, Blackwell: 158–180.

  • Armstrong, D. (2004). Truth and truthmakers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bauer, W. (2011). An argument for the extrinsic grounding of mass. Erkenntnis: An International Journal of Scientific Philosophy, 74(1), 81–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2007). Nature’s metaphysics: laws and properties. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2013). Limitations of power. In J. Greco and R. Groff (Eds.), Powers and Capacities in Philosophy: The New Aristotelianism (pp. 15–47). Routledge.

  • Bourget, D., & Chalmers, D. J. (2014). What do philosophers believe? Philosophical Studies, 170(3), 465–500.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1874). In L. L. McAllister (Ed.), Psychology from an empirical standpoint. Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press. 1973.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R. (1957). Perceiving: a philosophical study. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. and Chalmers, D. J. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58(1), 7–19.

  • Davidson, D. (1987). Knowing one’s own mind. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 60, 441–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (2001). Scientific essentialism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (2002). The philosophy of nature: a guide to the new essentialism. Chesham: Acumen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B., & Lierse, C. (1994). Dispositional essentialism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 72(1), 27–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitch, W. T. (2008). Nano-intentionality: a defense of intrinsic intentionality. Biology and Philosophy, 23(2), 157–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gross, D. J. (1996). The role of symmetry in fundamental physics. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 93, 14256–14259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heil, J. (2003). From an ontological point of view. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heil, J. (2012). The universe as we find it. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T., & Potrč, M. (2008). Austere realism: contextual semantics meets minimal ontology. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1748). An enquiry concerning human understanding. In E. A. Burtt (Ed.), The English philosophers: from bacon to mill (pp. 611–721). New York: Modern Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Isaacs, A. (2000). Oxford dictionary of physics (4th ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langton, R., & Lewis, D. (1998). Defining ‘intrinsic’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 58(2), 333–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986a). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986b). Introduction. Philosophical Papers, vol. II. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Reprinted in Lange 2007: 322–4. All citations refer to the reprinted version.)

  • Lewis, D. (1989). Dispositional theories of value. The Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 63, 113–137.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1997). Finkish dispositions. Philosophical Quarterly, 47, 143–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C. B., & Pfeifer, K. (1986). Intentionality and the non-psychological. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 46, 531–554.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C. B. (1993). Power for realists. Ontology, causality, and mind: essays in honour of D. M. Armstrong. J. Bacon, K. Campbell and L. Reinhardt (Eds.), Dordrecht: Kluwer: 175–186.

  • Martin, C. B. (2008). The mind in nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKitrick, J. (2003). A case for extrinsic dispositions. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 81(2), 155–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKitrick, J. (2005). Are dispositions causally relevant? Synthese, 144, 357–371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mendola, J. (2009). Anti-externalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Molnar, G. (2003). Powers: a study in metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S. (1999). Intentionality and the physical: a new theory of disposition ascription. The Philosophical Quarterly, 49(195), 215–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S. (2006). The ungrounded argument. Synthese, 149, 471–489.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S., & Anjum, R. L. (2011). Getting causes from powers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Place, U. T. (1996). Intentionality as the mark of the dispositional. Dialectica, 50(2), 91–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2005). Towards non-being: the logic and metaphysics of intentionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The Meaning of ‘Meaning’. In Philosophical Papers, Vol. 2: Mind, Language and Reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Putnam, H. (1973). Meaning and reference. Journal of Philosophy, 70, 699–711.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1953). Reference and modality. In From a Logical Point of View. Second Edition, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press: 139–159.

  • Quiroga, R. Q., Reddy, L., Kreiman, G., Koch, C., & Fried, I. (2005). Invariant visual representation by single neurons in the human brain. Nature, 435, 1102–1107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Randall, L. (2005). Warped passages: unravelling the mysteries of the universe’s hidden dimensions. New York: HarperCollins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1963). The concept of mind. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2010a). The internal relatedness of all things. Mind, 119(474), 341–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2010b). Monism: the priority of the whole. Philosophical Review, 119(1), 31–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2016). Grounding in the image of causation. Philosophical Studies, 173(1), 49–100.

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2001). In-between believing. The Philosophical Quarterly, 51(202), 76–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2002). A phenomenal, dispositional account of belief. Noûs, 36(2), 249–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1979). What is an intentional state? Mind, 88, 74–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1983). Intentionality: an essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (2004). Mind: a brief introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skrbina, D. (2005). Panpsychism in the West. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Strawson, G. (2006). Consciousness and its place in nature: does physicalism entail panpsychism? A. Freeman (Ed.) Exeter: Imprint Academic.

  • Yablo, S. (1999). Intrinsicness. Philosophical Topics, 26, 590–627.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for extremely helpful, detailed comments and suggestions concerning multiple aspects of this paper. Thanks also to participants at a meeting of the Alabama Philosophical Society (October 2, 2015) for discussion of ideas in section 4.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to William A. Bauer.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bauer, W.A. Physical Intentionality, Extrinsicness, and the Direction of Causation. Acta Anal 31, 397–417 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-016-0283-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-016-0283-2

Keywords

Navigation