Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-x5gtn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-24T04:57:56.555Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Literary Examples and Philosophical Confusion

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 January 2010

Extract

It is by no means unusual in works of philosophy for writers to make use of examples from literature or (like e.g. Peter Winch and Eugene Kamenka) to bemoan the lack of literary examples in the work of other philosophers. Nor is it unusual for philosophers to write substantial tomes without ever mentioning any work of literature or (like R. M. Hare and C. W. K. Mundle) to condemn the use of literary examples as a threat to clarity of thought. This contradiction in practice and principle might lead us to suspect that what we are here dealing with is at least to some extent a philosophical disagreement, and I believe this to be the case. Unfortunately, what is extremely unusual is any direct discussion of the philosophical issues involved, that is to say any discussion of what philosophers are doing when they appeal in their writings to works of literature, and of what if anything is lost by those who fail to do so.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 1983

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 ‘The Universalisability of Moral Judgments’, The Monist 49, 199200.Google Scholar

2 Marxism and Ethics, (Macmillan), 35.Google Scholar

3 Freedom and Reason, (Oxford University Press), 183Google Scholar and Moral Thinking, (Oxford University Press), 4749.Google Scholar

4 A Critique of Linguistic Philosophy, (London: Clarendon Press), 14.Google Scholar

5 Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Suppl. Vol. 49 (1975).Google Scholar

6 ‘On Being Moved by Anna Karenina and Anna Karenina’, Philosophy 52, 345.Google Scholar

7 I am not, of course denying that the sort of enlightenment which characterizes fiction, can sometimes be found in the description of non-fictional events—for example, in great journalism. I have in mind, for instance, Orwell's account of a hanging or the shooting of an elephant in Burma. But it would be important to note here that Orwell does not just state what happened, but tells a story.

8 Ducasse, S., ‘Taste, Meaning and Reality in Art’ in Hook, S. (ed.) Art and Philosophy, (New York: University Press), 190.Google Scholar

9 Hare, , op. cit.Google Scholar

10 Gombay, A., ‘What You Don't Know Doesn't Hurt You’, Proc. Arist. Soc. (1979), 244.Google Scholar

11 Ducasse, , op. cit.Google Scholar

12 Culture and Value, (Blackwell), 17Google Scholar. I am grateful to the editor of the British Journal of Aesthetics, Dr T. J. Diffey, for permission to quote extensively from my review of this work.

13 Ibid., 28.

14 Ibid., 17.

15 Ibid., 58.

16 From ‘The Contemporary Novel’ quoted in D. H. Lawrence: The Critical Heritage, Draper, R. P. (ed.) (Routledge), 276Google Scholar

17 It may be said that Mill breaks decisively with this aspect of his introduction of qualitative considerations. But it is worth noting that in the last resort Mill is forced to explain even this aspect as a matter of what most qualified judges would choose, i.e. as a matter of numbers.

18 ‘Essay on Bentham’, in Utilitarianism (Fontana), 120.Google Scholar

19 Intruder in the Dust (Chatto & Windus), 6869.Google Scholar

20 In Wisdom: Twelve Essays, (Blackwell), 274.Google Scholar

21 Ibid., 275.

23 Ibid., 276.

24 Zettel, (Basil Blackwell), 82.Google Scholar

25 Cary, Joyce, Art and Reality, (Cambridge University Press), 154155.Google Scholar