Skip to main content
Log in

All Things in Mind: Panpsychist Elements in Spinoza, Deleuze, and Peirce

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Biosemiotics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Benedict de Spinoza, C.S. Peirce, and Gilles Deleuze delineate a trajectory through the history of ideas in the dialogue about the potentials and limitations of panpsychism, the view that world is fundamentally made up of mind. As a parallel trajectory to the panpsychism debate in contemporary philosophy of mind and cognitive psychology, this approach can inform and enrich the discussion of the role and scope of mind in the natural world. The philosophies of mind developed by Deleuze and Peirce are Spinozistic in their natural monism but move beyond Spinoza to explain mind as a part of the natural world in semiotic terms.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For example, see Coleman 2012; Strawson 2006; Griffin 1998; Chalmers 1996, and McGinn 1991.

  2. Steven Cahn’s canonical anthology, Classics of Western Philosophy, (Cahn 1997), now in its Seventh Edition, contains only parts I and II of The Ethics. In fairness to Cahn, however, any anthology is, by its nature, selective, and these two parts take up more space than that allotted to either Descartes or Leibniz.

  3. Peirce has only recently begun to gain recognition for his wide range of intellectual accomplishments. Philosopher Thomas Sebeok, for one, asked: “Who is the most original and most versatile intellect that the Americas have so far produced? The answer “Charles S. Peirce” is uncontested, because any second would be so far behind as not to be worth nominating. Mathematician, astronomer, chemist, geodesist, surveyor, cartographer, metrologist, spectroscopist, engineer, inventor; psychologist, philologist, lexicographer, historian of science, mathematical economist, lifelong student of medicine; book reviewer, dramatist, actor, short story writer; phenomenologist, semiotician, logician, rhetorician, metaphysician…” (Sebeok 1981 17).

  4. Although Peirce came to call his own version pragmaticism, a term “ugly enough to be safe from kidnappers” (Peirce 1960c CP 5.414).

  5. Peirce reiterates this point as part of his explanation of synechism (CP 7.573). Billy Crystal’s character in The Princess Bride popularized the idea when he noted that the Man in Black “was only mostly dead,” having not yet been bound by the total cessation of mind due, of course, to true love.

  6. While all thoughts are signs, it is not the case that all signs are thoughts. Thought-signs demand interpretation via a triadic rather than merely dyadic process.

  7. Peirce works out his own metaphor: consciousness as a bottomless lake in which all our experiences are suspended at various depths (Peirce 1958a CP 7.547). He also describes various levels of consciousness in terms of animal life (Peirce 1958b CP 7.585).

  8. For example, Steven Nadler notes, “What we find in Spinoza, in fact, are some very suggestive remarks for a particular kind of project, one that represents a naturalistic account of consciousness that is precocious in so far as it points the way to just the kind of empirical, scientific inquiry into consciousness that characterizes contemporary neuroscience and (some) recent philosophy of mind” (Nadler 2008 586).

References

  • Cahn, S. M. (1997). Classics of western philosophy (6th ed.). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carriero, J. (2011). Conatus and perfection in Spinoza. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 35, 69–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (1996). The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. New York: Oxford University Press

  • Chalmers, D. J. (2003). Consciousness and its place in nature. In S. Stich & F. Warfield (Eds.), Blackwell guide to the philosophy of mind (pp. 102–142). Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chandler, D. (2007). Semiotics: The basics. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, S. (2012). Mental chemistry: combination for panpsychists. Dialectica, 66(1), 137–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Spinoza, B. (1994). A Spinoza Reader: The Ethics and Other Works. ed and trans: Curley, E. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Delany, C. F. (1993). Science, knowledge, and mind: A study in the philosophy of C.S. Peirce. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, G. (1994). Difference and repetition (trans: Patton, P.). New York: Columbia University Press.

  • Deleuze, G. (2001[1968]). Spinoza: Practical philosophy (trans: Hurley, R.). San Francisco: City Lights Publisher.

  • Griffin, D. R. (1998). Unsnarling the world-knot: Consciousness, freedom, and the mind-body problem. Berkeley: University of California Press.

  • Hausman, C. (1993). Charles S. Peirce’s Evolutionary Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Houser, N. (1983). Peirce’s general taxonomy of consciousness. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce, 19(4), 331–359.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keeton, M. T. (1952). Peirce and Montgomery. In P. P. Wiener & F. H. Young (Eds.), Studies in the philosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce (pp. 312–324). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGinn, C. (1991). The problem of consciousness: Essays towards a resolution. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell Publishers, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nadler, S. (2008). Spinoza and consciousness. Mind, 117(467), 575–601.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. P. (1958a[1859-1904]). Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Volume 7. ed. A. Burks. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University.

  • Peirce, C. P. (1958b[1859-1904]). Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Volume 8. ed. A. Burks. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University.

  • Peirce, C. P. (1960a[1859-1904]). Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Volume 1-2. ed. C. Hartshorne and P. Weiss. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University.

  • Peirce, C. P. (1960b[1859-1904]). Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Volume 3-4. ed. C. Hartshorne and P. Weiss. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University.

  • Peirce, C. P. (1960c[1859-1904]). Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Volume 5-6. ed. C. Hartshorne and P. Weiss. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University.

  • Sebeok, T. (1979). The sign & its masters. Austin: The University of Texas Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sebeok, T. (1981). The Play of Musement. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  • Strawson, G. (2006). In A. Freeman (Ed.), Consciousness and its place in nature: Does physicalism entail panpsychism? Exeter: Imprint Academic.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jonathan Beever.

Additional information

Special Issue “Origins of Mind” edited by Liz Stillwaggon Swan and Andrew M. Winters

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Beever, J., Cisney, V. All Things in Mind: Panpsychist Elements in Spinoza, Deleuze, and Peirce. Biosemiotics 6, 351–365 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-013-9167-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-013-9167-7

Keywords

Navigation