Skip to main content
Log in

Interkinaesthetic affectivity: a phenomenological approach

  • Published:
Continental Philosophy Review Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This Husserlian transcendental-phenomenological investigation of interkinaesthetic affectivity first clarifies the sense of affectivity that is at stake here, then shows how Husserl’s distinctive approach to kinaesthetic experience provides evidential access to the interkinaesthetic field. After describing several structures of interkinaesthetic-affective experience, I indicate how a Husserlian critique of the presupposition that we are “psychophysical” entities might suggest a more inclusive approach to a biosocial plenum that includes all metabolic life.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Cf. 34/87. All references in this form refer to Husserl (1950ff.), cited by volume/page number. Husserl (2001ff.) is cited with the abbreviation HM and the volume/page number.

  2. On the “pregiving” experience or life of consciousness, see, e.g., 37/287, 355; 11/256; 15/149; 34/70, 98f., 262, 319, 449, 451, 486; Husserl (1973), 174[152] (henceforth cited as EU/German page number [English page number]), and cf. 4/4f., 22f.; 8/473, 476; 11/162; 34/49 n. 1, 159f., 223, 251, 317, 452. Note that the sense of “pregiven” that is at stake here does not refer to something that temporally precedes full-fledged “givenness” (although the term is indeed sometimes used this way in genetic-phenomenological accounts). Instead, it refers to the natural attitude’s automatic acceptance of a ready-made world that is simply “there” for us as the universal basis for all action and affection, etc. (cf., e.g., 34/33, 72, and see also 302ff., where this is characterized as the universal prejudice within which all specific prejudices move). To put all this another way, here I am not concerned with a mundane phenomenology that places the sedimented accomplishments of the sciences in brackets solely in order to “go back to” the pre-scientific lifeworld and investigate its “pregiven” tacit structures, for as Husserl indicates (EU/49[50]; cf. 34/582), this is only the first step toward a true transcendental-phenomenological investigation of the correlational a priori in its universal scope (see 6/§§41–46): in addition to “making no use of,” e.g., naturalistic explanations (or other assumptions, results, etc., of mundane science), we must also “inquire back into” the transcendental life through whose operations everything “pregiven” comes about for us in the first place (34/223). For further methodological reflections on these and related issues, see Funke (1987), esp. Chapters 5–7 on critical transcendental phenomenology versus lifeworld metaphysics.

  3. Cf. 4/297, where Husserl notes that sociality presupposes lived-bodily intersubjectivity; although the term “intercorporeity” is usually associated with Merleau-Ponty, the latter famously drew upon Ideen II in a number of respects, and this passage may have spurred him to come to the term.

  4. For Husserl, this is true of phenomenological investigation in general; see, e.g., 3-1/135; HM4/73f.

  5. For some previous phenomenological investigation of the interkinaesthetic dimension (as well as some hints toward related findings in other disciplines), see Behnke (1997, 1999, 2003, 2004c, 2007c). Cf. also Lotz (2002b).

  6. Cf. Behnke (2007b). I considered not only familiar material from Ideen II (Husserliana 4), Analysen zur passiven Synthesis (Husserliana 11) and its later companion volume Aktive Synthesen (Husserliana 31), Formale und transzendentale Logik (Husserliana 17), Krisis (Husserliana 6), and Erfahrung und Urteil, but also material from the intersubjectivity volumes (Husserliana 13, 14, 15); from the early (1893–1913) texts on Wahrnehmung und Aufmerksamkeit (Husserliana 38); from the 1920/1924 lecture course Einleitung in die Ethik (Husserliana 37); from the 1922/23 lecture course Einleitung in die Philosophie (Husserliana 35); from the later (1926–1935) working manuscripts collected under the title Zur phänomenologischen Reduktion (Husserliana 34); and from the C manuscripts, now available in HM/8 under the title Späte Texte über Zeitkonstitution (1929–1934). For other introductions to Husserl’s notion of affection, see, e.g., Montavont (1994); and Steinbock (2001) (along with the references he suggests, li n. 36). For a broader context, see Lohmar (1998). For earlier influential discussions in Husserlian terms, see Landgrebe (1954); Aguirre (1970), Dritter Teil, II, especially §§31–32; Holenstein (1972), especially §§8, 11, 21, 40–42; de Almeida (1972), §14; Kern (1975), §30. For examples of more recent approaches to specific issues in a Husserlian context, see, e.g., Depraz (1994, 1998, 1999, 2000); Zahavi (1999), pp. 115–127; Lotz (2002a, 2007); Steinbock (2004) (my thanks to Brady Heiner for providing a copy of this essay); Lohmar (2005). Here it is not possible to consider either the literature on affectivity in Straus, Sartre, Levinas, Patočka, Merleau-Ponty, and Henry, or the recent work of Waldenfels in this area.

  7. It has been suggested (Holenstein 1972, p. 63; Shin 1978, p. 105) that Husserl often generalized his concepts as he worked them out; the problem, however, is that as the initial sphere of reference becomes but one example of the concept in question, the terminology does not change to reflect the wider sense or differentiate it from the original one. For examples of extended senses of “affection,” see, e.g., 37/355, 34/160.

  8. For more on the latter “Durchgang”-moments, see Behnke (2007a); for the sense of a “dynamic” phenomenology in contrast to both “static” and “genetic” approaches, see Behnke (2004b).

  9. Husserl also makes this distinction by contrasting “objectivating affection” with “feeling-affection” (31/9).

  10. See, e.g., 4/219f.; cf. 11/166.

  11. See, e.g., 14/54; HM8/99 n. 1, 3, and cf. also 34/262f.

  12. Although “undergoing” is often contrasted with “doing,” here “undergoing” implies appreciating streaming subjective processes, in contrast to focusing on the abiding transtemporal unities/identities constituted through these (usually anonymous) processes. I will return to this issue in Sect. 3 below.

  13. Yasuhiko Murakami emphasizes the methodological use of extreme cases in Levinas’s treatment of affectivity (2006), pp. 21f. Cf. also, e.g., Nader El-Bizri, (2006), pp. 312f.

  14. Sokolowski (1974), pp. 108f.

  15. Here it is not possible to offer a complete account of Husserl’s notion of kinaesthesis or to trace the discussion of this theme in subsequent literature.

  16. Cairns (1976), p. 64. Cf. Kern (1975), p. 108 n. 102. On kinaesthetic consciousness in general, see Claesges (1964); Rohr-Dietschi (1974); Behnke (2001b).

  17. Cairns (1976), p. 73. It should be emphasized once again that for Husserl, kinaesthetic performances belong to the broader realm of the “I” whether or not they are explicitly guided by the active, awake “I” and whether or not they come to explicit awareness; see, e.g., 14/447, 450, 452 n. 1; HM8/336 (cf. 53, 258); Cairns (1976), p. 92 (cf. 62, 64f.).

  18. Cf. Behnke (2001a), pp. 105ff.; and Gallagher (1986b), pp. 145, 150f.

  19. Cf. Behnke (2004a, 2007c). In addition to the two points just mentioned—the localization of kinaesthetic capability in somaesthetic sensibility and the role of the kinaesthetic “how of the receivingness” with regard to any somaesthetic sensations whatsoever—and to Husserl’s usual concern with the (often unthematized) role of the kinaestheses in bringing correlative sensuous profiles of externally perceived objects to givenness (cf., e.g., 11/185 n. 1, 363), the kinaestheses of “making a body” must also be taken into consideration (see, e.g., Behnke 1997, pp. 186ff.); all of these aspects of kinaesthetic functioning interact in complex ways that cannot be discussed here.

  20. Cf. Behnke (2004a).

  21. Cf., e.g., HM8/338, 351f. On the lucidly lived body—experienced from within, in lucid awareness and in the manner proper to kinaesthetic consciousness rather than in the mode of “separative seeing”—see Behnke (1984). Cf. also Behnke (1990a, 1990b, 2001b). Natalie Depraz has also independently developed a notion of a “lucid body.” While mine was developed under the influence of Jean Gebser (1973, but cf. also Mohanty (1970/71, pp. 118ff, 1972, Part Three, Chap. 1) and informed by transformative somatic practice (cf. Behnke 2007c), hers was developed under the influence of Sartre and informed by both Eastern Orthodox Christian and Tibetan Buddhist spiritual practices (cf. Depraz 2001a). I was not able to study Depraz’s Lucidité du corps (2001b) prior to carrying out the present investigation and writing this research report, but on first glance, there would certainly seem to be many possible points of contact between Depraz’s work there and my findings here, as well as certain amicable differences of method and interpretation. However, we are, I think, in agreement on the importance of working out a “Husserlian description of transcendental flesh” (Depraz 2001a, p. 493). I am influenced in this regard by Mohanty (1985, e.g., pp. 163f., 211, 242, and cf. also Kern 1975, pp. 43f., p. 47).

  22. Cf. Behnke (1999, 2004b, 2005).

  23. On the reduction to the primal standing-streaming present, see, e.g., 34/384ff. and cf. 185ff., as well as HM8/185ff. On the “original instinct of ‘objectivation’” (HM8/258), cf. Nam-In Lee (1993). On the habitual apperceptive focus on the “external,” see, e.g., 34/64. On the constitution, explication, and enrichment of abiding transtemporal unities/identities, see EU/passim.

  24. See, e.g., HM8/352; cf. 134, and see also Cairns (1976), p. 84.

  25. Maldiney (1991), p. 114, cited in Dastur (1997), pp. 73f.

  26. On the metaphor of a phenomenological “archaeology,” see HM8/356f. Cf. also HM8/394 on the ongoingly interwoven co-functioning of the “strata.” On what I am terming transcendental “mindfulness,” cf. 34/153f. And on further methodological issues merely hinted at here, see Behnke (2007a).

  27. Cf., e.g., 34/46f. on taking episodes from everyday praxis as examples for phenomenological analysis. Note that all of the examples in this section must be understood in terms of the exemplicating move (cf. Zaner 1973, pp. 38f., 41f.)—i.e., taken as examples rather than for their own sake—and that the structures mentioned in no way represent claims about “the” essence of interkinaesthetic affectivity. Instead, I have merely identified certain styles of possibilities that transcend the facts of any given instantiation of them. On the transformation of “essence” into “style” in Husserl’s later phenomenology, cf. Behnke (2004c). Further research in a variety of settings beyond the limits of the present investigation is obviously needed.

  28. Much more sophisticated examples of this structure occur in team sports where one looks for gaps in the other team’s defense, or in such martial arts as aikido, where one looks for energetic points of vulnerability.

  29. Here it is not possible to provide a complete phenomenological description of such structures as mutual or asymmetrical permeability of projects, conflicts among projects, etc.

  30. On “prominence by absence,” see Zaner (1981), pp. 245ff.

  31. Here the term “body mask” refers to patterns of corporeal comportment adopted for public social roles; contrast, for example, a puppy straining at the leash, eager to explore every provocation from a dancing world, with the far more guarded movement style of the adult who is walking the dog, or consider what types of movement might be perceived as “undignified” at a solemn occasion, and so on.

  32. The word “gemütlich” means “good-natured, friendly, genial, comfortable, restful”; “gemütlich werden” means “unbend”; “es sich gemütlich machen” means “make oneself at home, relax”; and “gemütliche Beisammensein” means a social gathering, an occasion for enjoying the pleasures of sociality (HM8/33).

  33. Gallagher (1986a), pp. 153ff.

  34. The notion of sensory-motor amnesia stems from the work of Thomas Hanna (1988). On the critique of corporeal experience, see Behnke (2001a, pp. 101ff., 2004c). The notion of a “dispossession” in need of a “recollection” in which one appropriates one’s own possibilities could also be worked out in Heideggerian terms, although without necessarily following the historical course of Heidegger’s own development (see, e.g., Buckley 1998, pp. 229ff.). Similarly, Husserl’s theme of cultural renewal (27/3ff.) needs to be worked out in more embodied terms. Finally, on the notion of “what is needed next here,” see Behnke (2005) and the references mentioned there.

  35. My background in music (chamber music, orchestra, free improvisation, improvisation with dancers) has given me many rich interkinaesthetic experiences that painfully contrast with what passes as “mainstream” experience in our time.

  36. Here it is not possible to provide a complete phenomenological description of the lived experience of feeling “replenished” (rather than, e.g., “drained”).

  37. John J. Drummond suggests that respect is a moral emotion; what I am suggesting here is that it is also, and correlatively, a style of kinaesthetic comportment. Cf. Drummond (2006).

  38. The context of this reminder is a work in progress I have provisionally entitled This Body that is Not a Thing.

  39. Here it is not possible to provide a complete phenomenological description of a “friendly” (open, accepting, supporting) presence (in contrast, e.g., to sensing a “hostile” or “menacing” presence).

  40. See, e.g., 19-1/24; 34/66, 176; HM8/41.

  41. See 34/363, and cf., e.g., 156, 285. The apperceptive retrieval that is at stake here complements the more familiar function of the transcendental-phenomenological epochē and reduction—namely, to suspend the naive-dogmatic positing (or “acceptance in advance”—cf. 34/222) of the absolute being (Sein) of the world and to bring to light the streaming functioning life that constitutes the world (cf., e.g., 34/395ff.)—by effecting a similar suspension of the unquestioned “acceptance in advance” of something’s being-thus (Sosein) and bringing to light the “apperceiving-as” that constitutes the phenomenon in question as having precisely this sense (34/280).

  42. Cf. 34/54, 393; see also 137f., and cf. 6/81f., 415. In other words, the abstraction that “purifies” the psyche from the psychophysical does not, in and of itself, also perform the work of the transcendental-phenomenological epochē and reduction: it is only the latter that suspends any automatic acceptance of the naive absolutization of the world and its pregiven entities.

  43. Cf., e.g., 34/49, 112. The theme of the mundanization of transcendental flesh cannot be pursued here.

  44. Cf. 32/217f. on the realm of the organic, encompassing individuals that maintain morphological identity across metabolic change, in contrast to the realm of the inorganic, where an object remains the same insofar as it has the same identical parts. Husserl suggests that it is this larger sense of morphological-biological individuality (rather than the “psyche” per se) that ought to be contrasted with sheerly physical res extensa; the distinction between organic individuals having a psychic life and organic individuals presumed to lack such a life then falls under the broader category of the organic in general—a conceptual reconfiguration that requires rethinking how the entire question of the “psychophysical” is to be addressed scientifically (cf. 32/225f.).

  45. Reported in Criswell Hanna (2003), in the context of describing the importance of somatics practitioners developing coherent heart rate variability (e.g., respiratory sinus arrhythmia) as yet another way (in addition to the transformative somatic practice in question) to benefit their clients and students, moving them “toward greater synchrony and coherence.” However, Backster’s research on the biocommunication phenomenon he terms “primary perception” may indicate that the relationship he has investigated does not change with distance in the way we might expect with an electromagnetic signal; see Jensen (2000), 292ff.

References

  • Aguirre, Antonio. 1970. Genetische Phänomenologie und Reduktion. Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Behnke, Elizabeth A. 1984. World without opposite/flesh of the world (A Carnal Introduction). Felton: California Center for Jean Gebser Studies. Reprinted. Study Project in Phenomenology of the Body, 1990; now available at www.lifwynnfoundation.org.

  • Behnke, Elizabeth A. 1990a. The lucidly lived body: Sensory awareness and the spontaneity of prepredicative experience. Paper presented at the Merleau-Ponty Circle, University Park, PA.

  • Behnke, Elizabeth A. 1990b. The lucidly lived body. Workshop on "Perceptions of the body,” Honolulu, HI.

  • Behnke, Elizabeth A. 1997. Ghost gestures: Phenomenological investigations of bodily micromovements and their intercorporeal implications. Human Studies 20: 181–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Behnke, Elizabeth A. 1999. From Merleau-Ponty’s concept of nature to an interspecies practice of peace. In Animal others, ed. H. Peter Steeves, 93–116. Albany: SUNY Press.

  • Behnke, Elizabeth A. 2001a. Phenomenology of embodiment/embodied phenomenology: Emerging work. In The reach of reflection: Issues for phenomenology’s second century, ed. Steven Crowell, Lester Embree, and Samuel J. Julian, vol. 1, 94–117. Boca Raton: Electron Press.

  • Behnke, Elizabeth A. 2001b. The immediacy of primal motility: An experiment in phenomenological practice (III). Paper given at Husserl Circle, Bloomington, IN.

  • Behnke, Elizabeth A. 2003. Contact improvisation and the lived world. In Kunst und Wahrheit. Festschrift für Walter Biemel zu seinem 85. Geburtstag, ed. Mădălina Diaconu, 39–61. Bucharest: Humanitas.

  • Behnke, Elizabeth A. 2004a. Body-as-constituting/Body-as-constituted: An experiment in phenomenological practice (V). Paper given at Husserl Circle, Georgetown.

  • Behnke, Elizabeth A. 2004b. On the dynamization of phenomenological concepts: An experimental essay in phenomenological practice. Focus Pragensis 4: 9–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Behnke, Elizabeth A. 2004c. The socially shaped body and the critique of corporeal experience. Paper given at Korean-American Phenomenology Conference, Memphis, TN.

  • Behnke, Elizabeth A. 2005. Bodily protentionality: An experiment in phenomenological practice (VI). Paper given at Husserl Circle, Dublin.

  • Behnke, Elizabeth A. 2007a. Phenomenologist at work. Paper given at Husserl Circle, Prague.

  • Behnke, Elizabeth A. 2007b. Husserl’s protean concept of affectivity: From the texts to the phenomena themselves. Philosophy Today (Forthcoming).

  • Behnke, Elizabeth A. 2007c. Bodily relationality: An experiment in phenomenological practice (VII). In Phenomenology 2005. Selected essays from North America, ed. Lester Embree and Thomas Nenon, vol. 5, 67–97. Bucharest: Zeta Books.

  • Buckley, R. Phillip. 1998. Stromdichtung and subjectivity in the later Heidegger. In Self-awareness, temporality, and alterity, ed. Dan Zahavi, 223–238. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  • Cairns, Dorian. 1976. Conversations with Husserl and Fink, ed. Husserl-Archives. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Claesges, Ulrich. 1964. Edmund Husserls Theorie der Raumkonstitution. Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Criswell Hanna, Eleanor. 2003. Editor’s introduction. Somatics Society Newsletter (Winter): 1.

  • Dastur, Françoise. 1997. Pour une phénoménologie de l’événement: L’attente et la surprise. Études Phénoménologiques 25: 59–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Almeida, Guido A. 1972. Sinn und Inhalt in der genetischen Phänomenologie E. Husserls. Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Depraz, Natalie. 1994. Temporalité et affection dans les manuscrits tardifs sur la temporalité (1929–1935) de Husserl. Alter 2: 63–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Depraz, Natalie. 1998. Can I anticipate myself? Self-affection and temporality. In Self-awareness, temporality, and alterity, ed. Dan Zahavi, 83–97. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  • Depraz, Natalie. 1999. Délimitation de l’émotion: Approche d’une phénoménologie du coeur. Alter 7: 121–148.

    Google Scholar 

  • Depraz, Natalie. 2000. Hyletic and kinetic facticity of the absolute flow and world creation. In The many faces of time, ed. John B. Brough and Lester Embree, 25–35. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  • Depraz, Natalie. 2001a. Holy body and rainbow body: The lived body as an exemplary access to the absolute. In The reach of reflection: Issues for phenomenology’s second century, ed. Steven Crowell, Lester Embree, and Samuel J. Julian, vol. 3, 481–503. Boca Raton: Electron Press.

  • Depraz, Natalie. 2001b. Lucidité du corps. De l’empirisme transcendantal en phénoménologie. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drummond, John J. 2006. Respect as a moral emotion: A phenomenological approach. Husserl Studies 22: 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • El-Bizri, Nader. 2006. Uneasy interrogations following Levinas. Studia Phaenomenologica 6: 293–315.

    Google Scholar 

  • Funke, Gerhard. 1987. Phänomenologie—Metaphysik oder Methode? Bonn: Bouvier, 1966. English publication: Phenomenology—Metaphysics or method? (trans. David J. Parent). Athens: Ohio University Press.

  • Gallagher, Shaun. 1986a. Lived body and environment. Research in Phenomenology 16: 139–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, Shaun. 1986b. Hyletic experience and the lived body. Husserl Studies 3: 131–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gebser, Jean. 1973. Ursprung und Gegenwart [1949/1953]. München: Deutscher Taschenbuch Verlag.

  • Hanna, Thomas. 1988. Somatics. Reading: Addison-Wesley.

  • Holenstein, Elmar. 1972. Phänomenologie der Assoziation. Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1950ff. Husserliana. Den Haag/Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff/Kluwer/Springer.

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1973. Erfahrung und Urteil, ed. Ludwig Landgrebe. Hamburg: Felix Meiner, 1999 [1938/39]. English publication: Experience and judgment. (trans. James S. Churchill and Karl Ameriks). Evanston, IL: Northwestern.

  • Husserl, Edmund. 2001ff. Husserliana Materialienbände. Dordrecht: Kluwer/Springer.

  • Jensen, Derrick. 2000. A language older than words. New York: Context Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kern, Iso. 1975. Idee und Methode der Philosophie. Leitgedanken für eine Theorie der Vernunft. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landgrebe, Ludwig. 1954. Prinzipien der Lehre vom Empfinden. Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung 8: 195–209. Reprinted in Der Weg der Phänomenologie. Das Problem einer ursprünglichen Erfahrung. Gütersloh: Gerd Mohn, 1963, 111–123.

  • Lee, Nam-In. 1993. Edmund Husserls Phänomenologie der Instinkte. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lohmar, Dieter. 1998. Erfahrung und kategoriales Denken. Hume, Kant und Husserl über vorprädikative Erfahrung und prädikative Erkenntnis. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lohmar, Dieter. 2005. Verschlungene Wege zur Sichtbarkeit. Vier Thesen über die phantasmatische Selbstaffektion als Funktion der Einbildungskraft in der Wahrnehmung. Focus Pragensis 5: 105–116.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lotz, Christian. 2002a. Husserls Genuss. Über den Zusammenhang von Leib, Affektion, Fühlen, und Werthaftigkeit. Husserl Studies 18: 19–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lotz, Christian. 2002b. Mitmachende Spiegelleiber. Anmerkungen zur Phänomenologie der konkreten Intersubjektivität bei Husserl. Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung 56: 72–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lotz, Christian. 2007. From affectivity to subjectivity: Husserl’s phenomenology revisited. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maldiney, Henri. 1991. Penser l’homme et la folie. Grenoble: J. Millon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mohanty, Jitendra N. (1970/71) Husserl’s concept of intentionality. Analecta Husserliana 1: 100–132.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mohanty, Jitendra N. 1972. The concept of intentionality. St. Louis: Warren H. Green.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mohanty, Jitendra N. 1985. The possibility of transcendental philosophy. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montavont, Anne. 1994. Le phénomène de l’affection dans les Analysen zur passiven Synthesis. Alter 2: 119–139.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murakami, Yasuhiko. 2006. Horizons de l’affectivité: L’hyperbole comme méthode phénoménologique de Lévinas. Studia Phaenomenologica 6: 17–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rohr-Dietschi, Ursula. 1974. Zur Genese des Selbstbewusstseins. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shin, Gui-Hyun. 1978. Die Struktur des inneren Zeitbewußtseins. Eine Studie über den Begriff der Protention in den veröffentlichten Schriften Edmund Husserls. Bern: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sokolowski, Robert. 1974. Husserlian meditations. Evanston: Northwestern.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steinbock. Anthony J. 2001. Translator’s Introduction. In Edmund Husserl, Analyses concerning passive and active synthesis: Lectures on transcendental logic, xv–lxvii (trans. Anthony J. Steinbock). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  • Steinbock, Anthony J. 2004. Affection and attention: On the phenomenology of becoming aware. Continental Philosophy Review 37: 21–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, Dan. 1999. Self-awareness and alterity. Evanston: Northwestern.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zaner, Richard M. 1973. Examples and possibles: A criticism of Husserl’s theory of free-phantasy variation. Research in Phenomenology 3: 29–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zaner, Richard M. 1981. The context of self. Athens: Ohio University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Elizabeth A. Behnke.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Behnke, E.A. Interkinaesthetic affectivity: a phenomenological approach. Cont Philos Rev 41, 143–161 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-008-9074-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-008-9074-9

Keywords

Navigation