Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Solving a Murder Case by Asking Critical Questions: An Approach to Fact-Finding in Terms of Argumentation and Story Schemes

  • Published:
Argumentation Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, we look at reasoning with evidence and facts in criminal cases. We show how this reasoning may be analysed in a dialectical way by means of critical questions that point to typical sources of doubt. We discuss critical questions about the evidential arguments adduced, about the narrative accounts of the facts considered, and about the way in which the arguments and narratives are connected in an analysis. Our treatment shows how two different types of knowledge, represented as schemes, play a role in reasoning with evidence: argumentation schemes and story schemes.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We use the term “fact” in its juridical sense, that is, descriptions of states or events the truth of which is currently unknown and has to be proven (cf. facta probanda or facts in issue, Anderson et al. 2005). With “evidence” we mean the evidential data, the primary sources of evidence the existence of which cannot be sensibly denied (e.g. witness statements made in court, forensic expert reports handed to the jury). Evidence and facts should not be confused: the existence of the evidential data does not guarantee the truth of the fact evidenced. For example, that there is a testimony by a witness who saw the suspect jump into a car does not guarantee that the suspect jumped into a car (the witness might lie or he might confuse the suspect with someone else).

  2. The concept of argumentation schemes was introduced by Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca (1971). See also Garssen (2001), van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1992), Kienpointner (1992) and Walton et al. (2008).

  3. The idea of general patterns of (types of) events that underlie stories stems from literature theory (e.g. Propp 1968) and has found applications in Cognitive Psychology and AI (Rumelhart 1975; Schank and Abelson 1977; Schank 1986). We have previously addressed the role of story schemes in the process of proof (Bex 2009; Bex and Verheij 2010; Bex 2011).

  4. We started our analysis of this case in (Bex and Verheij 2009; Bex and Verheij 2011a), of which the present paper is an extension.

  5. In the Netherlands the judges are required to provide a written verdict in which their considerations are summarized. Many of these verdicts are available to the public on http://www.rechtspraak.nl. The verdicts in the Nadia van der V. case are available (in Dutch): LJN AO3150 (court of Utrecht) and LJN AT5190 (court of appeal Arnhem).

  6. This approach has its roots in Wigmore’s (1931) evidence charts and has been further developed by “New Evidence Theorists” such as Anderson et al. (2005). Similar argument structures have been discussed by, among others, Freeman (1991), Reed et al. (2007) and Verheij (2005b). Bex et al. (2003) have further discussed the link between Wigmore’s graphs and such argument structures.

  7. This explanatory story-based approach, the main proponents of which are Wagenaar et al. (1993) and Pardo and Allen (2007), is based on work from cognitive and legal psychology (Bennett and Feldman 1981; Pennington and Hastie 1993).

  8. Argumentative analyses of the anchored narratives theory by Wagenaar, Crombag and Van Koppen have been given by Verheij (2000), Bex et al. (2006) and Verheij and Bex (2009).

  9. Anderson et al.’s work, for example, is firmly based on what is called the Rationalist Tradition (Anderson et al. 2005, pp. 78–86), which argues that it is necessary to rationally reason with the evidence in order to establish whether or not our belief in the facts is justified. Conversely, Bennett and Feldman’s (1981) and Pennington and Hastie’s (1993) work was also meant as a descriptive theory of how people reason with masses of evidence in legal cases.

  10. The rhetorical role of both arguments and stories, while interesting, has not been explored in the work on the hybrid theory.

  11. See van Eemeren (1994) for a concise introduction to this view.

  12. Often, new explananda appear during the investigation or treatment of a case. For example, once a possible suspect has been found a new explanandum could be “why was this man acting suspiciously near the crime scene?”

  13. Josephson (2002) discusses abductive reasoning in the context of reasoning with narratives and criminal evidence. Walton (2001) provides a more general account, contrasting abductive reasoning with presumptive and plausible reasoning.

  14. Often, c explains e because c is a cause of e and in our other work we mostly model explanation using causal links. However, in order to sidestep the often difficult and subtle discussions about causality, here we simply talk about explanatory relations. This also allows, for example, teleological or intentional explanations (see also Bex et al. 2009; and Bex 2011, pp. 24–31).

  15. Pennington and Hastie (1993) say that a story is coherent if it is consistent and it follows a general motive—goal—action—consequence sequence (see Sect. 3.2) and any individual causal links in the story are plausible. In Thagard (2004) coherence depends on the numerical strength of the explanatory relations between events in the story, which is in turn determined by formal coherence principles.

  16. See e.g. Walton et al. (2008, Chap. 5).

  17. As is argued by Schank and Abelson (1977) and Schank (1986), the knowledge that is used when thinking about patterns of action often does not have the form of individual causal or explanatory rules but is more naturally thought of as a collection of coherent and generalized events or event types, see Sect. 3.2.

  18. Experiments by Pennington and Hastie (1993) have shown that stories that explain the facts are closest to how legal decision makers actually think about a case and Wagenaar et al. (1993) hence argue that stories are the only viable way to argue with complex masses of evidence.

  19. See Bex and Walton (2010), Pardo and Allen (2007), who have argued that reasoning in trials involves comparing stories about the facts.

  20. Twining (1999) and Anderson et al. (2005) argue that stories are “dangerous” because they can, for instance, be based on false generalizations, and Wagenaar et al. (1993) argue that we should be careful not to let a “good” story push away a “true” story.

  21. This observation was already made by Pennington and Hastie (1993) and Wagenaar et al. (1993), who say that a story must explain the evidence and that it must be anchored in safe commonsense knowledge.

  22. See (Bex and Verheij 2011b) for a further discussion on how sets of facts can be used as reasons for legal conclusions.

  23. This is the case in, for example, Pennington and Hastie’s (1993), Josephson’s (2002) and Thagard’s (2004) approaches.

  24. In Walton's treatment, argumentation schemes do not only occur as generalized rules of inference, but also as (generalizable) small derivations or pieces of dialogue (Verheij 2003). Cf. also Prakken (2010) who argues that some argumentation schemes are compressions of more complex types of defeasible reasoning and Verheij (2009), who shows how argumentation schemes have been incorporated into more formal models of argumentation.

  25. See Hitchcock (2010) for an exposition of how logicians or epistemologists might go about constructing (new) argumentation schemes.

  26. In Bex and Verheij (2011b), we further explain the link between the factual and the legal aspects of a case.

  27. There is theoretical discussion about the nature and existence of direct evidence, see for instance Anderson et al. (2005), pp. 62–63. For our purposes, it suffices to note that we consider an event to be directly supported when there is a direct, argumentative (evidential) chain of reasoning from evidence to the event.

  28. Pennington and Hastie (1993) have shown that the chronological ordering is more convincing than an arbitrary ordering.

  29. Freeman (2006) has provided a classification of types of warrants based on epistemic considerations. He distinguishes a priori, empirical, institutional and evaluative warrants.

  30. The tests raised controversy in another well-publicised Dutch case, namely the Deventer Moordzaak.

  31. This second example is based on an actual Dutch case, aptly named the “Ballpoint-case” (Feteris 1999).

  32. The exact role and nature of the weighing of reasons goes beyond the goals of this paper. In our perspective on the weighing of reasons, the issue whether certain given pros outweigh given cons is itself open for argumentation. For instance, in the law, precedents can sometimes be used to argue how certain reasons must be weighed. See also Wellman (1971), Naess (1978), Govier (1999), Feteris (2008), Hage (1996, 1997), Verheij (1996). The debate on the weighing of reasons has recently been revived by the Symposium on Conductive Arguments, organized at University of Windsor in 2010 (about which a special issue of the journal Informal Logic is in preparation).

References

  • Anderson, T.J., D.A. Schum, and W.L. Twining. 2005. Analysis of evidence, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, W.L., and M.S. Feldman. 1981. Reconstructing reality in the courtroom: Justice and judgment in American culture. London: Methuen-Tavistock.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bex, F.J. 2009. Analysing stories using schemes. In Legal evidence and proof: Statistics, stories, logic, ed. H. Kaptein, H. Prakken, and B. Verheij, 93–116. Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bex, F.J. 2011. Arguments, stories and criminal evidence: A formal hybrid theory. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bex, F.J., T. Bench-Capon, and K. Atkinson. 2009. Did he jump or was he pushed? Abductive practical reasoning. Artificial Intelligence and Law 17(2): 79–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bex, F.J., P.J. van Koppen, H. Prakken, and B. Verheij. 2010. A hybrid formal theory of arguments, stories and criminal evidence. Artificial Intelligence and Law 18(2): 123–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bex, F.J., H. Prakken, C. Reed, and D.N. Walton. 2003. Towards a formal account of reasoning about evidence: Argumentation schemes and generalisations. Artificial Intelligence and Law 11: 125–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bex, F.J., H. Prakken, and B. Verheij. 2006. Anchored narratives in reasoning about evidence. In Legal knowledge and information systems. JURIX 2006: The nineteenth annual conference, ed. T. Van Engers, 11–20. Amsterdam: IOS Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bex, F.J., and B. Verheij. 2009. Het Onderbouwen van een Feitelijk Oordeel in een Strafzaak: Methode, casus, aanbevelingen (Grounding a judgement about the facts in a criminal case: Method, case, recommendations). In Reizen met Mijn Rechter: Psychologie van het Recht, ed. P.J. van Koppen, H. Merkelbach, M. Jelicic, and J.W. de Keijser, 935–952. Deventer: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bex, F.J., and Verheij, B. 2010. Story schemes for argumentation about the facts of a crime. In Proceedings of the 2010 AAAI fall symposium on computational narratives. AAAI technical report FS-10-04. Menlo Park (CA): AAAI Press.

  • Bex, F.J., and B. Verheij. 2011a. Arguments, stories and evidence: critical questions for fact-finding. In Proceedings of the 7th conference of the international society for the study of argumentation (ISSA 2010), eds. F.H. van Eemeren, B. Garssen, D. Godden, and G. Mitchell, 71–84. Amsterdam: Rozenberg/Sic Sat.

  • Bex, F.J., and B. Verheij. 2011b. Legal shifts in the process of proof. In Proceedings of the 13th ICAIL, Pittsburgh, USA, 11–20. New York: ACM Press.

  • Bex, F.J., and Walton, D. 2010. Burdens and standards of proof for inference to the best explanation. In Legal knowledge and information systems. JURIX 2010: The twenty-third annual conference. Frontiers in artificial intelligence and applications 223, ed. R.G.F. Winkels, 37–46. Amsterdam: IOS Press.

  • Cohen, L.J. 1977. The probable and the provable. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Feteris, E.T. 1999. What went wrong in the ballpoint case? In Complex cases: Perspectives on the Netherlands criminal justice system, ed. M. Malsch, and J.F. Nijboer, 11–26. Amsterdam: Thela Thesis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feteris, E.T. 2008. Weighing and balancing in the justification of judicial decisions. Informal Logic 28: 20–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finlayson, M.A., W. Richards, and P.H. Winston. 2010. Computational models of narrative: Review of a workshop. AI Magazine 31(2): 97–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, J.B. 1991. Dialectics and the macrostructure of arguments: A theory of argument structure. Berlin: Foris Publications.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, J.B. 2006. Systematizing Toulmin’s warrants: An epistemic approach. In Arguing on the Toulmin model. New essays in argument analysis and evaluation, ed. D.L. Hitchcock, and B. Verheij, 87–100. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garssen, B. 2001. Argument schemes. In Crucial concepts in argumentation theory, ed. F. van Eemeren, 81–99. Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Govier, T., ed. 1999. Reasoning with pros and cons. Conductive arguments revisited. In The philosophy of argument. Newport: Vale Press.

  • Hage, J.C. 1996. A Theory of legal reasoning and a logic to match. Artificial Intelligence and Law 4: 199–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hage, J.C. 1997. Reasoning with rules. An essay on legal reasoning and its underlying logic. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, D.L. 2010. The generation of argumentation schemes. In Dialectics, dialogue and argumentation. An examination of douglas walton’s theories of reasoning and argument, ed. C.A. Reed, and C. Tindale, 157–166. London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Josephson, J.R. 2002. On the proof dynamics of inference to the best explanation. In The dynamics of judicial proof—computation, logic and common sense, ed. M. MacCrimmon, and P. Tillers, 287–306. Berlin: Physica Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kienpointner, M. 1992. Alltagslogik: struktur and funktion von argumentations-mustern. Stuttgart: Fromman-Holzboog.

    Google Scholar 

  • Naess, A. 1978. Elementaire argumentatieleer. (Elementary theory of argumentation). Baarn: Ambo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nijboer, J.F., and A. Sennef. 1999. Justification. In Complex cases: Perspectives on the Netherlands criminal justice system, ed. M. Malsch, and J.F. Nijboer, 11–26. Amsterdam: Thela Thesis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pardo, M.S., and R.J. Allen. 2007. Juridical proof and the best explanation. Law and Philosophy 27: 223–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pennington, N., and R. Hastie. 1993. Reasoning in explanation-based decision making. Cognition 49(1–2): 123–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perelman, C., and L. Olbrechts-Tyteca. 1971. The new rhetoric: A treatise on argumentation, 2nd edn, (trans: J. Wilkinson and P. Weaver). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. (First published, as La Nouvelle Rhetorique, in 1958).

  • Pollock, J.L. 1987. Defeasible reasoning. Cognitive Science 11(4): 481–518.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prakken, H. 2010. On the nature of argument schemes. In Dialectics, dialogue and argumentation. An examination of Douglas Walton’s theories of reasoning and argument, ed. C.A. Reed, and C. Tindale, 167–185. London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prakken, H. 2011. Argumentation without arguments. Argumentation 25: 171–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Propp, V. 1968. the morphology of the folktale. Austin (TX): University of Texas Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reed, C., D. Walton, and F. Macagno. 2007. Argument diagramming in logic, law and artificial intelligence. Knowledge Engineering Review 22(1): 87–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rumelhart, D.E. 1975. Notes on a schema for stories. In Representation and understanding: Studies in cognitive science, ed. D.G. Bobrow, and A. Collins. New York (NY): Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schank, R.C., and R.P. Abelson. 1977. Scripts, plans, goals and understanding: An inquiry into human knowledge structures. Hillsdale (NJ): Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schank, R.C. 1986. Explanations patterns: Understanding mechanically and creatively. Hillsdale (NJ): Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. 2004. Causal inference in legal decision making: Explanatory coherence vs. bayesian networks. Applied Artificial Intelligence 18(3): 231–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toolan, M. 2001. Narrative: a critical linguistic introduction, 2nd ed. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, S.E. 1958. The uses of argument. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Twining, W.L. 1999. Necessary but dangerous? Generalizations and narrative in argumentation about ‘facts’ in criminal process. In Complex cases: Perspectives on the Netherlands criminal justice system, ed. J.F. Nijboer, and M. Malsch, 69–98. Amsterdam: Thela Thesis.

    Google Scholar 

  • van den Braak, S.W. 2010. Sensemaking Software for Crime Analysis. Doctoral dissertation, Department of Information and Computing Sciences, Utrecht University.

  • van Eemeren, F.H., and R. Grootendorst. 1992. Argumentation, communication, and fallacies: a pragma-dialectical perspective. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F.H. 1994. The Study of argumentation as normative pragmatics. In Studies in pragma-dialectics, ed. F.H. van Eemeren, and R. Grootendorst, 3–8. Amsterdam: Sic Sat.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verheij, B. 1996. Rules, reasons, arguments. Formal studies of argumentation and defeat. Maastricht: Dissertation Universiteit Maastricht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verheij, B. 2000. Dialectical argumentation as a heuristic for courtroom decision making. In Rationality, information and progress in law and psychology. Liber Amicorum Hans F. Crombag, ed. P.J. van Koppen, and N. Roos, 203–226. Maastricht: Metajuridica Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verheij, B. 2003. Dialectical argumentation with argumentation schemes: An approach to legal logic. Artificial Intelligence and Law 11(2): 167–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Verheij, B. 2005a. Evaluating arguments based on Toulmin’s scheme. Argumentation 19(3): 347–371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Verheij, B. 2005b. Virtual arguments: On the design of argument assistants for lawyers and other arguers. The Hague: T.M.C. Asser Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verheij, B. 2009. The Toulmin argument model in artificial intelligence. Or: How semi-formal, defeasible argumentation schemes creep into logic. In Argumentation in artificial intelligence, ed. I. Rahwan, and G. Simari, 219–238. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Verheij, B., and F.J. Bex. 2009. Accepting the truth of a story about the facts of a criminal case. In Legal evidence and proof: Statistics, stories, logic, ed. H. Kaptein, H. Prakken, and B. Verheij, 161–193. Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagenaar, W.A., P.J. van Koppen, and H.F.M. Crombag. 1993. Anchored narratives. The psychology of criminal evidence. London: Harvester Wheatsheaf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. 1996. Argumentation schemes for presumptive reasoning. Mahwah (NJ): Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D.N. 2001. Abductive, presumptive and plausible arguments. Informal Logic 21(2): 141–172.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D.N. 2002. Legal argumentation and evidence. University Park (Pennsylvania): Penn. State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D.N., C.A. Reed, and F. Macagno. 2008. Argumentation schemes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, C. 1971. Challenge and response. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wigmore, J.H. 1931. The principles of judicial proof or the process of proof as given by logic, psychology, and general experience, and illustrated in judicial trials, 2nd ed. Boston (Massachusetts): Little, Brown and Company.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Floris Bex.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Bex, F., Verheij, B. Solving a Murder Case by Asking Critical Questions: An Approach to Fact-Finding in Terms of Argumentation and Story Schemes. Argumentation 26, 325–353 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-011-9257-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-011-9257-0

Keywords

Navigation