Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

A Virtue Epistemological Approach to the Demarcation Problem

Implications for Teaching About Feng Shui in Science Education

  • SI: Feng Shui
  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We argue for a virtue epistemological approach to the demarcation problem, for we think that such an approach makes sense from the perspective of an ameliorative epistemology. We argue that sustained and consistent pseudoscientific beliefs and attitudes call for an explanation in terms of underlying epistemic vices, and that remedying them calls for charging the relevant people with vice, but in a responsible and sensitive way. We exemplify some common epistemic vices associated with pseudoscientific beliefs through the case of Feng Shui. We then discuss the value of incorporating pseudoscience in science education and advocate teaching students to identify epistemic virtues and vices in scientific and pseudoscientific practices. We argue for an education focused on epistemic character building and cultivating epistemically virtuous students from early on. This will lead them to become good epistemic agents, in general, and careful (producers and) consumers of science and pseudoscience in particular.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. It is worth noting here that the demarcation problem was naturally a preoccupation for the 1950–1970s analytical philosophy of science projects (like those of Kuhn, Popper, Lakatos) that aspired to offer grand, unified models of science. But with the rise of the Stanford School in the philosophy of science in the 1980s, championing ideals of disunity and plurality in science, the demarcation problem lost its salience. As Feyerabend (1993) noted, if we cannot clearly delineate/define what science is, then how could we say what pseudoscience is in any principled way? We thank an anonymous referee for pointing this out to us.

  2. Also see Roberts and Woods’ (2007) discussion of Woltertorff’s book, John Locke and the Ethics of Belief in regard to this distinction.

  3. Robert Merton (1948) was one of the prominent scholars who characterized science in terms of practices, or rather, norms for practice. For him, science was characterized by an “ethos” that can be captured by four institutional norms (sometimes collectively dubbed “CUDOS”): communism, products of science belong to the community and should be freely shared; universalism, acceptance or rejection of scientific facts, regardless of their origin, should not be based on any personal or social factors; disinterestedness, scientists should not be driven by personal or ideological motives; and organized skepticism; organizationally, science involves a skeptical attitude and scrutiny of any ideologies. Merton proposed that these are descriptive rather than normative. These norms have frequently been criticized as too unrealistic and oversimplified and we agree: they are too idealistic and in fact in some cases, arguably undesirable. There are persuasive counterarguments and counterexamples in the literature. See, for instance, Mitroff (1974).

  4. See Battaly (2014) for a discussion on two conceptions of virtues: one (reliabilism) according to which they are just qualities that produce desired ends/effects, another (responsibilism) according to which they are “praiseworthy psychologies” that involve good motives to produce the desired end. While epistemic ends are surely important, we think it is implausible that a scientist could be consistently reliable without having a motive to reach the desired epistemic ends.

  5. See Stump (2007), Fairweather (2011), Ivanova (2010), and Bhakthavatsalam (2017) for virtue epistemological (reliabilist as well responsibilist) discussions of Pierre Duhem’s (1954) notion of “good sense”—a higher level intellectual quality—in scientists that plays a role in theory choice.

  6. See Crerar (2018) for arguments in this regard.

  7. By this, we take him to mean that knowledge stands in some relation to the world—say, correspondence or some pragmatic relation—independent of virtues or vices. We should also note that Cassam is a vice consequentialist in the sense that (as developed in Cassam 2018) character traits that promote the gaining, having, and sharing of knowledge are virtues and those that obstruct them are vices. (We thank an anonymous reviewer for this latter point.).

  8. See Merchants of Doubt by Naomi Oreskes and Erik Conway (2010) for more cases.

  9. See Paternotte and Ivanova (2017) for historical cases of successful science arising from epistemically vicious scientists.

  10. For this reason, Andrew Wakefield who persistently linked vaccines and autism despite plenty of evidence to the contrary would qualify as a pseudoscientist although biomedical research is a legitimate scientific field.

  11. With regard to (b), one area worth touching on and that is quite relevant to the present discussion is scientism. Scientism has been characterized in various ways such as: presenting an overly triumphalist image of science at the cost of recognizing its historical epistemic and moral pitfalls; believing that science is the only source of all knowledge; claiming that science is superior to all other pursuits; scientists (implicitly/explicitly) claiming to be an authority in fields other than science (for instance, Stephen Hawking and Mlodinow (2010)) claiming philosophy dead); and refusing to meaningfully engage in critiques of pseudoscientific fields and rejecting them by fiat. (See Kidd (2016a) for a virtue epistemological treatment of Feyerabend’s criticism of a 1975 petition in The Humanist, authored and signed by several scientists, that rejected astrology by fiat rather than by appeal to good, detailed criticisms on rational/ epistemic grounds.) Ian James Kidd (2017) has persuasively argued that proponents of scientistic stances suffer from much the same vices as the ones discussed above in the context of pseudoscience: closed-mindedness, epistemic arrogance, dogmatism, and the like. So as we can see, adopting a virtue/vice-epistemological perspective has the advantage of not just demarcating pseudoscience from science, but critiquing epistemically vicious attitudes across the board.

  12. See, for instance, Battaly (2010) and Andrew Aberdein (2014).

  13. This is a key idea of “epistemic situationism”. See Mark Alfano (2012) for more.

  14. The first emperor’s underground terracotta army and the mausoleum they surrounded were clearly important to him and his descendants. And in the Han dynasty that followed the Qin empire, the belief in life after death was widely accepted, and the burial practice was heavily emphasized.

  15. The Feng Shui conflict between these two famous buildings penetrated deeply into people’s minds, and it was widely reported in western media, such as CNN (https://www.cnn.com/style/article/100-years-of-i-m-pei-bank-of-china/index.html) and the New York Times.

  16. More information can be found at http://architectuul.com/architecture/bank-of-china-tower.

  17. https://www.nytimes.com/1986/12/06/obituaries/sir-edward-youde-of-hong-kong-dies.html

  18. There are serious concerns about the claims Feng Shui masters made. Many of them fabricated their personal history and their “Feng Shui education” as they saw fit. For example, one popular Feng Shui master in Hong Kong, Peter So Man Fung (蘇民峰),claimed he learned from some famous Feng Shui masters when he started his Feng Shui career but later denied it when he became more famous. Also, almost all of them focus on their success stories and ignore their failures.

  19. Today, HSBC still follows Feng Shui practices seriously. On Oct. 22, 2020, when its two auspicious lions sitting at the front gate, Stephan and Stitt, were unveiled after restoration from damages made in Hong Kong protests, Feng Shui master David Lung King-Chuen was at the public ceremony to offer his blessing.

  20. See Martin (1994), Slater (2008), and Bhakthavatsalam (2019) for arguments.

  21. See Martin (1994) for examples.

References

  • Aberdein, A. (2014). Defence of Virtue: The Legitimacy of Agent-Based Argument Appraisal. Informal Logic, 34(1), 77–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alfano, M. (2012). Expanding the situationist challenge to responsibilist virtue epistemology. Philosophical Quarterly, 62(247), 223–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baehr, J. (2016) Introduction In Baehr (Ed.) Intellectual virtues and education essays in applied virtue epistemology (pp. 1 - 15). Routledge

  • Battaly, H. (1998) What is virtue epistemology? Twentieth World Congress in Philosophy Boston, Massachusetts https://www.bu.edu/wcp/Papers/Valu/ValuBatt.htm Accessed 27th December 2020

  • Battaly, H. (2010). Attacking Character: Ad Hominem Argument and Virtue Epistemology. Informal Logic, 30(4), 361–390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Battaly, H. (2014) Varieties of epistemic vice In Matheson and Vitz (Eds.) The Ethics of Belief Oxford University Press

  • Bhakthavatsalam, S. (2017) Duhemian good sense and agent reliabilism Studies in History and Philosophy of Science – Part A 64, 22 – 29

  • Bhakthavatsalam, S. (2019). The value of false theories in science education. Science & Education, 28, 5–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carter, J. A. (2014). Robust virtue epistemology as anti-luck epistemology: A new solution. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 97(1), 140–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cassam, Q. (2015). Stealthy Vices. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective, 4, 19–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassam, Q. (2016). Vice Epistemology. The Monist, 99(2), 159–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cassam, Q. (2018) Vices of the mind Oxford University Press

  • Chen Qiyou 陳奇猷 (1984) Lüshi Chunqiu Xinshi 呂氏春秋新釋, Shanghai: Shanghai Guji Chubanshe

  • Day, K. (2015) Fengshui as a narrative of localisation: Case studies of contemporary architecture in Hong Kong and Shanghai https://researchbank.swinburne.edu.au/file/33e80725-8942-421a-8326-d2ce0bb656eb/1/Kirsten%20Day%20Thesis.pdf Accessed 7th January 2021

  • Crerar, C. (2018). Motivational approaches to intellectual vice. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 96(4), 753–766.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Derksen, A. A. (1993). The seven sins of demarcation. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 24, 17–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duhem, P. (1954) The aim and structure of physical theory. Princeton University Press

  • Eitel, E. J. (1873/1987) Feng shui: The rudiments of natural science in China Hong Kong: Lane Crawford (Graham Brash, Singapore)

  • Fairweather, A. (2011). The epistemic value of good sense. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 43(1), 139–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. (1993) Against method (3rd ed.) London: Verso

  • Gilbert, M. (1994) Remarks on collective belief in F. Schmitt (Ed.) Socializing epistemology: The social dimensions of knowledge. Rowman and Littlefield

  • Hansson, S. (2009). Cutting the Gordian knot of demarcation. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 23, 237–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, S. (2013) Defining pseudoscience and science In M. Pigliucci and M. Boudry (Eds.) Philosophy of Pseudoscience (pp. 61–77) University of Chicago Press

  • Hansson, S. (2021) Science and pseudo-science. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2021 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), forthcoming URL = https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/pseudo-science/. Accessed 19 June 2021

  • Hawking, S., Mlodinow, L. (2010) The grand design. Bantham Press

  • Ivanova, M. (2010). Pierre Duhem’s good sense as a guide to theory choice. Studies in

  • History and Philosophy of Science, 41, 58–64

  • Kawall, J. (2002). Other-regarding Epistemic Virtues. Ratio, 15(3), 257–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kidd, I. J. (2016a). Why did Feyerabend defend astrology? Integrity, Virtue, and the Authority of Science. Social Epistemology, 30(4), 464–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kidd, I. J. (2016b). Charging Others with Epistemic vice. The Monist, 99(2), 181–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kidd, I. J. (2017). Is Scientism Epistemically Vicious? In J. Ridder, R. Peels, & R. Woudenberg (Eds.), Scientism: Prospects and problems (pp. 222–249). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kidd, I. J. (2019). Epistemic Corruption and Education. Episteme, 16(2), 220–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knoop, A. (2001) Feng shui for architects American Institute of Architects Newsletter http://www.lezley.info/feng-shui.htm Accessed January 7th 2021

  • Kuhn, T. (1974). Logic of discovery or psychology of research? book iiIn P. A. Schilpp (Ed.), The philosophy of Karl Popper The Library of Living Philosophers (Vol. xiv, pp. 798–819). Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig, J (1992) The intellectual virtues and the life of the mind Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc

  • Lakatos, I. (1981) Science and pseudoscience In S. Brown et al. (Eds.) Conceptions of Inquiry: A Reader (pp.114 – 121) Methuen

  • Laudan, L. (1983) The demise of the demarcation problem In R.S. Cohan and L. Laudan (Eds.) Physics, philosophy, and psychoanalysis (pp. 111–127). Reidel

  • Laudan, L. (2004) The epistemic, the cognitive, and the social In P. Machamer and G. Wolters (Eds.) Science, values, and objectivity (pp. 14 – 23) University of Pittsburgh Press

  • Lip, E. (1990) Feng shui for business. Heian International

  • Lobato, E., Mendoza, J., Sims, V., & Chin, M. (2014). Examining the relationship between conspiracy theories, paranormal beliefs, and pseudoscience acceptance among a university population. Applied Cognitive Psychology, 28(5), 617–625.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lugg, A. (1987). Bunkum, flim-flam and quackery Pseudoscience as a philosophical problem. Dialectica, 41, 221–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. (1971). The use of pseudo-science in science education. Science Education, 55(1), 53–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. (1994). Pseudoscience, the paranormal, and science education. Science & Education, 3, 357–371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M. (2019). Feng shui: Teaching about science and pseudoscience. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Merton, R. (1948). The sociology of science: Theoretical and empirical investigations. The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitroff, I. (1974). Norms and counter-norms in a select group of the Apollo moon scientists: A case study of the ambivalence of scientists. American Sociological Review, 39(4), 579–595.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oreskes, N., & Conway, E. (2010). Merchants of doubt: How a handful of scientists obscured the truth on issues from tobacco smoke to global warming. Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paternotte, C., & Ivanova, M. (2017). Virtues and Vices in Scientific Practice. Synthese, 194(5), 1787–1807.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paton, M. J. (2007). Feng Shui: A continuation of the art of swindlers? Journal of Chinese Philosophy, 34(3), 427–445.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci, M. (2013) The demarcation problem A (belated) response to Laudan In M. Pigliucci and M. Boudry (Eds.) (pp. 9–28). University of Chicago Press

  • Popper, K. (1962). Conjectures and refutations The growth of scientific knowledge. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riggs, W. (2009). Two Problems of Easy Credit. Synthese, 169(1), 201–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, R., & Woods, W. J. (2007). Intellectual virtues: An essay in regulative epistemology. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Slater, M. (2008). How to justify teaching false science. Science Education, 92(3), 526–542.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (1980). The Raft and the Pyramid: Coherence versus Foundations in the Theory of Knowledge. Midwest Studies in Philosohy, 5(1), 3–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E (2007) A virtue epistemology: Apt belief and reflective knowledge Volume I. Oxford University Press

  • Sosa, E (2009) Reflective knowledge: Apt belief and reflective knowledge Volume II. Oxford University Press

  • Sosa, E (2011) Knowing full well Princeton University Press

  • Stump, D. (2007). Pierre Duhem’s virtue epistemology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 38, 149–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swanton, C. (2003) Virtue ethics: A pluralistic view Oxford University Press

  • Tanesini, A. (2016). Teaching Virtue: Changing Attitudes. Logos and Episteme, 7(4), 503–527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (1978) Why astrology is a pseudoscience Philosophy of Science Association (PSA 1978) 1, 223–234

  • Zagzebski, L. (1996). Virtues of the mind: An inquiry into the nature of virtue and the ethical foundations of knowledge. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L. (1999) What is knowledge? In Greco and Sosa (Eds.) The Blackwell Guide to Epistemology. Blackwell

  • Zagzebski, L. (2016) Knowledge and the motive for truth In Baronett (Ed.) Journey into philosophy: An introduction with classic and contemporary readings Routledge 94 – 100

  • Zhang, D. (2002). Key concepts in Chinese Philosophy, translated and edited by Edmund Ryden. Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sindhuja Bhakthavatsalam.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

The authors declare that they have no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bhakthavatsalam, S., Sun, W. A Virtue Epistemological Approach to the Demarcation Problem. Sci & Educ 30, 1421–1452 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-021-00256-5

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-021-00256-5

Keywords

Navigation