Skip to main content
Log in

Is there room for reference borrowing in Donnellan’s historical explanation theory?

  • Research Article
  • Published:
Linguistics and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Famously, both Saul Kripke and Keith Donnellan opposed description theories and insisted on the role of history in determining the reference of a proper name token. No wonder, then, that their views on proper names have often been assimilated. By focusing on reference borrowing—an alleged phenomenon that Kripke takes to be fundamental—we argue that they should not be. In particular, we claim that according to Donnellan a proper name token never borrows its reference from preceding tokens which it is historically connected to. On the contrary, its reference is always fixed anew on who or what the speaker has in mind when he or she produces it. In fact, what is important to realize is that Donnellan and Kripke took two different histories to be relevant: that of the proper name token produced by the speaker (Kripke), and that of the cognitive status of the speaker when he or she produces it (Donnellan). We end by suggesting that this difference between Kripke’s and Donnellan’s accounts of proper names rests on a more general difference in their approach to language.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Abbott, B. (2010). Reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Almog, J. (2004). The proper form of semantics. In M. Reimer & A. Bezuidenhout (Eds.), Descriptions and beyond (pp. 390–419). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Almog, J. (2012). Referential uses and the foundations of direct reference. In J. Almog & P. Leonardi (Eds.), Having in mind: The philosophy of Keith Donnellan (pp. 176–184). Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Almog, J. (2014). Referential mechanics: Direct reference and the foundations of semantics. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bianchi, A. (2007). Speaking and thinking (Or: a more Kaplanian way to a unified account of language and thought). In M. Beaney, C. Penco & M. Vignolo (Eds.), Explaining the mental: Naturalist and non-naturalist approaches to mental acts and processes (pp. 13-32). Newcastle: Cambridge Scholar Publishing.

  • Bianchi, A. (2011). Reference and descriptions. In M. Sbisà, J. O. Östman & J. Verschueren (Eds.), Philosophical perspectives for pragmatics (pp. 253-279). Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company.

  • Bianchi, A. (2012). Two ways of being a (direct) referentialist. In J. Almog & P. Leonardi (Eds.), Having in mind: The philosophy of Keith Donnellan (pp. 79-92). Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Bianchi, A. (forthcoming). Repetition and reference. In A. Bianchi (Ed.), On reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Canfield, J. V. (1977). Donnellan’s theory of names. Dialogue, 16, 104–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Capuano, A. (2012a). The ground zero of semantics. In J. Almog & P. Leonardi (Eds.), Having in mind: The philosophy of Keith Donnellan (pp. 7–29). Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Capuano, A. (2012b). From having in mind to direct reference. In W. P. Kabasenche, M. O’Rourke, & M. H. Slater (Eds.), Reference and referring (pp. 189–208). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1986). A nice derangement of epitaphs. In R. E. Grandy & R. Warner (Eds.), Philosophical grounds of rationality: Intentions, categories, ends (pp. 157–174). Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press. Reprinted in Davidson, D. (2005). Truth, language, and history (pp. 89–107). Oxford: Clarendon Press. Page numbers given relate to the latter volume.

  • Davidson, D. (1994). The social aspect of language. In B. McGuinness & G. Oliveri (Eds.), The philosophy of Michael Dummett (pp. 1–16). Dordrecht: Kluwer. Reprinted in Davidson, D. (2005). Truth, language, and history (pp. 109–125). Oxford: Clarendon Press. Page numbers given relate to the latter volume.

  • Devitt, M. (1974). Singular terms. Journal of Philosophy, 71, 183–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (1981). Designation. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2011). Deference and the use theory. ProtoSociology, 27, 196–211.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (forthcoming). Should proper names still seem so problematic? In A. Bianchi (Ed.), On reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Devitt, M., & Sterelny, K. (1999). Language and reality: An introduction to the philosophy of language (Second ed.). Oxford: Blackwell Publishers. (First edition 1987.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Donnellan, K. S. (1966). Reference and definite descriptions. Philosophical Review, 75, 281–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donnellan, K. S. (1967). Reasons and causes. In P. Edwards (Ed.), The encyclopedia of philosophy (Vol. 7, pp. 85–88). New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donnellan, K. S. (1968). Putting Humpty Dumpty together again. Philosophical Review, 77, 203–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donnellan, K. S. (1970). Proper names and identifying descriptions. Synthese, 21, 335–358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donnellan, K. S. (1973). Substances as individuals. Journal of Philosophy, 70, 711–712.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donnellan, K. S. (1974). Speaking of nothing. Philosophical Review, 83, 3–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donnellan, K. S. (1977). The contingent a priori and rigid designators. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 2, 12–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donnellan, K. S. (1978). Speaker reference, descriptions and anaphora. In P. Cole (Ed.), Syntax and semantics (Vol. 9, pp. 47–68). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donnellan, K. S. (1989). Belief and the identity of reference. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 14, 275–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donnellan, K. S. (2012). Introduction. In K. S. Donnellan, Essays on reference, language, and mind, edited by J. Almog & P. Leonardi (pp. xiii–xx). Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dožudić, D. (2013). Reference in context: On Donnellan’s Essays on reference, language, and mind. Prolegomena, 12, 121–140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1986). A nice derangement of epitaphs: Some comments on Davidson and Hacking. In E. Lepore (Ed.), Truth and interpretation: Perspectives on the philosophy of Donald Davidson (pp. 459–476). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1973). The causal theory of names. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 47, 187–208. Reprinted in Evans, G. (1985). Collected papers (pp. 1–24). Oxford: Clarendon Press. Page numbers given relate to this volume.

  • Hinchliff, M. (2012). Has the theory of reference rested on a mistake? In W. P. Kabasenche, M. O’Rourke, & M. H. Slater (Eds.), Reference and referring (pp. 235–252). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1968–1969). Quantifying in. Synthese, 19, 178–214.

  • Kaplan, D. (1989). Afterthoughts. In J. Almog, J. Perry, & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan (pp. 565–614). Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (2012). An idea of Donnellan. In J. Almog & P. Leonardi (Eds.), Having in mind: The philosophy of Keith Donnellan (pp. 122–175). Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. A. (1972). Naming and necessity. In D. Davidson & G. Harman (Eds.), Semantics of natural language (pp. 253–355 and 763–769). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. A. (1977). Speaker’s reference and semantic reference. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 2, 255–276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. A. (1979). A puzzle about belief. In A. Margalit (Ed.), Meaning and use (pp. 239–283). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. A. (1980). Naming and necessity. Oxford: Blackwell. Reprint with a new preface of Kripke (1972).

  • MacKay, A. F. (1968). Mr. Donnellan and Humpty Dumpty on referring. Philosophical Review, 77, 197–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martí, G. (forthcoming). Reference without cognition. In A. Bianchi (Ed.), On reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • McKinsey, M. (1976). Divided reference in causal theories of names. Philosophical Studies, 30, 235–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKinsey, M. (2011). Understanding proper names. Linguistics and Philosophy, 33, 325–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1911). Knowledge by acquaintance and knowledge by description. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 11, 108–128. Reprinted in Russell, B. (2004). Mysticism and logic (pp. 165–183). Mineola: Dover. Page numbers given relate to this volume.

  • Searle, J. R. (1983). Intentionality: An essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1959). Individuals: An essay in descriptive metaphysics. London: Methuen.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wettstein, H. (1988). Cognitive significance without cognitive content. Mind, 97, 1–28. Reprinted in Wettstein, H. (1991). Has semantics rested on a mistake? And other essays (pp. 132–158 and 211–221). Stanford: Stanford University Press. Page numbers given relate to this volume.

  • Wettstein, H. (2004). The magic prism: An essay in the philosophy of language. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wettstein, H. (2012). Having in mind. In J. Almog & P. Leonardi (Eds.), Having in mind: The philosophy of Keith Donnellan (pp. 93–106). Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This is the result of fully collaborative work. We would like to thank Clotilde Calabi for her kindness, and Joseph Almog, Antonio Capuano, Paolo Leonardi, Andrea Marino, Genoveva Martí, Ernesto Napoli, Paul Nichols, Marco Santambrogio, Alberto Voltolini, three anonymous referees, and especially Michael Devitt, for their comments on earlier drafts.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andrea Bianchi.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bianchi, A., Bonanini, A. Is there room for reference borrowing in Donnellan’s historical explanation theory?. Linguist and Philos 37, 175–203 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-014-9153-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-014-9153-9

Keywords

Navigation