Skip to main content
Log in

Some Consequences (and Enablings) of Process Metaphysics

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Axiomathes Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The interactivist model has explored a number of consequences of process metaphysics. These include reversals of some fundamental metaphysical assumptions dominant since the ancient Greeks, and multiple further consequences throughout the metaphysics of the world, minds, and persons. This article surveys some of these consequences, ranging from issues regarding entities and supervenience to the emergence of normative phenomena such as representation, rationality, persons, and ethics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Parmenides argued (against Heraclitus) against change, and Democritus and Empedocles proposed models of apparent change with an unchanging substrate—atoms for Democritus and substances for Empedocles (Graham 2006). It is this underlying assumption of the metaphysical necessity of an unchanging substrate that is crucial to the position in the main text, and I refer to such an assumption as that of a substance metaphysics, for both “stuffs” as for Empedocles and “atoms” as for Democritus.

  2. Quantum field theory is not a complete physics, and, in fact, cannot be fully correct. But there is no returning to a particle framework: non-localities of interactions, a lack of a consistent definition of particle detections in an accelerating frame, vacuum activity (such as the Casimir effect; Aitchison 1985; Mostepanenko et al. 1997; Sciama 1991), and other phenomena are not consistent with the particularities and localities of particles.

  3. Finite sized “particles” would have non-zero probability of interaction, but they encounter serious problems of their own. For example, if they are deformable, then it is not clear in what sense they are fundamental, rather than decomposable. If they are rigidly not deformable, then they would transmit force through their width instantaneously, in contradiction to the special theory of relativity. There would be extreme difficulty in explaining differing kinds of interactions, such as gravity and electromagnetism, and so on. As mentioned next in the text, if a hybrid position is considered, in which point particles interact via fields, this is strictly false, but it nevertheless already grants much of what I take to be of basic importance in a field-as-process framework.

  4. Aristotle developed a sophisticated metaphysics that also honored this Parmenidean constraint. Classically, he has been interpreted as assuming a basic level of Prime Matter that does not change as a substrate for change. Some contemporary interpretations argue that he was not committed to Prime Matter—the notion of an unchanging substrate for each change, however, is still maintained (e.g., Gill 1989).

  5. I argue that Jaegwon Kim’s arguments against emergence, and Hume’s argument against deriving norms from facts, both depend on unstated substance and particle assumptions (Bickhard 2009a, in preparation).

  6. Note that a model of the emergence of normative phenomena out of non-normative phenomena must address Hume’s argument that this is impossible. For the unsoundness of Hume’s argument, see Bickhard (2009a, in preparation).

  7. They can be indirectly pushed if they happen to be in a directly pushable container. They can be moved in various ways, e.g., by manipulating the thermodynamic gradients in which they are operating (e.g., shifting the course of a hurricane by altering air temperature gradients), and this could be considered unconventional “pushing”.

  8. See Bickhard and Campbell (2003).

  9. There are multiple variants of supervenience, depending on the scope and strength of the modalities involved and of the presumed base (McLaughlin and Bennett 2005). The discussion in the text does not depend on these variations.

  10. As with fields and other processes, an instant of time can be defined as limit point (i.e., relationally), but a spatial distribution of values or particles (or atoms, molecules, etc.) cannot constitute a flame (or any other process): the temporal flow must also be included. If the process can be modeled mathematically, this is generally via differential equations, but the basic point holds independently of the mathematics: just consider exactly the same physical distribution of molecules as in a candle flame, but with completely random momenta.

  11. Such “states” can exist as ongoing conditions, such as the condition of burning or of thinking about metaphysics, but these are by definition themselves conditions of temporally extended process, not infinitely thin time slices.

  12. There is a further perspective on this regarding substances or particles: in a process metaphysics, there is, arguably, no ground for postulating either bare particulars or (clusters of) proper properties. Everything is patterns of unfolding relations in larger unfolding patterns. ‘Instances of patterns’ is as close as possible to notions of entities, and relationally located regions in dynamic patterns is as close as possible to ‘particular’ point locations.

  13. Similarly, what might appear to be exceptions, such as various forms of non-standard analysis, are based on inherently relational category theory or inherently relational model theory. Still further, the apparent units bases of developments in physics, such as string theory or loop quantum gravity—strings and loops—are also relational (Smolin 2001). There is an assumption of an absolute background in current string theory, but that is a defect to be overcome, not a metaphysical implication of the approach (Smolin 2001).

  14. Perhaps the strongest opposite pole would be Teller’s “local physicalism” or “particularism” (Teller 1986, 1989), but Teller introduced this framework as part of arguing that it is incompatible with quantum mechanics.

  15. Note that this is not a nomic relation; it is a kind of relationalism necessary in order for any (field) laws to be definable, even in Lewis’s “best system”.

  16. Mathematical modeling of self-organization is seriously problematic in any case (Hooker, forthcoming), but the claim here is not just that self-organization cannot be mathematically modeled in terms of discrete causal chains, but that discrete causal chains cannot metaphysically capture the relational grounds of self-organization.

  17. The environment affords (or is constituted by) various potentialities, while indications of such potential interactions are in the animal’s CNS.

  18. Millikan and Cummins (Millikan 1984, 1993; Cummins 1996) propose respective models that separate the determination of representational content from that which is represented, and, thus, have an approach for attempting to account for representational error: the content falsely applies to the represented. But these models too fail to account for organism detectable error (Bickhard 2009a, in preparation).

  19. Some models—e.g., Dretske (1988) and Clark (Clark 2001; Wheeler and Clark 1999)—are explicitly presented as accounting for representation, thus representational error, only from the perspective of an external observer—an analyzer or explainer of the system. But this leaves sui generis representation, as has to have emerged in evolution, unaddressed. Further, it leaves the representations of the analyzer or observer unaddressed (Bickhard 2004a, 2009a, in preparation; Bickhard and Terveen 1995).

  20. The allusion to Gibson is deliberate, and is elaborated in Bickhard and Richie (1983) and elsewhere.

  21. See (Piaget 1954; Bickhard 1988a; Bickhard and Campbell 1989).

  22. This amounts to a kind of functional-dynamic version of implicit definition (Bickhard 2009a).

  23. Consistent with this, in the development of understandings of modality in children, we find an early phase of a lack of coordinated differentiation among modalities, not one of an absence of modality to which modality is later added (Piaget 1987; Bickhard 1988b).

  24. A term for which I am indebted to a conversation with Raymundo Morado.

  25. Situation conventions do not constitute the only resolutions of mutual “social” situations: I may be only interested in killing you, for example, perhaps even without you ever realizing that we are in a mutual situation, and certainly without a coordination problem solution. Or I may be interested in deceiving you in a con game or espionage move, in which I may want you to think that some conventions are in place, but in which I intend to violate the purported coordinative resolution—there is a situation in which or level at which I intend to deviate from the purported coordination. More commonly, we take a social situation to constitute an organization of conventional frameworks, but discover in the course of interacting that there are senses in which we are not in full accord. These most commonly yield attempts to restore or repair situation conventions, but can also yield a destruction of all but the most minimal frameworks for competition or conflict (Bickhard, forthcoming).

  26. One manifestation of this is that even truth purportedly becomes a factual, non-normative property—e.g., a factual matter of Tarskian correspondences (or not) (Campbell 1992, forthcoming).

  27. A more complete model of values can be found elsewhere (e.g., Campbell and Bickhard 1986; Bickhard 2006, in preparation). This model requires, in its turn, a model of reflective consciousness (Bickhard 2005).

  28. He perhaps partially recognized this tangle of problems, especially the weak arguments deriving moral principles from the rational and reasoning nature of human beings, in his point that morality in this life would be rewarded in the afterlife—and that the necessity for such a balancing of justice in an afterlife is a reason for believing in an afterlife.

References

  • Aitchison IJR (1985) Nothing’s plenty: the vacuum in modern quantum field theory. Contemp Phys 26(4):333–391

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berger PL, Luckmann T (1966) The social construction of reality. Doubleday, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard MH (1980) Cognition, convention, and communication. Praeger Publishers, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard MH (1988a) Piaget on variation and selection models: structuralism, logical necessity, and interactivism. Hum Dev 31:274–312

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard MH (1988b) The necessity of possibility and necessity: Rev Piaget’s Possibility Necessity. Harv Educ Rev 58(4):502–507

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard MH (1992a) How does the environment affect the person? In: Winegar LT, Valsiner J (eds) Children’s development within social contexts: metatheory and theory. Erlbaum, Hillsdale, pp 63–92

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard MH (1992b) Scaffolding and self scaffolding: central aspects of development. In: Winegar LT, Valsiner J (eds) Children’s development within social contexts: research and methodology. Erlbaum, Hillsdale, pp 33–52

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard MH (1993) Representational content in humans and machines. J Exp Theor Artif Intell 5:285–333

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard MH (1996) Troubles with computationalism. In: O’Donohue W, Kitchener RF (eds) The philosophy of psychology. Sage, London, pp 173–183

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard MH (2000) Emergence. In: Andersen PB, Emmeche C, Finnemann NO, Christiansen PV (eds) Downward causation. University of Aarhus Press, Aarhus, pp 322–348

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard MH (2002) Critical principles: on the negative side of rationality. New Ideas Psychol 20:1–34

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard MH (2004a) Process and emergence: normative function and representation. Axiomathes: Int J Ontol Cogn Syst 14:135–169. Reprinted from: Bickhard MH (2003) Process and emergence: normative function and representation. In: Seibt J (ed) Process theories: crossdisciplinary studies in dynamic categories. Kluwer Academic, Dordrecht, pp 121–155

  • Bickhard MH (2004b) The social ontology of persons. In: Carpendale JIM, Muller U (eds) Social interaction and the development of knowledge. Erlbaum, Mahwah, pp 111–132

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard MH (2005) Consciousness and reflective consciousness. Philos Psychol 18(2):205–218

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard MH (2006) Developmental normativity and normative development. In: Smith L, Voneche J (eds) Norms in human development. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 57–76

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard MH (2008a) Are you social? The ontological and developmental emergence of the person. In: Müller U, Carpendale JIM, Budwig N, Sokol B (eds) Social life and social knowledge. Taylor & Francis, New York, pp 17–42

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard MH (2008b) Social ontology as convention. Topoi 27(1–2):139–149

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard MH (2009a) The interactivist model. Synthese 166(3):547–591

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard MH (2009b) Interactivism. In: Symons J, Calvo P (eds) The routledge companion to philosophy of psychology. Routledge, London, pp 346–359

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard MH (2009c) Some remarks on process metaphysics and representation. Cybern Hum Knowing 15(3–4):71–74

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard MH (in preparation) The whole person: toward a naturalism of persons—contributions to an ontological psychology

  • Bickhard MH, Campbell RL (1989) Interactivism and genetic epistemology. Arch Psychol 57(221):99–121

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard MH, Campbell RL (1996) Topologies of learning and development. New Ideas Psychol 14(2):111–156

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard MH, Campbell DT (2003) Variations in variation and selection: the ubiquity of the variation-and-selective retention ratchet in emergent organizational complexity. Found Sci 8(3):215–282

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard MH, Richie DM (1983) On the nature of representation: a case study of James Gibson’s theory of perception. Praeger Publishers, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard MH, Terveen L (1995) Foundational issues in artificial intelligence and cognitive science: impasse and solution. Elsevier Scientific, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Bonnay D (2008) Logicality and invariance. Bull Symb Log 14(1):29–68

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Busse R (2009) Humean supervenience, vectorial fields, and the spinning sphere. Dialectica 63(4):449–489

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butterfield J (2006) Against Pointillisme about mechanics. Br J Philos Sci 57:709–753

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell DT (1974) Evolutionary epistemology. In: Schilpp PA (ed) The philosophy of karl popper. Open Court, LaSalle, pp 413–463

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell RJ (1992) Truth and historicity. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell RJ (2009a) A process-based model for an interactive ontology. Synthese 166(3):453–477

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell RJ (2009b) The emergence of action. New Ideas Psychol 28:283–295

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell RJ (forthcoming) The concept of truth

  • Campbell RJ, Bickhard MH (this issue) Physicalism, emergence, and downward causation. Axiomathes

  • Campbell RL, Bickhard MH (1986) Knowing levels and developmental stages. Contributions to human development. Karger, Basel

    Google Scholar 

  • Cao TY (1999) Conceptual foundations of quantum field theory. U. of Cambridge Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen WD, Bickhard MH (2002) The process dynamics of normative function. Monist 85(1):3–28

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (2001) Mindware. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins R (1996) Representations, targets, and attitudes. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Damasio AR (1995) Descartes’ error: emotion, reason, and the human brain. Putnam, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies PCW (1984) Particles do not exist. In: Christensen SM (ed) Quantum theory of gravity. Adam Hilger, Bristol, pp 66–77

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey J (1960/1929) The quest for certainty. Capricorn Books, New York

  • Dretske FI (1988) Explaining behavior. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Fowers BJ (2010) Introduction to a eudaimonic ontology. Presented at the Mid-Winter Meeting of the Society for Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology, Miami, FL, March 2010

  • Gill M-L (1989) Aristotle on substance. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Graham DW (2006) Explaining the cosmos. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Halvorson H, Clifton R (2002) No place for particles in relativistic quantum theories? Philos Sci 69(1):1–28

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hooker CA (1992) Physical intelligibility, projection, objectivity and completeness: the divergent ideals of Bohr and Einstein. Br J Philos Sci 42:491–511

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hooker CA (2009) Interaction and bio-cognitive order. Synthese 166:513–546

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hooker CA (forthcoming) Complex systems handbook: introductory essay. In: Hooker C (ed) Handbook of philosophy of science. Philosophy of complex systems, vol 10. Elsevier, Amsterdam

  • Hooker CA (this issue) Rationality as effective organisation of interaction and its naturalist framework

  • Huggett N (2000) Philosophical foundations of quantum field theory. Br J Philos Sci 51(supplement):617–637

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Humphrey NK (1976) The social function of intellect. In: Bateson PPG, Hinde RA (eds) Growing points in ethology. Cambridge University Press, London, pp 303–317

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson F (1998) From metaphysics to ethics. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Juarrero A (1999) Dynamics in action: intentional behavior as a complex system. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Karakostas V (2009) Humean supervenience in the light of contemporary science. Metaphysica 10:1–33

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim J (1998) Mind in a physical world. MIT, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim J (2005) Physicalism or something near enough. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman J, Ross D (2007) Every thing must go. Oxford Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis DK (1969) Convention. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis DK (1986a) Introduction. In: Philosophical papers (vol. 2). (ix-xvii). Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Lewis DK (1986b) On the plurality of worlds. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis DK (1994) Humean supervenience debugged. Mind New Ser 103(412):473–490

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loewer B (1996) Humean supervenience. Philos Top 24:101–127

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre A (1998) A short history of ethics. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Mann W-R (2000) The discovery of things. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin J (2003) Emergent persons. New Ideas Psychol 21:85–99

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin J, Sugarman J, Thompson J (2003) Psychology and the question of agency. SUNY Press, Albany

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin J, Sugarman JH, Hickinbottom S (2010) Persons: understanding psychological selfhood and agency. Springer, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin B, Bennett K (2005) Supervenience. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/supervenience/

  • Millikan RG (1984) Language, thought, and other biological categories. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan RG (1993) White queen psychology and other essays for alice. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Mostepanenko VM, Trunov NN, Znajek RL (1997) The Casimir effect and its applications. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Oppy G (2000) “Humean” supervenience? Philos Stud: Int J Philos Anal Tradit 101(1):77–105

    Google Scholar 

  • Palmer J (2010) Parmenides and presocratic philosophy. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget J (1954) The construction of reality in the child. Basic, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Piaget J (1987) Possibility and necessity, vol 1 and 2. U. of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis

    Google Scholar 

  • Poli R (forthcoming-a) On the concept of a person: the social nature of persons. In: Nicolescu B, Stavinschi M (eds) Transdisciplinary approaches of the dialogue between science, art, and religion in the Europe of tomorrow

  • Poli R (forthcoming-b) Three concepts of person. In: Action theories: social action, theory of mind, philosophy of action, religious action

  • Robinson D (1989) Matter, motion, and humean supervenience. Australas J Philos 67(4):394–409

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rouse J (2002) How scientific practices matter: reclaiming philosophical naturalism. U. of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Schelling TC (1963) The strategy of conflict. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Sciama DW (1991) The physical significance of the vacuum state of a quantum field. In: Saunders S, Brown HR (eds) The philosophy of vacuum. Clarendon, Oxford, pp 137–158

    Google Scholar 

  • Seibt J (2003) Free process theory: towards a typology of occurings. In: Seibt J (ed) Process theories: crossdisciplinary studies in dynamic categories. Kluwer Academic, Dordrecht, pp 23–55

    Google Scholar 

  • Seibt J (2009) Forms of emergent interaction in General Process Theory. Synthese 166(3):479–512

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sher GY (1991) The bounds of logic. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Skewes J, Hooker CA (2009) Bio-agency and the problem of action. Biol Philos 24(3):283–300

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smolin L (2001) Three roads to quantum gravity. Basic, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterba JP (2008) Completing the Kantian Project: from rationality to equality. Proc Addresses Am Philos Assoc 82(2):47–83

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppe F (1977) The structure of scientific theories, 2nd edn. University of Illinois Press, Urbana, Ill

    Google Scholar 

  • Tarski A (1986) What are logical notions? Text of a 1966 lecture, ed. J. Corcoran. Hist Philos Log 7:143–154

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Teller P (1986) Relational holism and quantum mechanics. Br J Philos Sci 37:71–81

    Google Scholar 

  • Teller P (1989) Relativity, relational holism, and the bell inequalities. In: Cushing J, McMullin E (eds) Philosophical consequences of quantum theory: reflections on Bell’s theorem. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, pp 208–223

    Google Scholar 

  • Tiles JE (1990) Dewey. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg S (1977) The search for unity, notes for a history of quantum field theory. Daedalus 106(4):17–35

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg S (1995) The quantum theory of fields, vol 1 foundations. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler M, Clark A (1999) Genic representation: reconciling content and causal complexity. Br J Philos Sci 50(1):103–135

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt W (1997) Aggregativity: reductive heuristics for finding emergence. Philos Sci 64:S372–S384. Reprinted In: Bedau MA, Humphreys P (eds) (2008) Emergence—contemporary readings in philosophy and science. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 99–110

  • Woodward J (2003) Making things happen. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Richard Campbell, Cliff Hooker, and Susan Schneider for improvements on earlier drafts.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mark H. Bickhard.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Bickhard, M.H. Some Consequences (and Enablings) of Process Metaphysics. Axiomathes 21, 3–32 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-010-9130-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-010-9130-z

Keywords

Navigation