Skip to main content
Log in

A minimal extension of Bayesian decision theory

  • Published:
Theory and Decision Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Savage denied that Bayesian decision theory applies in large worlds. This paper proposes a minimal extension of Bayesian decision theory to a large-world context that evaluates an event \(E\) by assigning it a number \(\pi (E)\) that reduces to an orthodox probability for a class of measurable events. The Hurwicz criterion evaluates \(\pi (E)\) as a weighted arithmetic mean of its upper and lower probabilities, which we derive from the measurable supersets and subsets of \(E\). The ambiguity aversion reported in experiments on the Ellsberg paradox is then explained by assigning a larger weight to the lower probability of winning than to the upper probability. However, arguments are given here that would make anything but equal weights irrational when using the Hurwicz criterion. The paper continues by embedding the Hurwicz criterion in an extension of expected utility theory that we call expectant utility.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Savage (1954) own candidate is the minimax regret criterion. Manski (2013) offers a vigorous defense of this proposal, but it seems to me a non-starter for a theory of rational decision because it fails to satisfy the Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives.

  2. European roulette has no 00. Bets on low or high remain on the table when 0 occurs.

  3. Vitali’s argument needs the Axiom of Choice, without which all sets on the circle can be taken to be Lebesgue measurable (assuming “inaccessible cardinals” exist—Solovay 1970). But to deny the Axiom of Choice would seem to deny the ethos that led Savage to insist on the relevance of large worlds by assuming that our current formalism is adequate to describe anything that nature might throw at us.

  4. His theorem has a countable set of exceptional points, but the later work of Banach and Tarski perfected his result on the way to proving their even more spectacular paradox.

  5. Postulate 2 does not say that the way the gamble (1) itself is structured is irrelevant, otherwise it would conflict with our later denial of Postulate 8.

  6. All limits in Postulate 3 are taken from within \(D\). If \((0,0)\) were excluded from the set \(D\), the theorem would fail as \(v(x,y)=x^{1-\alpha }y^{\alpha }\) would remain a possibility.

  7. \(f(x+y)=f(x)+f(y)\) implies \(f'(x+y)=f'(x)\). So \(f'(y)=f'(0)\) and \(f(y)=f'(0)y\).

  8. The identity does not hold if \(E\) is unmeasured and \({\alpha }\not ={1 \over 2}\), because implies that \(1=(1-{\alpha })p+{\alpha }P + (1-{\alpha })(1-P)+{\alpha }(1-p) = 1+(2\alpha -1)(P-p)\), where \(p\) and \(P\) are the lower and upper probabilities of \(E\).

  9. Postulate 9 does not even imply that a gamble can be identified with \({\mathcal{P}}\) when all the prizes are \({\mathcal{P}}\). But when \(\mathcal{M}\not =\emptyset \) and so \(B\) is a measured event, this conclusion follows from requiring that Bayesian decision theory holds for gambles constructed only from measured events.

  10. Note that we are asking more than that \(\pi \) be a measure on \(\mathcal{M}\). In particular, although our standard normalization of VN&M utility functions ensures that \(\pi (\emptyset )=0\) and \(\pi (B)=1\) and so \(\pi \) is always a measure on \(\{\emptyset , B\}\), it need not be true that \(\{\emptyset , B\}\subseteq \mathcal{M}\). Example 5 is a case in which \(\mathcal{M}\) is taken to be empty (Sect. 2.1).

References

  • Anscombe, F., & Auman, R. (1963). A definition of subjective probability. Annals of Mathematical Statistics, 34, 199–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K. (1971). Essays on the theory of risk bearing. Chicago: Markham.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K., & Hurwicz, L. (1972). An optimality criterion for decision-making under ignorance. In C. Carter & J. Ford (Eds.), Uncertainty and expectations in economics. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Binmore, K. (2005). Natural justice. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Binmore, K. (2009). Rational decisions. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chernoff, H. (1954). Rational selection of decision functions. Econometrica, 22, 422–443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghirardato, P., Maccheroni, F., Marinacci, M. (2002). Ambiguity from the differential viewpoint. Social Science Working Paper 1130.

  • Gillies, D. (2000). Philosophical theories of probability. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Good, I. J. (1983). Good thinking: The foundations of probability and its applications. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halmos, P. (1950). Measure theory. Princeton: Van Nostrand.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Halpern, J., & Fagin, R. (1992). Two views of belief: Belief as generalized probability and belief as evidence. Artificial Intelligence, 54, 275–3178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurwicz, L. (1951). Optimality criteria for decision making under ignorance. Cowles Commission Discussion Paper, Statistics 370.

  • Keeney, R., & Raiffa, H. (1975). Additive value functions. In J. Ponssard, et al. (Eds.), Theorie de la decision et applications. Paris: Fondation national pour L’Eneignment de la Gestion des Enterprises.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klibanoff, P., Marinacci, M., & Mukerji, S. (2005). A smooth model of decision-making under ambiguity. Econometrica, 73, 1849–1892.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luce, R., & Raiffa, H. (1957). Games and decisions. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manski, C. (2013). Public policy in an uncertain world. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milnor, J. (1954). Games against nature. In R. Thrall, C. Coombs, & R. Davies (Eds.), Decision processes. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Savage, L. (1954). The foundations of statistics. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmeidler, D. (1989). Subjective probability and expected utility without additivity. Econometrica, 57, 571–585.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmeidler, D. (2004). Subjective probability and expected utility without additivity. In I. Gilboa (Ed.), Uncertainty in economic theory: Essays in honor of David Schmeidler’s 65th birthday. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shackle, G. (1949). Expectation in economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solovay, R. (1970). A model for set theory in which every set of real numbers is Lebesgue measurable. Annals of Mathematics, 92, 1–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P. (1974). The measurement of belief. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society, 2, 160–191.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagon, S. (1985). The Banach-Tarski paradox. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Widder, D. (1941). The Laplace transform. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful for funding from the European Research Council under the European Community’s Seventh Framework Programme (FP7/2007-2013)/ERC grant 295449. I am also grateful to David Kelsey and Karl Schlag for commenting on a previous version of the paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ken Binmore.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Binmore, K. A minimal extension of Bayesian decision theory. Theory Decis 80, 341–362 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-015-9505-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-015-9505-0

Keywords

Navigation