Skip to main content
Log in

Life Sciences for Philosophers and Philosophy for Life Scientists: What Should We Teach?

  • Notes from the Field
  • Published:
Biological Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Following recent debate on the relations between philosophy of science and the sciences, we wish to draw attention to some actual ways of training both young philosophers of science and young life scientists and clinicians. First, we recall a successful case of training philosophers of the life sciences in a strictly scientific environment. Second, after a brief review of the reasons why life scientists and clinicians are currently asking for more ethics, more methodology of science, and more philosophy of science in the training of life scientists and clinicians, we present two training models that could spur the discussion on how to meet the requests coming from the scientific community. We argue that in order to reflect on mutual relations between philosophy of science and the sciences and to foster proper interactions, issues regarding (1) the topics considered, (2) the features of educational curricula, and (3) the institutional organizations should be addressed jointly.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There is a long and classical tradition (Poincaré, Duhem, Campbell, Mach, Boltzmann, Hertz, Enriques, Bernard, Popper, some post-Popperians, etc.) according to which philosophy of science is mainly concerned with methodological/epistemological issues, while the ontological, aesthetic, ethical, and political issues are sometimes tackled (see Poincaré on ethics, Popper on politics, etc.) but considered self-contained intersecting disciplines. We do not want to enter into this debate here, which surely would deserve an ampler space.

  2. See, e.g., Quintero (2014) and Rehg and SmithBattler (2015).

  3. From a review of PubMed, it appears that occurrences of “philosophy of science” have constantly increased in the last few years as follows: 2015: 102; 2016: 109; 2017: 117; 2018: 139; 2019 (half year): 82. Joint occurrences of “philosophy of science” and “education” have also shown a slight increase: 2015: 9; 2016: 6; 2017: 12; 2018: 12; 2019 (half year): 7.

  4. According to PubMed, “ethics” has been directly addressed by many works in the last few years, with a basically constant trend (apart from a decline in 2018). Occurrences in works: 2015: 937; 2016: 943; 2017: 947; 2018: 102; 2019 (half year): 472.

  5. See, e.g., Spike (1991).

  6. See, e.g., Andreoletti and Maugeri (2019).

  7. G. Testa was appointed as deputy director.

  8. A remarkably large number of papers having among their authors former students of this program have appeared in high-impact journals. We cannot list them all. Let us just recall, e.g., Maugeri and Blasimme (2011), Nardini and Sprenger (2013), Germain et al. (2014), Boem et al. (2016), and Sanchini et al. (2016). Various other publications appeared in such journals as: AJOB Neuroscience; Bioethics; Biological Theory; Biotechnology Journal; Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics; European Journal of Cancer; Journal of Assisted Reproduction and Genetics; Journal of Medical Ethics; Lancet Oncology; Medicine, Healthcare, and Philosophy; Minds and Machines; Multidisciplinary Respiratory Medicine; PLOS Biology; Public Health Ethics; Studies in History and Philosophy of Biology & Biomedical Sciences; The American Journal of Bioethics; Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics; and so on, as well as in a number of collected volumes.

  9. Actually, not all of these works were read in their entirety. Chapters and excerpts were appropriately chosen.

  10. There has also been a FOLSATEC marriage and now there is a FOLSATEC child!

  11. See the paper in PNAS written by a group of scientists and philosophers (L. Laplane, P. Mantovani, R. Adolphs, H. Chang, A. Mantovani, M. McFall-Ngai, C. Rovelli, and E. Sober): Laplane et al. (2019).

  12. It is also worth recalling Grüne-Yanoff (2014), who provided a detailed analysis of the limits of the standard teaching of the science curriculum, and suggested a few directions in which it should be revised.

  13. There is a huge literature on scientific frauds and misconduct. See, for example, Corbyn (2012), Edwards and Siddhartha (2017), Yong et al. (2013), Hartgerink (2015), Horbach and Halffman (2016), and Ioannidis (2011).

  14. See, e.g., Fang and Casadevall (2011), Steen et al. (2013), Resnik et al. (2015), and Wager and Williams (2011). See also: http://www.the-scientist.com/?articles.view/articleNo/44895/title/The-Top-10-Retractions-of-2015/ and http://www.the-scientist.com/?articles.view/articleNo/47813/title/Top-10-Retractions-of-2016/.

  15. Here there is an enormous literature. As an example of contemporary debate, see what is said about He Jiankui's announcement and the first germline-edited babies through CRISPR technique: Cyranoski and Ledford (2018) and Cyranoski (2018), and the editorial on “How to respond to CRISPR babies” (Nature 564, 5 (2018), https://doi.org/10.1038/d41586-018-07634-0); Cohen (2018); Normile D (2018).

  16. See, for example, McCoy and Emanuel (2017), Fontanarosa and Bauchner (2017), Thornton (2017), Fineberg (2017), and Ginsburg and Levinson (2017).

  17. As is known, replicability concerns the possibility to reobtain the same results with the same experimental set up and procedure by the same researcher in the same lab; reproducibility regards the possibility to reobtain the same results with a different experimental set up and procedure by a different researcher in a different lab.

  18. It is so pervasive that there is also a Wikipedia entry on this: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Replication_crisis.

  19. Boniolo and Vaccari (2012), Andreoletti (2016), Begley and Ioannidis (2015), Casadevall and Fang (2010), Jarvis and Williams (2016), and Freedman and Inglese (2014). See also the special issue of Nature (2017) on “Challenges in irreproducible research”; and the manifesto for reproducible results, Munafò et al. (2017) and Freedman et al. (2015).

  20. The irreproducibility of scientific results is such a clearly perceived issue that we are seeing the birth of new funding agencies exactly devoted to replication of scientific results. See, for example, Baker (2016).

  21. See, for example, concerns about drugs (e.g., Andreoletti and Teira 2019).

  22. Of course, here we cannot avoid quoting Ioannidis (2005), whose impact on public opinion has also been enormous, as an article in The Economist of Oct 19, 2013, shows (“How science goes wrong. Scientific research has changed the world. Now it needs to change itself”). For the perception of the problem, see also Nuzzo (2014).

  23. To recall just a few, for research groups see, e.g., the “Theory and Method in Biosciences” research group (University of Sydney); “ImmunoConcEpT” group (University of Bordeaux); and the PhiInBioMed network. With respect to teaching, examples are provided both by wide initiatives—such as the R3 Graduate Science Initiative “Critically ‘Thinking Science’” at Johns Hopkins University (Maryland, USA) led by Gundula Bosch—or by the insertion of specific courses into curricula – as, e.g., the course on “The science and its philosophy,” delivered by the Department of Biology at the University of Lund (Sweden), and mandatory for all PhD students in biology. See also what is done in the medical schools of the University of Redlands (California) by James Krueger and of the University of Alabama (USA) by Ted Poston. Another important educational example, where biological and biomedical aspects are considered together with humanistic aspects, is given by the European Advanced Seminar in the Philosophy of the Life Sciences (EASPLS), which has been held every two years (the last two times at the Konrad Lorenz Institute for Evolution and Cognition Research in Austria) since 2008.

  24. On some features of conventional curricula, see Grüne-Yanoff (2014), § 2.

  25. See, e.g., the major/minor university system.

  26. While strongly supporting the transfer of some scientific knowledge to philosophers and philosophical, conceptual, and methodological tools to scientists, we cannot forget that the enterprise requires strong commitment. Building, for example, a common language and theoretical framework is far from trivial, and often requires selecting the proper degree of simplification—such that, while keeping the core message totally intact, sometimes there is no need to be familiar with all the subtleties that only major experts in the field command.

References

  • Altenberg L (2015) Statistical problems in a paper on variation in cancer risk among tissues, and new discoveries. arXiv:1501.04605

  • Amey L, Donald KJ, Teodorczuk A (2017) Teaching clinical reasoning to medical students. Br J Hosp Med 78(7):399–401

    Google Scholar 

  • Andreoletti M (2016) Reproducibility: hallmark labs with a replicability record. Nature 537:34

    Google Scholar 

  • Andreoletti M, Maugeri P (2019) Does medicine need philosophy? Oral Dis 25:1419–1422. https://doi.org/10.1111/odi.13143

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andreoletti M, Teira D (2019) Rules versus standards: what are the costs of epistemic norms in drug regulation? Sci Technol Human Values 44:1093–1115. https://doi.org/10.1177/0162243919828070

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baker M (2016) Dutch agency launches first grants programme dedicated to replication; three-year pilot devotes €3 million to verifying other studies. Nat News. https://doi.org/10.1038/nature.2016.20287

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Begley CG, Ioannidis JP (2015) Reproducibility in science: improving the standard for basic and preclinical research. Circ Res 116:116–126

    Google Scholar 

  • Boem F, Ratti E, Andreoletti M, Boniolo G (2016) Why genes are like lemons. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 57:88–95

    Google Scholar 

  • Boniolo G, Vaccari T (2012) Publishing: alarming shift away from sharing results. Nature 488:157

    Google Scholar 

  • Boon M, Van Baalen S (2019) Epistemology for interdisciplinary research—shifting philosophical paradigms of science. Eur J Philos Sci 9:16. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-018-0242-4

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bosch G (2018) Train PhD students to be thinkers not just specialists. Nature 554(7692):277. https://doi.org/10.1038/d41586-018-01853-1

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bosch G, Casadevall A (2017) Graduate biomedical science education needs a new philosophy. mBio 8:e01539. https://doi.org/10.1128/mBio.01539-17

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Casadevall A (2015) Put the “Ph” back in PhD. Johns Hopkins Public Health, Summer 2015. http://magazine.jhsph.edu/2015/summer/forum/rethinking-put-the-ph-back-in-phd/

  • Casadevall A, Fang FC (2010) Reproducible science. Infect Immun 78:4972–4975

    Google Scholar 

  • Casadevall A, Fang FC (2012) Reforming science: methodological and cultural reforms. Infect Immun 80:891–896

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen J (2018) What now for human genome editing? Science 362(6419):1090–1092

    Google Scholar 

  • Corbyn Z (2012) Misconduct is the main cause of life-sciences retractions. Opaque announcements in journals can hide fraud, study finds. Nature 490:21

    Google Scholar 

  • Couzin-Frankel J (2013) Shaking up science. Science 339:386–389

    Google Scholar 

  • Cyranoski D (2018) First CRISPR babies: six questions that remain. Nature. https://doi.org/10.1038/d41586-018-07607-3

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cyranoski D, Ledford H (2018) Genome-edited baby claim provokes international outcry. Nature 563:607–608. https://doi.org/10.1038/d41586-018-07545-0

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edwards MA, Siddhartha R (2017) Academic research in the 21st century: maintaining scientific integrity in a climate of perverse incentives and hypercompetition. Environ Eng Sci 234:51–61

    Google Scholar 

  • Elizondo Omaña RE et al (2010) Teaching skills to promote clinical reasoning in early basic science courses. Anat Sci Educ 3(5):267–271

    Google Scholar 

  • Fang FC, Casadevall A (2011) Retracted science and the retraction index. Infect Immun 79:3855–3859

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferretti G, Linkeviciute A, Boniolo G (2017) Comprehending and communicating statistics in breast cancer screening. Ethical implications and potential solutions. In: Gadebusch-Bondio M, Spöring F, Gordon J-S (eds) Medical ethics, prediction and prognosis: interdipliplinary perspectives. Routledge, New York, pp 30–41

    Google Scholar 

  • Fineberg HV (2017) Conflict of interest: why does it matter? JAMA 317(17):1717–1718

    Google Scholar 

  • Fontanarosa P, Bauchner H (2017) Conflict of interest and medical journals. JAMA 317(17):1768–1771

    Google Scholar 

  • Freedman LP, Inglese J (2014) The increasing urgency for standards in basic biologic. Cancer Res 74:4024–4029

    Google Scholar 

  • Freedman LP, Cockburn IM, Simcoe TS (2015) The economics of reproducibility in preclinical research. PLoS Biol 13:e1002165. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pbio.1002165

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fulford W (1991) The potential of medicine as a resource for philosophy. Theor Med 12(1):81–85

    Google Scholar 

  • Gay S, Bartlett M, McKinley R (2013) Teaching clinical reasoning to medical students. Clin Teach 10(5):308–312

    Google Scholar 

  • Germain P-L, Ratti E, Boem F (2014) Junk or functional DNA? ENCODE and the function controversy. Biol Philos 29:807–831

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginsburg S, Levinson W (2017) Is there a conflict of interest? JAMA 317(17):1796–1797

    Google Scholar 

  • Grüne-Yanoff T (2014) Teaching philosophy of science to scientists: why, what and how. Eur J Philos Sci 4:115–134

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartgerink CH (2015) Research misconduct: speed translation of misconduct reports. Nature 522:419

    Google Scholar 

  • Horbach SPJM, Halffman W (2016) Promoting virtue or punishing fraud: mapping contrasts in the language of ‘scientific integrity’. Sci Eng Ethics 23(6):1461–1485. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-016-9858-y

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ioannidis JP (2005) Why most published research findings are false. PLoS Med 2:e124

    Google Scholar 

  • Ioannidis JP (2011) An epidemic of false claims. Competition and conflicts of interest distort too many medical findings. Sci Am 304:16

    Google Scholar 

  • Jarvis MF, Williams M (2016) Irreproducibility in preclinical biomedical research: perceptions, uncertainties, and knowledge gaps. Trends Pharmacol Sci 37:290–302

    Google Scholar 

  • Kurzenhäuser S, Hoffrage U (2002) Teaching Bayesian reasoning: an evaluation of a classroom tutorial for medical students. Med Teach 24(5):516–521

    Google Scholar 

  • Laplane L et al (2019) Why science needs philosophy. PNAS 116(10):3948–3952

    Google Scholar 

  • Loong T-W (2003) Understanding sensitivity and specificity with the right side of the brain. BMJ 327:716–719

    Google Scholar 

  • Losee J (1972) A historical introduction to the philosophy of science. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Maugeri P, Blasimme A (2011) Humanised models of cancer in molecular medicine: the experimental control of disanalogies. Hist Philos Life Sci 33:603–622

    Google Scholar 

  • McCoy MS, Emanuel EJ (2017) Why there are no “potential” conflicts of interest. JAMA 317(17):1721–1722

    Google Scholar 

  • Munafò MR, Nosek BA, Bishop DVM, Button KS, Chambers CD, Percie du Sert N et al (2017) A manifesto for reproducible science. Nat Hum Behav 1:0021

    Google Scholar 

  • Nardini C, Sprenger J (2013) Bias and conditioning in sequential medical trials. Philos Sci 80:1053–1064

    Google Scholar 

  • Normile D (2018) For China, a CRISPR first goes too far. Science 362(6419):1091

    Google Scholar 

  • Nuzzo R (2014) Scientific method: statistical errors. P values, the ‘gold standard’ of statistical validity, are not as reliable as many scientists assume. Nature 506:150–152

    Google Scholar 

  • Oldroyd R (1986) The arch of knowledge: an introductory study of the history of the philosophy and methodology of science. Routledge Kegan & Paul, Abingdon

    Google Scholar 

  • Pradeu T (2017) Thirty years of Biology & Philosophy: philosophy of which biology? Biol Philos 32(2):149–167

    Google Scholar 

  • Prather CM, Choate DM, Michel MJ, Crowl TA (2009) Putting the “Ph” back into “PhD”: framing graduate research in a theoretical context. Front Ecol Environ 7:389–390

    Google Scholar 

  • Quintero GA (2014) Medical education and the healthcare system—why does the curriculum need to be reformed? BMC Med 12:213. https://doi.org/10.1186/s12916-014-0213-3

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rehg E, SmithBattler L (2015) On to the ‘rough ground’: introducing doctoral students to philosophical perspectives on knowledge. Nurs Philos 16(2):98–109. https://doi.org/10.1111/nup.12077

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Resnik DB, Wager E, Kissling GE (2015) Retraction policies of top scientific journals ranked by impact factor. J Med Libr Assoc 103:136–139

    Google Scholar 

  • Sanchini V, Bonizzi G, Monturano M, Pece S, Viale G, Di Fiore PP et al (2016) Research biobanks: why information and information-based consents are not enough. Bioethics 30:260–271

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith R (2016) Medicine’s need for philosophy. In: the BMJ opinion. http://blogs.bmj.com/bmj/2016/04/08/richard-smith-medicines-need-for-philosophy/. Accessed 8 Apr 2016

  • Snow CP (1961) The two cultures and the scientific revolution: the Rede Lecture 1959. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

  • Spike J (1991) The need for teaching philosophy in medical education. Theor Med 12(4):359–365

    Google Scholar 

  • Steen RG, Casadevall A, Fang FC (2013) Why has the number of scientific retractions increased? PLoS ONE 8:e68397

    Google Scholar 

  • Thornton JP (2017) Conflict of interest and legal issues for investigators and authors. JAMA 317(17):1761–1762

    Google Scholar 

  • Velickovic V (2015) What everyone should know about statistical correlation. A common analytical error hinders biomedical research and misleads the public. Am Sci 103:26–29

    Google Scholar 

  • Wager E, Williams P (2011) Why and how do journals retract articles? An analysis of medline retractions 1988–2008. J Med Ethics 37:567–570

    Google Scholar 

  • Wegwarth O, Schwartz LM, Woloshin S, Gaissmaier W, Gigerenzer G (2012) Do physicians understand cancer screening statistics? A national survey of primary care physicians in the United States. Ann Intern Med 156:340–349

    Google Scholar 

  • Yong E, Ledford H, Van Norden R (2013) Research ethics: 3 ways to blow the whistle. Reporting suspicions of scientific fraud is rarely easy, but some paths are more effective than others. Nature 503:454–457

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank Thomas Pradeu for his useful comments on a previous version of the paper and three anonymous reviewers whose suggestions have helped to improve this article.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Giovanni Boniolo.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

This is the first of a series of field reports and other informal accounts of educational and other initiatives bridging philosophy of biology and the broader society that we plan to publish in Biological Theory.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Boniolo, G., Campaner, R. Life Sciences for Philosophers and Philosophy for Life Scientists: What Should We Teach?. Biol Theory 15, 1–11 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-019-00333-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-019-00333-7

Keywords

Navigation