- A party without cake is just a meeting.

Julia Child

1 Introduction

Restaurants, home kitchens, cafes, pubs, dining tables, takeout places, food trucks, food street vendors, markets, ice cream parlors, picnic areas, beaches, public squares, waiting rooms, gardens, backyards, cars, buses, trains, airplanes… This is only a short list of sites that human beings, nowadays and throughout history, have been using as spaces to eat and drink (Rawson & Shore 2019: 9–29). It is a list that evokes a complex history of eating practices,Footnote 1 more or less intentionally designed to accompany people’s everyday needs, toils, and leisures. We shall refer to these spaces with the expression gastrospaces, a neologism stressing the close ties between food and space.

In this paper, we set out to establish gastrospaces as a subject of scholarly inquiry as well as an item to include in policy agendas at local and non-local levels. We maintain that such spaces can be key sites of justice and injustice. The core of our argument points at their capacity to enable or hinder people’s ability to develop and exercise two fundamental moral powers, what John Rawls calls the “capacity for a sense of justice” and “the capacity to form, to revise, and rationally to pursue a conception of one’s rational advantage or good” (Rawls 2005: 19). For example, at the outset of her study on the importance of “table talk” for democratic agency and participation, Flammang (2016: 2) observes:

Eating is something we do frequently […]. Of course, there are cultural differences in rules about civil tables—who should speak, when and how; what behavior is acceptable; what topics are off limits; and how conflict should be resolved. Indeed, it is our daily exposure to the making, enforcing, and breaking of these rules that constitutes our daily doses of political awareness, growth, and transformation. It is at tables and in conversations that we make sense of the many layers of our experiences with political import.

Here we take a broader perspective than Flammang, by considering not only the conversational and “civil” dimensions of gastrospaces, but also the political issues surrounding the distinctively spatial dimensions of these sites—such as urban planning, design, access, and inclusion/exclusion—which raise important questions of justice.

Our approach combines the resources of analytical political philosophy and analytic ontology. On the one hand, it brings out the conceptual and ontological assumptions that implicitly underlie much political philosophical analysis; we focus specifically on the properties of gastrospaces to better understand where, when, and how it is possible to intervene in order to more effectively realize justice goals in such spaces. On the other hand, our approach employs political philosophy to develop a theoretical understanding of gastrospaces that is driven by (and aimed at realizing) specific justice goals, and which can help devise real-world interventions. Our aim is to provide a philosophical account of those entities that we think should be of special significance in public and academic discourse.

We begin (§2) by explaining what the value of gastrospaces is in relation to the development and exercise of the two moral powers, thus clarifying the relevance of our topic from the point of view of political philosophy.Footnote 2 This analysis, however, would be incomplete without a proper account of what gastrospaces are. More specifically, it would lack a clear understanding of the key components of such spaces, and of how this information could be used to design or modify them in order to advance the two moral powers. To this effect, in §3 we unfold a theoretical framework for gastrospaces, in three steps: first (§3.1), we show the limits of the concept of “third place;” second (§3.2), we lay out the foundations for an ontological model of gastrospaces, which maps out the most basic entities included within them; third (§3.3), we introduce five features of gastrospaces that integrate our ontological model and can help us to better understand whether and how the ontological properties of such spaces are linked to the development, exercise, and realization of the two moral powers.Footnote 3 As well as being theoretically innovative, our study can also provide a novel blueprint for real-world interventions regarding gastrospaces. We conclude (§4) by briefly illustrating how three potential categories of actors can benefit from our framework in relation to the design, use, and modification of gastrospaces: institutions, keepers, and users.

2 Justice and Gastrospaces

The importance of gastrospaces in shaping and cementing social relationships in contemporary societies is well known. The COVID-19 pandemic offers a clear example: widespread lockdowns in many countries forced the temporary closure of restaurants, cafes, and other eating spaces, thereby precluding the conditions for social gatherings (Bonotti et al. 2022; Bonotti and Zech 2021) and depriving many people of the opportunity to share significant meals and to engage in social interactions (e.g., see Ammar et al. 2020). Meanwhile, those restrictive measures also changed the way people ate at home and contributed to the development of new foodways such as digital commensality.Footnote 4 Yet, despite their importance, gastrospaces have not been systematically examined within normative political philosophy: What is their role in a theory of justice? What kinds of moral goals do they help to realize?

To address these and related questions we take a broadly Rawlsian perspective grounded in Rawls’s influential account of the two “moral powers:” “the capacity for a sense of justice” and “the capacity to form, to revise, and rationally to pursue a conception of one’s rational advantage or good” (2005: 19). In order to be able to develop and exercise their two moral powers, all individuals need access to certain primary goods, i.e., “all-purpose means,” which include basic rights and liberties, the opportunity to access positions of power and responsibility, income and wealth, and the social bases of self-respect. The latter provides each person with “a…sense of his own value, his secure conviction that his conception of his good, his plan of life, is worth carrying out…[as well as]…a confidence in one’s ability, so far as it is within one’s power, to fulfill one’s intentions” (Rawls 1999: 386).

Our choice to focus on the two Rawlsian moral powers rests on their marked “thinness” and flexibility: all individuals possess them regardless of their conception of the good and their legal status (e.g., regardless of whether they are legal citizens or resident non-citizens).Footnote 5 These aspects (i.e., thinness and flexibility) also afford us key theoretical flexibility: they ensure that our analysis also applies to transient or “invisible” individuals, such as travelers and illegal residents.Footnote 6

On what grounds, then, can we argue that gastrospaces are a legitimate concern of theories of justice? To answer this question, we follow Cordelli (2015: 94). In her analysis of justice and relational resources, she suggests three criteria for establishing whether a good should be considered as primary and, therefore, a concern of theories of justice:

  1. (1)

    The good should be “generally necessary [although not sufficient] for the development and exercise of (at least one of) the two moral powers.”

  2. (2)

    The good should be “valuable across a variety of conceptions of the good, without their value being grounded in any such conception.”

  3. (3)

    Social institutions should play a role in the distribution of the good.

In what follows, we set out to show that gastrospaces meet each of the three criteria.Footnote 7 We begin by considering the first criterion in connection with both moral powers, starting from the second of such powers.

2.1 The First Criterion: Gastrospaces and the Two Moral Powers

Gastrospaces are crucial for individuals’ ability to exercise their second moral power, i.e. to realize their life plans and conceptions of the good, insofar as they provide key sites where to prepare or consume food, both at home and in public. For example, access to certain gastrospaces, such as soup kitchens (e.g., see Marovelli 2019), serves to realize food security, a basic necessity for any individual to be able to pursue their conception of the good, whatever the latter might be. Likewise, other gastrospaces, like home kitchens, are not only an effective means for guaranteeing the right to cook one’s own food, but also spaces where individuals and groups gain or even reconstruct a sense of stability and belonging (Supski 2006; Longhurst et al. 2009), or foster collective memories and identities rooted in cultural and familiar practices (Meah and Jackson 2016). In this sense, gastrospaces can promote individuals’ inherently valuable relationships and goals as is also the case, for example, with mosque and synagogue canteens serving halal and kosher meals, which provide Muslims and Jews with access to food that complies with norms central to their religious faiths and cultural identities (Barnhill et al. 2014).Footnote 8 Or they can enable self-expression and creativity,Footnote 9 leisure, or the aesthetic appreciation of food. In other cases, gastrospaces can help realize instrumentally valuable goals and relationships, e.g., by advancing people’s work opportunitiesFootnote 10 or providing them with access to networks of trust, care, emotional support, or social influence (cf. Cordelli 2015: 94–96).

Gastrospaces can also provide individuals with the social bases of self-respect. When eating out is a widespread practice in a society, for example, not being able to enjoy it can seriously undermine a person’s self-respectFootnote 11—think, for example, of a child who can never eat the food linked to their culinary traditions outside their home because it is either not available anywhere or because consuming it is frowned upon even by acquaintances and friends. Or consider how refugee camps not equipped with sufficient cooking technologies can have a negative impact on the self-respect of those who live there (see, e.g., Barbieri et al. 2017 who offer an overview of cooking facilities in refugee camps).

Let us now consider the first moral power, i.e., the capacity for a sense of justice, and assess whether and how gastrospaces can help enhance it: how can gastrospaces help people understand and act according to the moral duties they owe to each other? Restaurants that advance a conception of justice centered on animal welfare by only serving vegan or vegetarian food,Footnote 12 or those that charge different prices for the same meal based on customers’ income,Footnote 13 are instances of gastrospaces that can help individuals to act in ways that further what they consider justice goals. For example, they can help cement bonds between fellow vegans or vegetarians, or between those who want to fight socio-economic inequalities, and potentially encourage other people to also pursue those justice goals. Consider, also, the role played by certain gastrospaces in promoting gender equality—e.g., feminist restaurants, cafes, and coffeehouses in Canada and the United States during the 1970s and 1980s, which contributed to advancing women’s empowerment against male oppression (Ketchum 2018), or gay bars that help foster LGBTIQ + people’s equal rights and recognition (Sisson 2016). Other kinds of gastrospaces, which are located in a gray area between public and private spheres—e.g., shared kitchens—might instead strengthen social ties between different members of the same society while developing “a sense of community around food” (see, e.g., the Australian project Community Kitchens).Footnote 14

The first moral power is also advanced by the development of relationships of trust among those who frequent gastrospaces, especially when such spaces further inclusive experiences (e.g., a public park where different groups can share cooking equipment and food), rather than being the expression of one or a few dominant identities and interests. These kinds of intergroup relationships can help reduce prejudice and discrimination across society, thus contributing to justice in an important way (cf. Allport 1954; Pettigrew 1998).

Finally, gastrospaces can help individuals to access knowledge that may be central to the advancement of justice goals. Eating out in certain spaces can provide individuals with important information related to justice issues (Gopnik 2018) and it can make people more aware of the society that surrounds them, offering insights on its social landscape and how it may change over time (Gibson and Molz 2016: 84–85). For instance, White (2012: 138) describes the role of kissaten (Japanese cafès) as “transitional facilitators” for those “migrant workers from the countryside, needing to learn the urban ropes.” Gastrospaces can also become important settings for debate and exchange of ideas, enhancing democratic skills that are often central to the advancement of justice goals. Consider, for example, the role of the local cafe as a site of political debate (see the locus classicus Habermas 1989) but also the dining table (including at the domestic level) as a stage for integration or conflict (Flammang 2016).

In summary, then, gastrospaces can often be places where people can live typical relations as citizens, where the latter term should be understood broadly in a non-legal sense to also include non-citizen residents as well as transient or “invisible” individuals. In gastrospaces, we can meet people who are very different from or very similar to us; discuss various types of issues; and, more generally, live a (partially) public life. Yet, we should be careful not to reduce the role of gastrospaces to this function. As we explained earlier, gastrospaces can often also foster the exercise of the second moral power, which is normally tied to people’s non-public identities, values, and allegiances rather than to their role and relations as citizens.

At this point, one might observe that while gastrospaces may be conducive to the exercise and development of the two moral powers, they are in fact not necessary for them. Individuals, that is, can at least in principle cultivate their conceptions of the good and advance their justice goals independently of gastrospaces. However, this conclusion seems to neglect some important facts about contemporary societies.

First, when access to certain kinds of goods is pervasive and intertwined with most people’s everyday lives, it is difficult to argue that such access is not an issue of justice. Take, for example, access to the Internet or to some form of transportation. Since work, educational and relational opportunities are nowadays inextricably dependent on people’s ability to have access to the Internet and to some kind of transportation, it would be unfeasible to argue that these are not primary goods essential for the exercise of our two moral powers. Likewise, gastrospaces are intertwined with most, if not all, people’s everyday lives. Workplace, school and university canteens, restaurants, cafes, pubs, etc. permeate and play a central role in people’s lives in contemporary societies (Warde and Martens 2000). Furthermore, in many societies key life events such as children’s birthday parties, weddings and, sometimes, funerals are typically held in gastrospaces, e.g., restaurants, cafes or people’s homes. Given all of that, if and when gastrospaces are, for example, inaccessible to certain types of people (e.g., because of their design, location, etc.), it would be puzzling to argue that this is not an issue of justice.

Second, and relatedly, it is not always possible for people to reproduce outside certain gastrospaces the kinds of experiences that the latter enable, and which help people to exercise their moral powers. In fact, some gastrospaces are particularly apt to foster some special social relationships precisely because they provide a neutral and non-familiar environment. Examples include business negotiations, political meetings, and romantic dating (for a sociological analysis of the role of eating out in those occasions, see Warde and Martens 2000, in particular chapters 9 and 10).

Third, we should be careful not to reduce gastrospaces to the narrower category of spaces of eating out. While the latter, as we have just argued, are nearly ubiquitous in most contemporary societies, the exercise and development of the two moral powers can also occur in a wide spectrum of domestic and seemingly more private gastrospaces, thus further demonstrating the latter’s pervasiveness. Think, for instance, of how the design of domestic spaces intersects with the history of women’s emancipation. A well-known case is the so-called ‘Frankfurt kitchen.” Designed by the Austrian architect Margarete Schütte-Lihotzky as a means to female emancipation, the kitchen stood out for its innovative spatial arrangement and equipment, aimed at economizing time and labor, hence eliminating domestic drudgery (Henderson 1996; Hessler 2009). Conceived to foster the demands of the German feminist movement, however, the Frankfurt kitchen eventually came to incarnate the “female redomestication” process in the Weimar Republic, forging a “professional workplace” for women that eliminated the “urge” to emancipate by leaving their homes. This example bears witness to the political importance of domestic gastrospaces—in addition to spaces of eating out—as sites of justice and injustice.

In sum, therefore, gastrospaces—whether public or private—are inherently intertwined with our daily lives and, therefore, necessary for the exercise of our moral powers.

2.2 The Second Criterion: The Neutral Value of Gastrospaces

While gastrospaces, we have seen, are necessary for the exercise of our moral powers, are they also “valuable across a variety of conceptions of the good, without their value being grounded in any such a conception”? It is evident, from the many examples that we have already provided, that gastrospaces are valuable for different people due to different reasons, and that therefore they are not linked to any specific conception of the good. Whether someone is a vegan or a carnivore, a religious person or an atheist, a conservative or a progressive, access to gastrospaces can be important for the development and exercise of either or both of their moral powers. We are not claiming, however, that every particular gastrospace can nurture every conception of the good. Inevitably, some of these spaces are closer than others to a specific (set of) conception(s) of the good whereas others are more flexible. Our key point, instead, is that as a general category gastrospaces do seem to be “valuable across a variety of conceptions of the good,” something that arguably could not be said regarding other categories of spaces, such as places of worship, sports centers, or music venues.

2.3 The Third Criterion: Gastrospaces and Social Institutions

Finally, we need to assess whether social institutions play a role in the distribution of gastrospaces as social primary goods.Footnote 15 It seems evident that gastrospaces depend on social institutions in a variety of forms and grades, from less (e.g., accidental gastrospaces during a walk) to more institutionalized ones (e.g., restaurants and cafes). There are, more specifically, two kinds of institutions that we believe play a role in the distribution of gastrospaces as social primary goods: the first comprises legal institutions that regulate many aspects of the design, organization, and management of such spaces—e.g., floor plan requirements and opening hours; rules establishing whether food or drink can be consumed in a park or on a beach, or what kind of food or drink can be served in restaurants and other venues; or, at the domestic level, kitchen appliance regulations. The second includes social institutions and norms—e.g., norms that stigmatize eating or drinking in places of worship; those which frown upon eating out with one’s children (or eating certain foods) after a certain time of the day; or religious norms that mandate certain kinds of kitchen design, such as the kosher requirement in Judaism that kitchens should have two separate sets of utensils, stoves and refrigerators, one for meat and poultry and the other for dairy foods. Some of these norms may be particularly unfavorable for certain people, as they may constrain their ability to develop and exercise their moral powers, especially when their “temporal autonomy” (Cordelli 2015: 103) is limited—e.g., if one always has to work during those hours when most eating out establishments are open then they will have fewer opportunities to eat out than those who have a more flexible working scheduleFootnote 16; or if a Jewish family that migrates to a new city is unable to buy or rent a property provided with a kosher kitchen, its members will be unable to pursue their religious conception of the good within their domestic gastrospace without incurring significant financial and/or practical costs.

It seems therefore clear from the foregoing analysis that gastrospaces should be considered primary goods and legitimate concern of justice: given their pervasive presence in contemporary societies, and the myriad of ways in which they are intertwined with people’s everyday lives—both at the domestic level and in public—they are generally necessary for people’s ability to develop and exercise their moral powers; also, as a category, they are not grounded in any specific conception of the good but rather help promote a wide array of such conceptions; and, finally, their distribution depends on a variety of legal and social institutions. Yet, how are we to assess to what extent gastrospaces foster or hinder the development and exercise of people’s moral powers? Which features of such spaces are key for carrying out this kind of evaluation and, where necessary, for modifying and re-designing such spaces? What are the entities that populate such spaces, and how are they related to each other?

While political philosophy can provide us with useful evaluative norms and parameters for assessing the normative importance of gastrospaces, it cannot provide us with a more specific understanding of how such spaces are, including their components, agents, individuation, and identity conditions. This additional information is important to better understand where, when, and how to intervene in order to render gastrospaces more conducive to the development and exercise of the two moral powers, e.g., how to design or modify (aspects of) such spaces.Footnote 17 To this end, in the next section we shall integrate the analysis conducted so far with a conceptual framework for representing in a systematic way gastrospaces, including those features of such spaces that are most relevant to people’s development and exercise of the two moral powers.

3 Gastrospaces: A Conceptual Framework

3.1 Gastrospaces Beyond Third Places

An obvious starting point for modeling “gastrospaces” suggested in the literatureFootnote 18 is by means of the cognate concept of “third places.” Third places are those that constitute a third alternative to home (“first” places) and workplace (“second” places), and that are often viewed as the paradigmatic sites of “eating out” experiences (e.g., Warde et al. 2019). A classic and standard study of third placesFootnote 19 is that developed by Oldenburg (1999: 20–42), for whom a third place is any space that presents the following eight features: (1) it is a neutral ground, i.e., it can accommodate a wide spectrum of people and social activities; (2) it is a leveler, i.e., class and rank are temporarily set aside in this kind of space; (3) it is a conversation-facilitator, i.e., “the talk there is good”; (4) it is accessible, i.e., in terms of hours and location; (5) it has its own regulars; (6) it enjoys a low profile, characterized by homeliness and plainness as well as lack of elegance; (7) it is playful, i.e., it facilitates different sorts of conversations; and, finally, it is a home away from home allowing guests to be in control of their activities and time schedule.

To what extent can we adapt Oldenburg’s analysis of third places to our study of gastrospaces? At first sight, the overlap between the two categories seems evident. And even though third places generally only include paradigmatic sites of eating out such as cafes and restaurants, one could aim to broaden the scope of that category to include all places of eating out or away from home, as actions that unfold in a public sphere.Footnote 20 In this sense, one may suggest that “eating out” can stand not only for those practices of consuming food or beverage at establishments such as restaurants, cafes, or pubs, but also for those practices that involve consuming them in “open” venues such as a beach, a park, or a square (e.g., Jacobs and Scholliers 2003; Burnett 2004); in addition, “eating out” may on occasion refer to practices such as eating a special meal at someone else’s home, consuming food or beverages during a trip (e.g., a car or a train ride), or in a casual spot (e.g., during a hike on a mountain). But even stretching the idea of third place to include all spaces of eating out or away from home would not deliver a theoretical notion that can account for the political and justice-related value of all the spaces where we eat.Footnote 21

First, the notion of third place suffers from several defects that hinder its theoretical neutrality. For example, contra (1), some politically aligned cafes do not offer a neutral ground (e.g., Wexler & Oberlander 2017) or, contra (2) and (6), exclusive restaurants are not levelers nor have a low profile (Rawson and Shore 2019: 51–86). Furthermore, some gastrospaces may not be very playful (e.g., traditional ramen shops, where the conversation is discouraged)Footnote 22 whereas others may be hard to reach and therefore not very accessible. Second, the notion of “third place” forces us to draw a distinction between first, second, and third places that is often virtually impossible to establish. More importantly, that distinction fails to capture—and somehow implicitly dismisses—the political value of first- and second-place gastrospaces, i.e., those located at home (e.g., kitchens and backyards) or in the workplace (e.g., canteens), an exclusion that seems arbitrary at the least.

In sum, Oldenburg’s framework—spelled out in terms of allegedly necessary features of third places—falls short of providing an adequate conceptual analysis of gastrospaces, as the latter represent a much wider and internally diverse category that can be hardly constrained by one narrow set of clauses. On this note, it is useful to remark that the term “gastrospace” makes reference to space, and not place, precisely to leave open the possibility that the very same space may be regarded as holding different places from the perspective of different agents.

3.2 Outline of an Ontological Model

We have shown that certain gastrospaces cannot be identified with third places, the latter being a much narrower category. What is required for a systematic analysis of gastrospaces, therefore, is a broader conceptual framework, which includes third places as a special case but also applies to a wider range of cases. The approach we shall propose employs the tools of analytic ontology to develop such a framework. We proceed in two steps: first, we offer a general ontological model of gastrospaces (from which intended models of specific gastrospaces can be derived); second, we use such a general model to track down the key features of gastrospaces that are linked to their justice-related functions.

In general terms, an ontological model is a representation of a given domain of entities, both particular (e.g., a particular person) and universal (e.g., the property of being human), along with the relations between them; also included in the representation are the norms regulating the conditions for an entity to be a component of the domain (Arp et al. 2015: 1–27). Ontological models serve as a tools for storing and sharing all the relevant information on a given domain of reality as well as for rethinking it, by categorizing its most salient entities and imagining new possibilities for them: in fact, an ontology depicts not only how the world is but also a space of possibility for it. Such models may be either formal—i.e., they are written in mathematical languages by using standard notations (e.g., logical connectives and formation rules)Footnote 23—or informal, i.e., they employ natural languages.Footnote 24 In this paper, we limit ourselves to sketch an informal ontological model.

At this point, though, following Rawls (2005) himself, a critic might point out that ontology is in fact incompatible with the kind of political liberalism that underlies our justice approach to gastrospaces.Footnote 25 Yet, our decision to choose an ontological approach—among many other potential ones—to the study of gastrospaces rests on two related reasons which we think help us to eschew precisely that criticism. First, ontology relies on the most primitive “building bricks” of what there is. As such, it provides a more general and theoretically fundamental representation of reality than alternative approaches. With respect to gastrospaces, ontology provides a plurality of models for the same space without building on a specific ideology or conception of the good. It is therefore particularly in tune with the idea of liberal neutrality that underlies our Rawlsian justice framework and in keeping with the conception of justice that we employ in this paper, which is centered on the two moral powers rather than being grounded in any controversial conception of the good.

Second, and relatedly, while ontologists may often disagree in their conclusions, they share common standards of inquiry (Paul 2012; Hawley 2018). In this sense, ontology can be understood as a sort of lingua franca to be used for a multiplicity of purposes. Of course, as any other means of representation, ontology relies on specific linguistic and technological assumptions (e.g., using English or a formal language, employing a certain software, etc.) as well as on the social or perceptual bias that any individual ontologist inevitably has (e.g., preferring features that better match their own idea of what a gastrospace is). Yet all ontologists share a commitment to common methodological criteria which set the standard of their discipline. These include inference to the best explanation; semantic transparency; conceptual coherence; the use of conceptual or linguistic analysis; explicit disclosure of underlying conceptual assumptions; and a basic formal ontology that is substantially shared across all formal ontological endeavors (see Bonotti et al. 2022).

These considerations also serve to clarify why our choice of an ontological approach is not antagonistic to other scholarly approaches to the analysis of space, which could be employed to study gastrospaces—e.g., studies in anthropology (e.g., Low 2017), geography (Lefebvre 1996; McCann 2002), sociology (Gabrielson and Parady 2010), and philosophy of the city (King 2020). Rather, ontology can be used to generate bridges and dialogues across these various approaches, by providing shared means of representation and analysis while respecting the specificities of micro- or local analyses and histories. Granted, in this paper we can provide only the initial tools necessary to deliver a systematic ontological representation of gastrospaces and our analysis will limit itself to informal ontological modeling. But, as recent literature analyzing space by means of formal ontology suggests (e.g., Bateman et al. 2010; Chen et al. 2019; Boonstra & Rauws 2021), a formal model can be fruitfully developed and put to use once a suitable informal conceptual framework has been supplied.

Moving then forward with our outline of an ontological model of gastrospaces, three categories of entities strike us as most prominent: (i) the types of agents that act within such spaces; (ii) the norms underscoring these agents’ behaviors; and (iii) the material conditions of such spaces. We use each of these terms in a technical sense and, for this reason, it is worth considering them one at a time.

  1. (i)

    Agents. These are entities that act in and set up the material conditions (e.g., furniture, walls, etc.) of gastrospaces, and that establish, abide by, or violate the social norms and institutional acts that regulate their functioning. Agents that populate gastrospaces are primarily humans; they can differ based on gender, sex, race, class, or other characteristics; they can also be categorized on the basis of the role thay accomplish in gastrospaces—e.g., customers, cooks, workers, dwellers, etc.—and they can be allocated to specific categories based on different criteria. However, besides humans, it seems reasonable that a broad ontological inventory of all possible things that can be regarded as agents should also include non-human agents. The list encompasses pets, wild animals, plants, ecosystems, and systems of microorganisms, among others. Take, for instance, the key role of yeasts in fermented foods, such as bread (Sariola 2021) and sake (Hey 2022). Such a broad conception of agency also aligns with recent literature in philosophy of biology, which has complexified the understanding of biological individuality (e.g., Godfrey-Smith 2013) and of agencyFootnote 26; it also resonates with ethical and legal theory, which regard as agents with politically relevant features large and small living systems (e.g., Celermajer et al. 2021), human-made machines (Allen et al. 2000), and possibly other entities too (e.g., Giaccardi et al. 2016).

  2. (ii)

    Norms. Agents’ behavior in gastrospaces is paramountly governed by different sorts of norms. For a start, there are social norms, which emerge informally and are not codified by means of institutional acts, especially written ones (Bicchieri 2006). Furthermore, there are also legal and institutional norms, which are issued by a formal authority (e.g., the state, the local council, etc.) capable of imposing tangible penalties (e.g., fines). But it is important to also include natural norms, that is all those psychological or scientific regularities that may help to explain the behavior of agents—whether humans or non-humans—in a gastrospace.Footnote 27 Recent literature in food psychology (e.g., Spence 2017), for example, has pointed out among others the importance of perceptual (e.g., color), linguistic (e.g., the name of a recipe on a menu), or design (e.g., the distribution of items on a buffet table) elements in norming the behavior of humans in a gastrospace.

  3. (iii)

    Material conditions. This category includes all the physical features within or around a gastrospace, such as the physical size and dimensions of the space, its components, and their respective features, e.g., furniture (colors, dimensions, shape), outside/inside barriers, and other kinds of dividers (e.g., walls, doors, windows). These physical features also include the so-called mereotopological relations (i.e., parthood and connection relations) between different components of the physical space.

These three categories underlie a general model (Fig. 1) which provides an overview of the basic ontological components and entities of a gastrospace. However, the model can be differently realized, i.e., each category may comprise different specific entities and relations in alternative scenarios, serving different goals. That is, the membership conditions of a given category contextually vary based on a wide range of diverse factors, e.g., social structures, overarching norms, and specific epistemic, social, and pragmatic goals (see Borghini et al. 2020a, b for a similar analysis of food ontologies). We call these different realizations “intended (ontological) models of gastrospaces.” These intended models may be more or less general: they may concern the realization of a class of places (e.g., restaurants) or a specific instantiation of a place (this specific restaurant I am designing or talking about) (Fig. 2).

Fig. 1
figure 1

Illustration of the proposed ontological model for gastrospaces, which rests on three ontological categories: agents, norms, and material conditions

Fig. 2
figure 2

Illustration of an intended ontological model, representing a prototypical Italian bar. The model specifies key elements for each of the three ontological categories (agents, norms, and material conditions)

3.3 Gastrospaces: Key Features

The purpose of our general ontological model and of different intended models is to map out and make explicit all the constituents of gastrospaces. These models, however, are far from capturing the everyday representations of such spaces that guide social interactions. In fact, when people approach gastrospaces, they do so with specific experiences in mind (e.g., gathering with friends). In the account offered by Shapin (2020), for instance, diners at Buck’s (a restaurant in Woodside, California, whose regulars are Silicon Valley entrepreneurs and venture capitalists) seek out an informal and intimate place, “designed (partly intentionally, partly accidentally) to be just the right setting for capital-meets-technoscientific-entrepreneurship” (2020: 336). Another neat case in point is offered by White’s (2012) analysis of coffee houses in Japan, which shows their multiple functions—from places where migrants could “understand a big city quickly” (2012: 139) to refuges from the urban pressure where “being alone is what is a premium good, not being together” (2012: 20), or even places where employees who frequent them can be their “other selves,” communicating ideas and feelings barely shareable at work, and even at home (2012: 159).Footnote 28

Our contention is that these and countless other experiences are typically enabled by certain (meta-)features of gastrospaces: these are abstract qualities of such spaces (e.g., the spatial arrangement of chairs and tables in a dining room) which can be linked to their functions (e.g., providing exclusive conversation opportunities for diners) or to the physical realization of certain political ideas (e.g., an ideology such as Marxism),Footnote 29 aesthetic concepts (e.g., harmony or elegance), or other abstract goals.Footnote 30 By way of illustration, in this study we focus on five prominent (meta-)features: (i) temporal and (ii) spatial flexibility; (iii) versatility; (iv) power distribution and authority; and (v) degree and type of social exchange.Footnote 31

These (meta-)features are highly abstract and can be realized jointly or separately via diverse intended models of gastrospaces, by combining the components of various ontological categories in disparate ways.Footnote 32 Furthermore, the (meta-)features seem to present a number of shared traits. First, they come in degrees, i.e., they can be more or less present in a gastrospace; second, none of these features is positive or negative per se, i.e., their presence or absence can either advance or hinder the realization of certain justice goals; third, each feature can be realized in multiple ways by different kinds of entities; fourth, these features are interrelated.

  1. (i)

    Temporal flexibility. A gastrospace can be more or less flexible in terms of time organization and management. Its temporality affects and is affected by the temporalities of the specific entities and agents that populate it. One example are opening hours, which can be determined by the law or by other social norms as well as by the personal inclination of relevant agents, e.g., the owner or the guests. Additional temporal constraints that affect flexibility may include seating times and temporal constraints associated with food.

  2. (ii)

    Spatial Flexibility. The spatial organization of a gastrospace can be more or less static. For example, gastrospaces may or may not have adjustable furniture that can be moved when needed; they may or may not enable a high variety of interactions with(in) their environment (e.g., a kitchen may have a folding dining table; a restaurant may allow customers to sit or just stand, and to do so indoor or outdoor) as well as with(in) the broader surroundings (e.g., depending on whether they are well connected with other different places). Furthermore, gastrospaces may accommodate to different degrees the special requirements of certain agents, such as customers in wheelchairs.

  3. (iii)

    Versatility. The versatility of a gastrospace consists in its ability to perform and be used for different functions. Some gastrospaces can perform multiple functions at the same time, without significant changes to their material conditions (e.g., spaces where you can have a coffee or a cocktail at the same hour, sitting at the same table). Conversely, others realize their versatility by modifying some of their ontological components (e.g., material conditions) according to a schedule and managing the space consequently (e.g., turning a dining room into a ballroom after 9 pm thanks to the presence of sufficient space and movable tables).

  4. (iv)

    Power distribution and authority. Gastrospaces generally involve power-based role distinctions between the various agents that act within or around them. These role distinctions provide each agent (or type of agents) with specific powers that can affect material conditions, norms, and other agents in that space—e.g., the chef who has the power to determine the menu. Furthermore, interactions and exchanges between different agents in a gastrospace are generally regulated by an authority. This authority can be internal—i.e., settled and handled by insiders (e.g., the owner), and its power limited and only exercised upon the people who frequent that place—or external—i.e., it exercises its power more widely, including in places beyond the one at stake, and it is held by a recognized institution (e.g., the local health department).

  5. (v)

    Degree and type of social exchange. An additional feature of gastrospaces is the degree and type of social interactions that they allow and encourage. Some gastrospaces allow a high level of interaction among people from diverse backgrounds and identities (e.g., racial, religious, gender, socio-economic, etc.). Others, instead, favor interaction between people with the same background or identity, like the aforementioned example of Buck’s restaurant, which women (as well as Hispanics and African Americans) hardly frequent (Shapin 2020). Still, others may discourage interaction among patrons and instead promote solo dining experiences, as in the case of Ichiran Restaurant in New York.Footnote 33

4 Conclusion: From Analysis to Intervention

In this paper, we have combined political philosophy and ontology to provide a novel normative framework for evaluating gastrospaces. First, we illustrated the value of gastrospaces from the perspective of political philosophy, by explaining how such spaces can help individuals to develop and exercise their two moral powers. We then complemented this analysis with a conceptual framework that includes an informal ontological model and five (meta-)features. What we have offered is, of course, an abridged version of a broader theoretical perspective, which purports to capture the wide variety of gastrospaces and their functions in our social and political life.

Our framework has potential practical implications too. To understand why, consider, for example, the (meta-)features that we identified in the previous section. These offer a map to guide justice-oriented interventions, by representing the potential dimensions along which the design or modification of gastrospaces may be carried out in order to promote, and potentially address, any obstacles to the development and exercise of the two moral powers. But what would these interventions look like? While we cannot address this question in depth here, we shall conclude by pointing out some directions an answer could take.

At the institutional level, gastrospaces can be regulated by various legal or political authorities (e.g., state, council). Relevant measures may include, for example, laws that regulate the opening hours of cafes and restaurants, as well as those that establish whether, when, and how food (and drink) can be consumed, and whether certain gastrospaces can discriminate against certain types of customers. Consider, for example, the case of gay bars discussed earlier. The opportunity that gay people have to meet in these gastrospaces qua members of the same group is precisely what renders those spaces particularly valuable for them. In such spaces, gay people can develop and exercise their second moral power by expressing their identities and jointly pursuing their conceptions of the good (e.g., by enjoying certain types of foods) as well as advance justice goals associated with the first moral power (e.g., creating coalitions of support for LGBTQ + rights). Ensuring that this and other vulnerable and marginalized groups remain in control of certain gastrospaces—thus de facto limiting the latter’s degree of social exchange—would therefore seem to be central to those group members’ ability to develop and exercise their moral powers, and this may require allowing them to exclude out-group members, thus exempting them from anti-discrimination laws that would normally apply to other gastrospaces.

But interventions can also be implemented by gastrospace keepers, i.e., those who own or manage, even temporarily, gastrospaces. Our ontological framework can help those actors not only to identify instances of injustice concerning such spaces but also to understand how they could voluntarily modify their establishments in ways that may better align with certain justice goals. For example, in response to criticisms of racist dress codes in some restaurants in the US, one commentator (Saxena 2020) pointed out that “restaurants are facing a unique opportunity to change how business is done, and an imperative to make things equitable. One small step in this direction is to abolish dress codes.” While one might argue that in this case legal/institutional interventions would be more appropriate, given the serious nature of the injustice at stake, in other cases restaurateurs may indeed be the best implementers of interventions aimed at (re)designing gastrospaces, setting aside the risk of excessive invasiveness that legal interventions may often carry with them.

Finally, our framework can also be useful for gastrospace users, from restaurant customers to beachgoers and those who enjoy eating in public parks or in their home kitchen. For all these different types of agents, knowing whether and to what extent any of the five (meta-)features is present in a gastrospace can be crucial for their ability to develop and exercise their moral powers. Our framework can provide gastrospace users with a clear understanding of what to look for when they have to decide in which gastrospaces they can best develop and exercise their moral powers.

This overview of potential areas of gastrospace interventions is admittedly sketchy and a more systematic analysis cannot be accommodated within the limited space of this paper. However, we hope that our conceptual and normative analysis of gastrospaces will open up a new research agenda, which critically re-evaluates the role and function of gastrospaces in our daily lives.