Skip to main content
Log in

Perception and its objects

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Early modern empiricists thought that the nature of perceptual experience is given by citing the object presented to the mind in that experience. Hallucination and illusion suggest that this requires untenable mind-dependent objects. Current orthodoxy replaces the appeal to direct objects with the claim that perceptual experience is characterized instead by its representational content. This paper argues that the move to content is problematic, and reclaims the early modern empiricist insight as perfectly consistent, even in cases of illusion, with the realist contention that these direct objects of perception are the persisting mind-independent physical objects we all know and love.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I concentrate throughout on the case of vision. I believe that much of what I say applies equally to the other modalities, although I do not address this here. There are plausible counterexamples to the sufficiency of this characterization of visual illusion; but it is adequate for present purposes. My forthcoming ‘How to Account for Illusion’, and Perception and its Objects, contain further discussion.

  2. Things are of course more complicated in case of secondary qualities, according to Locke. For, in one sense, all secondary quality perception is illusory: nothing in the mind-independent physical world is red, in the basic sense in which mind-dependent ideas are red. Still, in having such an idea before the mind, a physical thing may be said to look red*, that is, either disposed to produce red ideas in normal observers in normal conditions, or microscopically constituted in whichever way actually grounds that disposition. Some, but not all, such perceptions may then be illusory in a derived sense, in which something looks red* which is not. None of these details are relevant for present purposes.

  3. See Stoneham (2002) for a compelling presentation of this account of Berkeley. Note, as with Locke’s account of the secondary qualities, predicates apply to persisting physical objects, according to Berkeley, in a way which is derivative of their more basic application to our fleeting ideas, which are their temporal, and ‘personal’, parts.

  4. Having said that, I believe that there are significant, and illuminating, structural similarities between the latter Berkeleyian view, and Lewis’ (1998) account of the metaphysics of persisting (that is, in his view, perduring, rather than enduring) macroscopic physical objects, especially in the presence of his Ramseyian humility (2002). My forthcoming ‘Berkeley and Modern Metaphysics’, and Perception and its Objects, contain detailed development of this suggestion.

  5. My forthcoming ‘Perception and Content’, and Perception and its Objects, contain extended critical investigation of (CV), in which the following difficulties are developed at length.

  6. I entirely acknowledge that this is a very rough placeholder for what must in the end by a far more developed account of visually relevant similarities.

  7. This idea is clearly in need of far more extended discussion. It also involves a controversial account of concepts and their possession. To make progress here I will have to leave further elucidation and defence for another occasion; but see Fodor (1998) for strong opposition.

  8. I rely heavily here upon Martin (2004).

  9. Thanks to Ian Phillips (draft) for pressing this objection very forcefully in his paper at the 2005 Warwick University Mindgrad conference.

  10. Many thanks to Anil Gupta, who raised this line of objection in his wonderful comments at the Pacific APA, 2006, in Portland.

  11. A second question from Gupta.

  12. The first of these engages a third issues raised by Gupta in Portland; the second was raised by Nicolas Bullot’s very helpful comments at the Pacific APA.

  13. See Campbell (2002), for a sustained and detailed development of this fundamental empiricist conviction.

  14. Many thanks to Justin Broackes, Nicolas Bullot, Steve Butterfill, John Campbell, David Charles, Bill Child, Tim Crane, Imogen Dickie, Naomi Eilan, Anil Gupta, John Hawthorne, Christoph Hoerl, Hemdat Lerman, John McDowell, Jennifer Nagel, Johannes Roessler, Nick Shea, Alison Simmons, Paul Snowdon, Matt Soteriou, Helen Steward, Charles Travis, Ralph Wedgwood, Michael Williams, and Tim Williamson, for helpful comments on previous versions of this material.

References

  • Berkeley, G. (1975a). Three dialogues between Hylas and Philonous. In M. Ayers (Ed.), George Berkeley: Philosophical works. London: Everyman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berkeley, G. (1975b). A treatise concerning the principles of human knowledge. In M. Ayers (Ed.), George Berkeley: Philosophical works. London: Everyman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brewer, B. (1999). Perception and reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Brewer, B. (Forthcoming). Berkeley and Modern Metaphysics.

  • Brewer, B. (Forthcoming). How to Account for Illusion. In A. Haddock, & F. Macpherson (Eds.), Disjunctivism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Brewer, B. (Forthcoming). Perception and Content. European Journal of Philosophy.

  • Brewer, B. (Forthcoming). Perception and its Objects. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Campbell, J. (2002). Reference and consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1982). The varieties of reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1998). Concepts: Where cognitive science went wrong. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Grice, H. P. (1989a). Logic and conversation. In his Studies in the Way of Words. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.

  • Grice, H. P. (1989b). Further notes on logic and conversation. In his Studies in the way of words. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.

  • Jastrow, J. (1900). Fact and fable in psychology. New York: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1998). The problem of temporary intrinsics: An excerpt from On the Plurality of Worlds. In P. Van Inwagen, & D. W. Zimmerman (Eds.), Metaphysics: The big questions. Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Lewis, D. 2002. Ramseyan humility. Gareth Evans Memorial Lecture to Oxford University, delivered posthumously by Stephanie Lewis, 2.iii.02.

  • Locke, J. 1975. An essay concerning human understanding. In P. H. Nidditch (Ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • McDowell, J. (1994). Mind and world. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. (2004). The Limits of Self-Awareness. Philosophical Studies, 120, 37–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (1992). Scenarios, Concepts and Perception. In T. Crane (Ed.), The Contents of Experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, I. Draft. Illusion and Content. Paper presented at the 2005 Warwick University Mindgrad Conference.

  • Snowdon, P. 1992. How to interpret direct perception. In T. Crane (Ed.), The contents of perception. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoneham, T. (2002). Berkeley’s world. Oxford University Press.

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1958). Philosophical investigations. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Bill Brewer.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Brewer, B. Perception and its objects. Philos Stud 132, 87–97 (2007). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-006-9051-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-006-9051-2

Keywords

Navigation