Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Why the Difference Between Explanation and Argument Matters to Science Education

  • Article
  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Contributing to the recent debate on whether or not explanations ought to be differentiated from arguments, this article argues that the distinction matters to science education. I articulate the distinction in terms of explanations and arguments having to meet different standards of adequacy. Standards of explanatory adequacy are important because they correspond to what counts as a good explanation in a science classroom, whereas a focus on evidence-based argumentation can obscure such standards of what makes an explanation explanatory. I provide further reasons for the relevance of not conflating explanations with arguments (and having standards of explanatory adequacy in view). First, what guides the adoption of the particular standards of explanatory adequacy that are relevant in a scientific case is the explanatory aim pursued in this context. Apart from explanatory aims being an important aspect of the nature of science, including explanatory aims in classroom instruction also promotes students seeing explanations as more than facts, and engages them in developing explanations as responses to interesting explanatory problems. Second, it is of relevance to science curricula that science aims at intervening in natural processes, not only for technological applications, but also as part of experimental discovery. Not any argument enables intervention in nature, as successful intervention specifically presupposes causal explanations. Students can fruitfully explore in the classroom how an explanatory account suggests different options for intervention.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Inductive inference is a quite generic category (including even abductive inference), so that often different types of inductive arguments are distinguished (M. H. Salmon 2002).

  2. Even though Osborne and Patterson’s (2011) characterization of the explanation-argument difference does not rely on the idea of causation, their discussion of the nature of explanation explicitly invokes causation: “the particular view adopted here is that the bread and butter explanations of school science are causal, for example, why do things fall, why is matter conserved, or how does photosynthesis happen … explanations consist of a subset of descriptions where new entities or properties are brought into being or invented to provide a causal account.” (pp. 628–629).

  3. This matters also in inference to the best explanation. Given that here one wants to infer the truth of one explanatory account (e.g., that the butler committed the murder using poison), Lipton (2004) recognizes that circular reasoning would result if ‘explanation’ always meant a true account. As a result, he disambiguates by using the term ‘potential explanation’—which has all characteristics of a valid explanation except possibly for truth—and clarifies that the inference is more precisely an inference to the best potential explanation (i.e., inferring that this potential explanation is true).

  4. In Sect. 2 I already challenged Osborne and Patterson’s (2011) characterization of the explanation-argument difference, who rely on the idea that an explanation’s explanandum is known to be true (while the explanans is tentative). Explanations of hypothetical phenomena provide an additional reason against this idea.

  5. Osborne and Patterson (2011) mention the goal of explanation, contrasting it with the goal of argumentation, however, as we will see, what matters in my context is the aim of an individual explanation (which differs from the aim of another explanation).

  6. Brigandt (2010b, 2012) illustrates how even the historical change of an individual scientific concept can be understood with reference to scientific aims, including explanatory aims.

  7. Given that curricula and classroom instruction are structured along the boundaries of traditional disciplines, only little place can be given to interdisciplinarity. But there are examples from the science classroom. For instance, an explanation of the evolution of horses, e.g., the change of the leg and foot bones, involves fossil data about these skeletal features (from the discipline of paleontology), an evolutionary tree leading up to modern horses (provided by systematics), and considerations about what makes a particular leg length and foot structure adapted to a particular habitat, such as permitting faster locomotion to outrun predators upon the shift from forest to steppe (involving the fields of functional anatomy and ecology). To be sure, for the purpose of classroom instruction, what matters less than discussing whether the explanatory ingredients are from distinct disciplines is to explore how some explanations involve several ingredients. Many explanations suggested by students are not false, but incomplete, so that it is relevant to understand how the suggestions from other students add to one’s explanation, and why given the explanatory aim or question at hand, an adequate explanation combines a number of considerations.

  8. The United States National Research Council’s (2012) K-12 science education framework portrays science in this fashion, when breaking it into eight practices (pp. 49–53). As the first practice, the framework lists that “Science begins with a question about a phenomenon … and seeks to develop theories that can provide explanatory answers to such questions” (p. 50), while practices 6 and 7 are the construction of explanations and engaging in argument from evidence so as to find the best explanation for a phenomenon.

  9. Carrying out an ideal intervention on an individual cause A is in many practical situations not possible given that an experimental intervention often affects many features adjacent to A (e.g., in the case of brain surgery), or a cause cannot be practically influenced at all (e.g., the earth mantle convection currents that cause the movement of the continents). Yet an interventionist account is merely meant as a metaphysical account of what a cause is; and a scientific explanation that cites some such causes still reveals at least in principle possible avenues for intervention.

  10. Even Braaten and Windschitl’s (2011) exemplary discussion of scientific explanation for the science education context fails to mention that science does and intends to intervene in nature.

References

  • Adúriz-Bravo, A. (2014). Revisiting school scientific argumentation from the perspective of the history and philosophy of science. In M. R. Matthews (Ed.), International handbook of research in history, philosophy and science teaching (pp. 1443–1472). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allchin, D. (2011). Evaluating knowledge of the nature of (whole) science. Science Education, 95, 518–542.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allchin, D. (2013). Teaching the nature of science: Perspectives & resources. Saint Paul: SHiPS Education Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2005). Explanation: A mechanist alternative. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 36, 421–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berland, L. K., & McNeill, K. L. (2012). For whom is argument and explanation a necessary distinction? A response to Osborne and Patterson. Science Education, 96, 808–813.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berland, L. K., & Reiser, B. J. (2009). Making sense of argumentation and explanation. Science Education, 93, 26–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braaten, M., & Windschitl, M. (2011). Working toward a stronger conceptualization of scientific explanation for science education. Science Education, 95, 639–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, I. (2010a). Beyond reduction and pluralism: Toward an epistemology of explanatory integration in biology. Erkenntnis, 73, 295–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, I. (2010b). The epistemic goal of a concept: Accounting for the rationality of semantic change and variation. Synthese, 177, 19–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, I. (2012). The dynamics of scientific concepts: The relevance of epistemic aims and values. In U. Feest & F. Steinle (Eds.), Scientific concepts and investigative practice (pp. 75–103). Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, I. (2013a). Explanation in biology: Reduction, pluralism, and explanatory aims. Science & Education, 22, 69–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, I. (2013b). Intelligent design and the nature of science: Philosophical and pedagogical points. In K. Kampourakis (Ed.), The philosophy of biology: A companion for educators (pp. 205–238). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, I. (2013c). Systems biology and the integration of mechanistic explanation and mathematical explanation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 44, 477–492.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Castro e Freire, C., & Motokane, M. T. (2013). Argument and explanation in classroom discouse. In IX Congreso internacional sobre investigación en la didáctica de las ciencias (pp. 744–748). Girona.

  • College Board, USA. (2009). Science: College Board standards for college success. New York: The College Board.

    Google Scholar 

  • Council of Ministers of Education, Canada. (1997). The common framework of science learning outcomes, K to 12: Pan-Canadian protocol for collaboration on school curriculum: For use by curriculum developers. Council of Ministers of Education, Canada/Conseil des ministres de l’Éducation du Canada.

  • Council of Ministers of Education, Canada. (2013). Pan-Canadian Assessment Program science assessment framework. Council of Ministers of Education, Canada/Conseil des ministres de l’Éducation du Canada.

  • Craver, C. F. (2006). When mechanistic models explain. Synthese, 153, 355–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2007). Explaining the brain: Mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F., & Darden, L. (2013). In search of mechanisms: Discoveries across the life sciences. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L., & Maull, N. (1977). Interfield theories. Philosophy of Science, 44, 43–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dauer, J. M., Doherty, J. H., Freed, A. L., & Anderson, C. W. (2014). Connections between student explanations and arguments from evidence about plant growth. CBE-Life Sciences Education, 13, 397–409.

    Google Scholar 

  • Department for Education, England. (2004). The national curriculum: Handbook for secondary teachers in England: Key stages 3 and 4. London: Department for Education and Skills, Qualifications and Curriculum Authority, United Kingdom.

    Google Scholar 

  • Department for Education, England. (2013). Science programmes of study: Key stage 3: National curriculum in England. Department for Education, United Kingdom.

  • Department for Education, England. (2014). The national curriculum in England: Key stages 3 and 4 framework document. Department for Education, United Kingdom.

  • Duschl, R. A. (1990). Restructuring science education: The importance of theories and their developments. New York: Teachers College.

    Google Scholar 

  • Falk, A., & Brodsky, L. (2013). Scientific argumentation as a foundation for the design of inquiry-based science instruction. Journal of Mathematics and Science: Collaborative Explorations, 13, 27–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flick, L. B., & Lederman, N. G. (Eds.). (2004). Scientific inquiry and nature of science: Implications for teaching, learning, and teacher education. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glymour, C. (2003). Learning, prediction and causal Bayes nets. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7, 43–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophy of science. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G., & Oppenheim, P. (1948). Studies in the logic of explanation. Philosophy of Science, 15, 135–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hmelo-Silver, C. E. (2004). Problem-based learning: What and how do students learn? Educational Psychology Review, 16, 235–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hmelo-Silver, C. E., & DeSimone, C. (2013). Problem-based learning: An instructional model of collaborative learning. In C. E. Hmelo-Silver (Ed.), The international handbook of collaborative learning (pp. 233–249). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Irzik, G., & Nola, R. (2011). A family resemblance approach to the nature of science for science education. Science & Education, 20, 591–607.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Janssen, F. J. J. M., & Berkel, B. (2015). Making philosophy of science education practical for science teachers. Science & Education, 24, 229–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kampourakis, K. (2016). The “general aspects” conceptualization as a pragmatic and effective means to introducing students to nature of science. Journal of Research in Science Teaching. doi:10.1002/tea.21305.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kampourakis, K., & Nehm, R. H. (2014). History and philosophy of science and the teaching of evolution: Students’ conceptions and explanations. In M. R. Matthews (Ed.), International handbook of research in history, philosophy and science teaching (pp. 377–399). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2001). Science, truth, and democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Klipp, E., Liebermeister, W., Wierling, C., Kowald, A., Lehrach, H., & Herwig, R. (2010). Systems biology: A textbook. Weinheim: Wiley-VCH.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krajcik, J. S., & Blumenfeld, P. (2014). Project-based learning. In R. K. Sawyer (Ed.), The Cambridge handbook of the learning sciences (pp. 275–297). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Krajcik, J. S., & Mamlok-Naaman, R. (2006). Using driving questions to motivate and sustain student interest in learning science. In K. Tobin (Ed.), Teaching and learning science: An encyclopedia (pp. 317–327). Westport: Greenwood Publishing Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacey, H. (1999). Is science value free? Values and scientific understanding. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lederman, N. G. (2007). Nature of science: Past, present, and future. In S. K. Abell & N. G. Lederman (Eds.), Handbook of research on science education (pp. 831–879). Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lederman, N. G., Abd-El-Khalick, F., Bell, R. L., & Schwartz, R. S. (2002). Views of nature of science questionnaire: Toward valid and meaningful assessment of learners’ conceptions of nature of science. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 39, 497–521.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, R., & Schauble, L. (2006). Scientific thinking and science literacy. In K. A. Renninger, I. E. Sigel, W. Damon, & R. M. Lerner (Eds.), Handbook of child psychology (Vol. 4, pp. 153–196). Hoboken: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lennox, J. G. (1991). Darwinian thought experiments: A function for just-so stories. In G. J. Massey & T. Horowitz (Eds.), Thought experiments in science and philosophy (pp. 223–245). Savage: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2004). Inference to the best explanation. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Love, A. C. (2008). Explaining evolutionary innovations and novelties: Criteria of explanatory adequacy and epistemological prerequisites. Philosophy of Science, 75, 874–886.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Love, A. C. (2013a). Interdisciplinary lessons for the teaching of biology from the practice of evo-devo. Science & Education, 22, 255–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Love, A. C. (2013b). Teaching evolutionary developmental biology: Concepts, problems, and controversy. In K. Kampourakis (Ed.), The philosophy of biology: A companion for educators (pp. 323–341). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McComas, W. F. (Ed.). (1998). The nature of science in science education: Rationales and strategies. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • McComas, W. F., Almazroa, H., & Clough, M. P. (1998). The nature of science in science education: An introduction. Science & Education, 7, 511–532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McNeill, K. L. (2009). Teachers’ use of curriculum to support students in writing scientific arguments to explain phenomena. Science Education, 93, 233–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McNeill, K. L. (2011). Elementary students’ views of explanation, argumentation, and evidence, and their abilities to construct arguments over the school year. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 48, 793–823.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McNeill, K. L., & Krajcik, J. (2007). Middle school students’ use of appropriate and inappropriate evidence in writing scientific explanations. In M. C. Lovett & P. Shah (Eds.), Thinking with data (pp. 233–265). New York: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • McNeill, K. L., & Krajcik, J. (2008). Scientific explanations: Characterizing and evaluating the effects of teachers’ instructional practices on student learning. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 45, 53–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McNeill, K. L., Lizotte, D. J., Krajcik, J., & Marx, R. W. (2006). Supporting students’ construction of scientific explanations by fading scaffolds in instructional materials. Journal of the Learning Sciences, 15, 153–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ministry of Education, New Zealand. (1993). Science in the New Zealand curriculum. Wellington: Learning Media.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moje, E., Peek-Brown, D., Sutherland, L., Marx, R., Blumenfeld, P., & Krajcik, J. S. (2004). Explaining explanations: Developing scientific literacy in middle-school project-based reforms. In D. Strickland & D. E. Alvermann (Eds.), Bridging the gap: Improving literacy learning for preadolescent and adolescent learners in grades 4–12 (pp. 227–251). New York: Teachers College Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • National Research Council, USA. (1996). National science education standards. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • National Research Council, USA. (2012). A framework for K-12 science education: Practices, crosscutting concepts, and core ideas. Committee on a Conceptual Framework for New K-12 Science Education Standards. Board on Science Education, Division of Behavioral and Social Sciences and Education. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press.

  • O’Malley, M. A., Brigandt, I., Love, A. C., Crawford, J. W., Gilbert, J. A., Knight, R., et al. (2014). Multilevel research strategies and biological systems. Philosophy of Science, 81, 811–828.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Osborne, J. F., Collins, S., Ratcliffe, M., Millar, R., & Duschl, R. (2003). What “ideas-about-science” should be taught in school science? A Delphi study of the expert community. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 40, 692–720.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Osborne, J. F., & Patterson, A. (2011). Scientific argument and explanation: A necessary distinction? Science Education, 95, 627–638.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Osborne, J. F., & Patterson, A. (2012). Authors’ response to “For whom is argument and explanation a necessary distinction? A response to Osborne and Patterson” by Berland and McNeill. Science Education, 96, 814–817.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pearl, J. (2000). Causality: Models, reasoning, and inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rudolph, J. L. (2000). Reconsidering the ‘nature of science’ as a curriculum component. Journal of Curriculum Studies, 32, 403–419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. C. (1970). Statistical explanation. In R. G. Colodny (Ed.), The nature and function of scientific theories (pp. 173–231). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. C. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. C. (1989). Four decades of scientific explanation. In P. Kitcher & W. C. Salmon (Eds.), Scientific explanation. Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. XIII, pp. 3–219). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, M. H. (2002). Introduction to logic and critical thinking. Belmont: Wadsworth Thomson Learning.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. C., Jeffrey, R. C., & Greeno, J. G. (1971). Statistical explanation and statistical relevance. Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandoval, W. A., & Reiser, B. J. (2004). Explanation-driven inquiry: Integrating conceptual and epistemic scaffolds for scientific inquiry. Science Education, 88, 345–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, R. S., & Lederman, N. (2008). What scientists say: Scientists’ views of nature of science and relation to science context. International Journal of Science Education, 30, 727–771.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (1996). Explanatory pluralism in evolutionary biology. Biology and Philosophy, 11, 193–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strobel, J., & van Barneveld, A. (2009). When is PBL more effective? A meta-synthesis of meta-analyses comparing PBL to conventional classrooms. Interdisciplinary Journal of Problem-Based Learning, 3, 44–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Szostak, R. (2002). How to do interdisciplinarity: Integrating the debate. Issues in Integrative Studies, 20, 103–122.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tala, S., & Vesterinen, V.-M. (2015). Nature of science contextualized: Studying nature of science with scientists. Science & Education, 24, 435–457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Dijk, E. M. (2011). Portraying real science in science communication. Science Education, 95, 1086–1100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Dijk, E. M. (2014). Understanding the heterogeneous nature of science: A comprehensive notion of PCK for scientific literacy. Science Education, 98, 397–411.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2002). What is a mechanism? A counterfactual account. Philosophy of Science, 69, S366–S377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2014). Scientific explanation. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/scientific-explanation.

  • Yang, H.-T., & Wang, K.-H. (2014). A teaching model for scaffolding 4th grade students’ scientific explanation writing. Research in Science Education, 44, 531–548.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zangori, L., Forbes, C. T., & Biggers, M. (2013). Fostering student sense making in elementary science learning environments: Elementary teachers’ use of science curriculum materials to promote explanation construction. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 50, 989–1017.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am indebted to four anonymous referees for their critical suggestions that greatly contributed to revisions of two earlier versions of the manuscript. I also thank the Fall 2014 Visiting Fellows of the Center for Philosophy of Science at the University of Pittsburgh for useful suggestions on this project.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ingo Brigandt.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author declares no conflict of interest.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Brigandt, I. Why the Difference Between Explanation and Argument Matters to Science Education. Sci & Educ 25, 251–275 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-016-9826-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-016-9826-6

Keywords

Navigation