Ethics in Darwin’s melancholy vision

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsc.2010.11.004Get rights and content

Abstract

Darwinian natural selection draws on Malthus’ harsh vision of human society to explain how organisms come to be adapted to their environments. Natural selection produces the appearance of teleology, but requires only efficient causal processes: undirected, heritable variation combined with effects of the variations on survival and reproduction. This paper draws a sharp distinction between the resulting form of backwards-directed teleology and the future-directed teleology we ascribe to intentional human activity. Rather than dismiss teleology as mere illusion, the paper concludes with an account of how future-directed teleology came to be a justifiable part of how we understand ourselves.

Section snippets

Introduction: Darwinian evolution and ethics

Darwin’s On the Origin of Species mentions ‘man’s origins’ only at the very last. But the implications of his general claim of common descent were clear: the animals that most resemble humans, the great apes, must share a relatively recent common ancestor with us. Furthermore, unlike previous evolutionary hypotheses, Darwin’s mechanism of natural selection is explicitly non-teleological. Instead of progress towards some end, evolution by natural selection reflects only the accumulation of

Malthus’ essay and Darwin’s harsh vision of nature

Reading the Reverend Dr. Thomas Malthus’ An Essay on the Principle of Population contributed to both Darwin’s and Wallace’s invention of the hypothesis of natural selection. Malthus’ essay also inspired a harsh tradition of social thought, some of whose themes are still familiar. More importantly for my purposes here, however, there is a strongly theodical element in Malthus’ essay—a point that sharply differentiates Malthus’ response to the grim facts he describes from Darwin’s.

As Malthus says

Evolutionary views of ethics today

In this section I want to briefly examine two examples of philosophical work on the relation between ethics and evolution. Despite taking opposite sides on the fundamental question of whether normative standards are objective or real, there is an important element that both these accounts share: neither involves a real transition between organisms to which norms and values don’t really apply except perhaps by analogy, and organisms to which they really do apply.

The reason for this resemblance,

The roots of normativity: an evolutionary tale

Like Sellars’ famous ‘Myth of Jones’, which offers a story about the development of our account of inner ‘mental’ states, including beliefs and phenomenal experience, the story I present here is not intended as a detailed account of the actual origins of normativity or even of normative language. Instead, I aim to set out a view of the status of normative language and its relation to the descriptive story evolution tells about our origins. The proposal is tentative and sketchy, but I believe

On drawing the Line

As we’ve seen, evolutionary approaches to normativity have difficulty drawing a line between organisms, behaviours and adaptations that are merely functionalb and those that are functionalf. If we begin by assuming our own actions, along with tools and machinery are functionalf and governed by normsf, evolutionary continuity makes it difficult to say where a transition to mere functionsb and normsb occurs. It becomes tempting to follow Collier and Stingl, and see certain things as goodf for

References (22)

  • R. Weikart

    Was Darwin or Spencer the father of laissez-faire social Darwinism?

    Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization

    (2009)
  • D. Braybrooke et al.

    Logic on the track of social change

    (1995)
  • J. Collier et al.

    Evolutionary naturalism and the objectivity of morality

    Biology and Philosophy

    (1993)
  • Darwin, C. (July 13 1856). Letter to J. D. Hooker,...
  • C. Darwin

    On the origin of species by means of natural selection, or the preservation of favoured races in the struggle for survival

    (1859)
  • Darwin, C. (May 22, 1860). Letter to A. Gray,...
  • C. Darwin

    The descent of man, and selection in relation to sex

    (1882)
  • S. Gould

    Darwin’s more stately mansion

    Science

    (1999)
  • J. Lennox

    Darwin was a teleologist

    Biology and Philosophy

    (2003)
  • Malthus, T. (1798). An essay on population,...
  • Cited by (0)

    View full text