Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-m8qmq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T10:14:25.051Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Justice and the Ada: Does Prioritizing and Rationing Health Care Discriminate against the Disabled?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 June 2009

Dan W. Brock
Affiliation:
Philosophy, Brown University

Extract

It is sometimes said that a society should be judged ethically by how it treats its least-fortunate or worst-off members. In one interpretation this is not a point about justice, but instead about moral virtues such as compassion and charity. In our response to the least fortunate among us, we display, or show that we lack, fundamental moral virtues of fellow feeling and concern for others in need. In a different interpretation, however, this point is about justice and a just society—the justice of a society is shown especially in how it treats its least-fortunate members.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Social Philosophy and Policy Foundation 1995

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971)Google Scholar; Buchanan, Allen, “Justice and Charity.” Ethics, vol. 97, no. 3 (1987), pp. 558–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

2 Daniels, Norman, Just Health Care (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985).CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed Daniels follows Rawls in understanding fair equality of opportunity as requiring equal opportunities for persons with similar talents and abilities.

3 Medicaid is a joint federal/state government program in the United States to provide health care to the poor.

4 I draw on Garland, Michael J., “Justice, Politics, and Community: Expanding Access and Rationing Health Services in Oregon,” Law. Medicine, and Health Care, vol. 20 (1992), p. 70.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

5 Hadorn, David, “Setting Health Care Priorities in Oregon: Cost-Effectiveness Meets the Rule of Rescue,” Journal of the Atnerican Medical Association, vol. 265 (1991), pp. 2218–25CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Eddy, David. “Oregon's Methods: Did Cost-Effectiveness Analysis Fail?Journal of the American Madical Association, vol. 266 (1991), pp. 2135–41.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

6 Kaplan, Robert and Anderson, John, “A General Health Policy Model: Update and Applications,” Health Services Research, vol. 23 (1988), pp. 203–35.Google ScholarPubMed

7 See Brock, Dan W.. “Quality of Life Measures in Health Care and Medical Ethics,” in The Quality of Life, ed. Sen, A. and Nussbaum, M. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993).Google Scholar

8 Daniels, Norman. “Is the Oregon Rationing Plan Fair?Journal of the American Medical Assotiation. vol. 265 (1991), pp. 2232–35.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

9 Unpublished letter from Secretary of Health and Human Services Louis W. Sullivan to Governor Barbara Roberts of Oregon, August 3, 1992.

10 Public Law 101–336, July 26, 1990. 104 Stat. 327. 42 USC 12101–12213, 47 USC 225 and 611.

11 Orentlichcr, David. “Rationing and the Americans with Disabilities Act,” Journal of the American Medical Association, vol. 271 (1994), pp. 308–14.CrossRefGoogle Scholar Orentlicher provides a comprehensive legal analysis of the likely application of the ADA (and other legislation protecting the disabled) to a variety of forms of health-care rationing.

12 Unpublished letter from Thomas J. Marzen and Daniel Avila, National Legal Center for the Medically Dependent and Disabled, Inc., to Representative Christopher H. Smith, U.S. House of Representatives, Decembers, 1991.

13 New York Times, 03 20, 1993, p. 8.Google Scholar

14 Marzen and Avila, unpublished letter.

16 Hadorn, David C., “The Problem of Discrimination in Health Care Priority SettingJournal of the American Medical Association, vol. 268 (1992), pp. 1454–59.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

17 Brock, Dan, “Ethical Issues in Recipient Selection for Organ Transplantation.” in Organ Substitution Technology: Ethical, Legal. and Public Policy Issues, ed. Mathieu, Debra (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1983), p. 94.Google Scholar

18 Kamm, Frances, Morality, Mortality: Volume 1, Death and Whom to Save from it (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993).Google Scholar

19 Brock, , “Ethical Issues in Recipient Selection for Organ Transplantation,” p. 94.Google Scholar

21 Roughly speaking, the weighted lottery would give a greater probability of being selected to receive a scarce organ to patients likely to benefit more from it, but would also give all in need at least some chance of being selected.

22 Public Law 101–336 (supra note 10).

23 Garland, , “Justice, Politics, and Community,” p. 70.Google Scholar

24 Brock, , “Ethical Issues in Recipient Selection for Organ Transplantation”Google Scholar; Wikler, Daniel, “Equity, Efficacy, and the Point System for Transplant Recipient Selection,” Transplantation Proceedings, vol. 21 (1991), pp. 3437–39.Google Scholar

25 Rawls, , A Theory of Justice, section 29.Google Scholar

26 Sullivan, unpublished letter.

27 Hadorn, , “The Problem of Discrimination in Health Care Priority Setting,” p. 1459.Google Scholar

28 Menzel, Paul T., “Oregon's Denial: Disabilities and Quality of Life,” Hastings Center Report, vol. 22, no. 6 (1992), pp. 2125.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

29 See. e.g., Asch, Adrienne. “Can Aborting ‘Imperfect’ Children Be Immoral?” in Contemporary Issues in Biomedical Ethics, 4th ed., ed. Beauchamp, Tom and Walters, Leroy (Encino, CA: Wadsworth Publishing, 1987).Google Scholar

30 See, e.g., Rawls, , A Theory of JusticeGoogle Scholar (endorsing primary goods as the relevant comparison); Sen, Amartya, Commodities and Capabilities (Amsterdam: North Holland, 1985)Google Scholar (endorsing equality of capability); Dworkin, Ronald, “What is Equality? Part I: Equality of Welfare,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, vol. 10 (1981), pp. 185246Google Scholar (criticizing equality of welfare); Dworkin, Ronald, “What is Equality? Part II: Equality of Resources,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, vol. 10 (1981), pp. 283345Google Scholar (endorsing a particular interpretation of equality of resources); Arneson, Richard, “Equality and Equality of Opportunity for Welfare,” Philosophical Studies, vol. 56 (1988)Google Scholar (endorsing equality of opportunity for welfare); and Cohen, G. A., “On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice,” Ethics, vol. 99 (1989). pp. 906–44CrossRefGoogle Scholar (endorsing equality of opportunity for advantage).

31 Daniels, , Just Health Care, chs. 1–4.Google Scholar

32 Brock, Dan W., “Justice, Health Care, and the Elderly,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, vol. 18, no. 3 (1989), pp. 297312.Google ScholarPubMed

33 Sullivan, unpublished letter.

34 See Daniels, Norman, “Rationing Fairly: Programmatic Considerations,” Bioethics, vol. 7, nos. 2 and 3 (1993), pp. 224–33CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; and Brock, Dan W., “Some Unresolved Issues in Priority-Setting of Mental Health Services,” in What Price Mental Health? The Ethics and Politics of Setting Priorities, ed. Boyle, P. (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 1995).Google Scholar