Skip to main content
Log in

Convention, correlation and consistency

  • Book Review
  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Peter Vanderschraaf’s Strategic Justice provides a defense of the egalitarian bargaining solution. Vanderschraaf’s discussion of the egalitarian solution invokes three arguments typically given to support the Nash bargaining solution. Overall, we reinforce Vanderschraaf’s criticism of arguments in favor of the Nash solution and point to potential weaknesses in Vanderschraaf’s positive case for the egalitarian solution.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In particular, they show that there always exists an equilibrium where both make demands compatible with the KS solution and that the KS solution is unique in this respect.

  2. Binmore (1993) offers such a defense, although it is worth noting that Binmore takes aim at procedures that involve an arbitrator. For instance, Moulin (1984) and Bossert and Tan (1995) show how different arbitration methods can lead to the KS and egalitarian solutions, respectively. Since the procedure discussed by Anbarci and Boyd (2011) does not involve an arbitrator, Binmore’s critique does not apply.

  3. This assumes the hare-hunting equilibrium is risk-dominant

  4. The difference between these models is that Young (1993a) investigates the Nash demand game (where bargainers simply issue claims and compatible claims are rewarded) while Young (1998) looks at a “contract” game where agents bargain over terms of a contract and in the end must agree to the same contract (see Young 1998: 783 for a discussion of the differences). In this section we consider a model that is closer to Young (1993a). It would be interesting to see whether similar results can be attained if we modify our model to make it more in-line with Young (1998).

  5. See, however, Bruner (2020).

  6. Some speculation as to why philosophers haven’t turned their attention to the asymmetric bargaining problem: for one, the analysis is cumbersome and can involve simulations that move at a snail’s pace. Second, philosophers for the most part seemed satisfied with Young’s stochastic stability analysis. Finally, it is unclear how one should go about generating asymmetric bargaining problems. We consider one method in this section, and point to the need for more work in this area.

  7. It is worth noting that Vanderschraaf is well aware that his evolutionary analysis of the bargaining problem is suggestive (and not definitive). For this reason, Vanderschraaf places more weight on the consistency argument he provides for egalitarianism in Chapter 8 of Strategic Justice (discussed in Sect. 3 of this paper).

  8. In many cases, it simply is impossible for the results of our simulation to perfectly match a bargaining solution since the claim precision of our simulation is only 1/100.

  9. It is worth noting that this means it is possible for a simulation to “count” for two or even three bargaining solutions despite the fact that the bargaining solutions do not coincide.

  10. When r is instead r = 0.02 the average size of the basin of attraction for the Nash, KS and egalitarian solutions are 0.472, 0.244 and 0.086, respectively.

  11. Ties occurred in cases where solutions either coincide or were extremely close to each other.

References

  • Anbarci, N., & Boyd, J. (2011). Nash demand game and the Kalai–Smorodinsky solution. Games and Economic Behavior, 71(1), 14–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andre, J.-B., & Baumard, N. (2011). Social opportunities and the evolution of fairness. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 289, 128–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Binmore, K. (1993). Bargaining and morality. In D. Gauthier & R. Sugden (Eds.), Rationality, justice and the social contract. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bossert, W., & Tan, G. (1995). An arbitration game and the egalitarian bargaining solution. Social Choice and Welfare, 12(1), 29–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruner, J. P. (2019). Minority (dis)advantage in population games. Synthese, 196, 413–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruner, J. P. (2020). Bargaining and the dynamics of divisional norms. Synthese, 197, 407–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ernst, Z. (2001). Explaining the social contract. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 52(1), 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ernst, Z. (2005). A plea for asymmetric games. Journal of Philosophy, 102(3), 109–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gauthier, D. (1993). Uniting separate persons. In D. Gauthier & R. Sugden (Eds.), Rationality, justice and the social contract: Themes from morals by agreement (pp. 176–192). Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hwang, S. H., Lim, W., Neary, P., & Newton, J. (2018). Conventional contracts, intentional behavior and logit choice: Equality without symmetry. Behav: Games Econ.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kalai, E. (1977). Proportional solution to bargaining situations: Interpersonal utility comparisons. Econometrica, 45(7), 1623–1630.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moehler, M. (2010). The (stabilized) Nash bargaining solution as a principle of distributive justice. Utilitas, 22(4), 447–473.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moehler, M. (2015). Rational cooperation and the Nash bargaining solution. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 18(3), 577–594.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moehler, M. (2018). Minimal morality: A multilevel social contract theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moulin, H. (1984). Implementing the Kalai–Smorodinsky bargaining solution. Journal of Economic Theory, 33(1), 32–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myerson, R. (1977). Two-person bargaining problems and comparable utility. Econometrica, 45(7), 1631–1637.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myerson, R. (1981). Utilitarianism, egalitarianism, and the timing effect in social choice problems. Econometrica, 49(4), 883–897.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newton, J. (2012). Coalitional stochastic stability. Games and Economic Behavior, 75, 842–854.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newton, J. (2018). Evolutionary game theory: A renaissance. Games, 9, 31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubinstein, A. (1982). Perfect equilibrium in a bargaining model. Econometrica, 50(1), 97–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms, B. (1996). Evolution of the social contract. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (1986). The economics of rights, co-operation and welfare. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, J. (1986). Non-cooperative bargaining theory: An introduction. Review of Economic Studies, 53, 709–724.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, W. (2012). On the axiomatics of resource allocation: Interpreting the consistency principle. Economics and Philosophy, 28(3), 385–421.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vanderschraaf, P. (1995). Convention as correlated equilibrium. Erkenntnis, 42, 65–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vanderschraaf, P. (2014). Learning and coordination: Inductive deliberation, equilibrium and convention. Routledge: Taylor and Francis.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Young, P. (1993a). An evolutionary model of bargaining. Journaal of Economic Theory, 59, 145–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Young, P. (1993b). The evolution of conventions. Econometrica, 61(1), 57–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Young, P. (1995). Equity: In theory and practice. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Young, P. (1998). Conventional contracts. Review of Economic Studies, 65, 773–792.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Many thanks to Peter V. (as he likes to be called) for detailed discussion of all things bargaining. I also thank the participants of the Grundlegung Group at the University of Groningen for comments on an earlier draft as well as participants of the Author Meets Critic Session at the 3rd PPE Society Meeting and the Vanderschraaf Workshop at Chapman University.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Justin P. Bruner.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bruner, J.P. Convention, correlation and consistency. Philos Stud 178, 1707–1718 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-020-01499-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-020-01499-8

Keywords

Navigation