Skip to main content

Stromdichtung and subjectivity in the later Heidegger

  • Chapter
Self-Awareness, Temporality, and Alterity

Part of the book series: Contributions to Phenomenology ((CTPH,volume 34))

Abstract

A not uncommon way to mark both the development of Heidegger’s thought and the distinction between the so-called “early” and “later” Heidegger is to focus on his philosophy of the subject. A frequently expressed view of Heidegger is that while Sein und Zeit offers a profound critique of the Cartesian subject, the existential analysis of Dasein still remains within the bounds of a traditional or “modern” view of the subject. This latent, modern view of the subject is said not only to be detectable within the language of “authenticity” and “resoluteness, “ but also to rise to an unfortunate climax in the Rektoratsrede of 1933. Heidegger’s subsequent “turn” (Kehre) is hence linked to a dramatic self-realization about the “subjectivist” nature of his early work and an effort to expunge this latent philosophy of the subject from his later thought. This particular reading of Heidegger, already present in the literature of the late 1940’s, became rather canonical, or at least, it became the passively understood framework from which to understand the development of Heidegger’s thought. Indeed, after William Richardson’s highly influential study of Heidegger, this reading not only became the way to grasp the distinction between what Richardson named “Heidegger I” and “Heidegger II, “ but as is implied by the title of his book—Martin Heidegger: Through Phenomenology to Thought 1—phenomenology itself is identified with a subjectivist perspective.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. William Richardson, Through Phenomenology to Thought (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1962).

    Google Scholar 

  2. See especially the sections on “Gemeingeist” in Edmund Husserl, Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität Texte aus dem Nachlass. Erster Teil (1905–1920). Zweiter Teil (1921–1928). Dritter Teil (1929–1935), hrsg. von Iso Kern, Hua XIII-XV (Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973); see also Hua XXVII, especially 21–23 and 43–59.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Martin Heidegger, Sein und Zeit (Tübingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag, 1979), 384; Being and Time, trans. J. Macquarrie and J. Robinson (New York: Harper and Row, 1962), 435.

    Google Scholar 

  4. SZ, 118ff.;BT, 154ff.

    Google Scholar 

  5. SZ, 384–385; BT, 436.

    Google Scholar 

  6. “Wir leben nicht nur nebeneinander sondern ineinander, ...” Ms. F I 24/76a. See as well, Hua XIV, 179, where Husserl suggests that in true community, “die Ichheit des einen ist nicht neben der des anderen, sondern lebt und wirkt in der anderen.”

    Google Scholar 

  7. Important research in this direction has been conducted by Rudolf Bernet (see for example, La vie du sujet:recherches sur l’interprétation de Husserl dans la phénoménolgie (Paris: P.U.F., 1994).

    Google Scholar 

  8. See Rudolf Bernet, “The Other in Myself, “ in Tradition and Renewal Philosophical Essays Commemorating the Centennial of Louvain ‘s Institute of Philosophy (Leuven, 1992), 61–79. 9.SZ, 130; 57, 168.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Bernet, “The Other in Myself, “ 75.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Martin Heidegger, Die Selbstbehauptung der Deutschen Universität, Das Rektorat 1933/34 (Frankfurt a.M.: Vittorio Klostermann, 1983), 19; “The Self-Assertion of the German University and the Rectorate 1933/34: Facts and Thoughts.” Trans. Karsten Harries. The Review of Metaphysics 38 (March, 1985), 479–480.

    Google Scholar 

  11. OT, 10, 15; SA, 471, 475.

    Google Scholar 

  12. “Aber ich war damals allerdings auch der Überzeugung, dass durch selbstständige Mitarbeit der Geistigen viele wesentlichen Ansätze der “NS. Bewegung” vertieft und gewandelt könnten, um die Bewegung so in den Stand zu setzen, in ihrer Weise mitzuhelfen, die verwirrte Lage Europas und die Krisis des abendländischen Geistes zu überwinden.” Letter to the rectorate of Freiburg, November 4, 1945. Printed in the unpublished doctoral thesis of Karl A. Moehling, “Martin Heidegger and the Nazi Party: An Examination, “ (Diss., Northern Illinois University, 1972), 264–268. One is tempted to be sceptical of Heidegger’s concern for the health of the West: in his rectorial address, mention of the “West” is made only once; for the rest, the crisis seems to have been a peculiarly “German” affair.

    Google Scholar 

  13. SB, 10–11; SA, 471.

    Google Scholar 

  14. SB, 14; A4, 475.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Löwith, Mew Leben in Deutschland, 32ff.

    Google Scholar 

  16. “Schicksal des deutschen Volkes.” SB, 9, 10, 15, 16–17; SA, 470, 471, 475, 477.

    Google Scholar 

  17. SZ, 41–43; BT, 67–68.

    Google Scholar 

  18. SB, 11; SA, 472.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Nevertheless, as Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe points out, a principled opposition to anti-semitism did not prevent Heidegger from cooperating with a movement for which anti-semitism was a principle issue. See Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe, “La fiction du politique, ” in Heidegger: Questions ouvertes, ed. J. Derrida and E. Levinas (Paris: Osiris, 1988), 190. This text is an extract of his full-length book, La fiction du politique (Paris: Christian Bourgois, 1988).

    Google Scholar 

  20. Of course, this is still Heidegger’s belief that the German people have a “special” mission as the heirs of Greek science; this leads leads Derrida to suggest that Heidegger’s thought displays a sort of “metaphysical racism.” Derrida, De l’esprit, 118–119; Of Spirit, 74.

    Google Scholar 

  21. The most evident similarity with the “formation” from below which marks Husserl’s use of the “I”-”We” analogy is that Heidegger too sees the need for a middle step along the way towards authentic community. For Husserl, this middle step is the community of philosophers; for Heidegger, the university. For a reform of the German university to take place, the German student-body must will it, decide it resolutely, determine the essence of the university as the place where science, the questioning of Being, will take place. And as the German university is the place where the “leaders and guardians of the fate of the German people are educated and disciplined” (SB, 10; SA, 471), it is the decision taken within the German university which lays the basis for the decision of the German nation.

    Google Scholar 

  22. On the one hand, the Führer, says Heidegger, does not determine the willing of the people, but is led by that willing (SB, 9; A4, 470.). On the other hand, the most damning statement from Heidegger’s involvement with National Socialism remains: “The Führer alone is the present and future German reality and its law.” Cf. Martin Heidegger, “Aufruf an die Deutschen Studenten” (3. Nov. 1933), printed in Martin Heidegger und das Dritte Reich, ed. B. Martin, (Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1989), 177.

    Google Scholar 

  23. The desire for the unity of the university is seen in Heidegger’s continuous attack on what he sees as the artificial division of the sciences (SB, 13, 15, 17; SA, 473, 474, 478); the subsequent desire for the unity of the German nation at large in the call for all the “services”—“Labour Service (Arbeitsdienst), Armed Service (Wehrdienst), Knowledge Service (Wissensdienst)— primordially coalesce and become one formative force)” (SB, 18; A4, 479).

    Google Scholar 

  24. SB, IS; SA, 419.

    Google Scholar 

  25. SB, 28–29; SA, 488–489.

    Google Scholar 

  26. SB, 18–19; SA, 479.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Martin Heidegger, Hölderlins Hymnen “Germanien” und “der Rhein”, ed. S. Ziegeler, Gesamtausgabe 39 (Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann, 1989);

    Google Scholar 

  28. Hölderlins Hymne “der Ister”, ed. W. Biemel, Gesamtausgabe 53 (Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann, 1984).

    Google Scholar 

  29. GA 39, 20ff.

    Google Scholar 

  30. GA 39, 57–58.

    Google Scholar 

  31. BT, 163; SZ, 126.

    Google Scholar 

  32. GA 53, 178.

    Google Scholar 

  33. GA 53, 41–42.

    Google Scholar 

  34. GA 53, 42.

    Google Scholar 

  35. GA 53, 178.

    Google Scholar 

  36. GA 53, 42–43.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1998 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Buckley, R.P. (1998). Stromdichtung and subjectivity in the later Heidegger. In: Zahavi, D. (eds) Self-Awareness, Temporality, and Alterity. Contributions to Phenomenology, vol 34. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9078-5_13

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9078-5_13

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5031-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-9078-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics