Skip to main content
Log in

Mandatory Disclosure and Medical Paternalism

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Medical practitioners are duty-bound to tell their patients the truth about their medical conditions, along with the risks and benefits of proposed treatments. Some patients, however, would rather not receive medical information. A recent response to this tension has been to argue that that the disclosure of medical information is not optional. As such, patients do not have permission to refuse medical information. In this paper I argue that, depending on the context, the disclosure of medical information can undermine the patient’s ability to exercise her autonomy or have therapeutically detrimental effects. In the light of these insights I go on to develop a context-sensitive approach to medical disclosure. The advantage of this account is that it addresses concerns on both sides of the debate; whilst it acknowledges that patients do not have an exercisable ‘right not to know,’ it allows that in some cases medical information ought to be withheld.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A second requirement of this doctrine is that the patient’s consent is freely given. Because this paper focuses on the disclosure of information, I will not explore the implications of this requirement here.

  2. It is widely acknowledged that it is impossible to give patients ‘full’ or ‘complete’ information about their condition and the treatments available to them. See for instance, Beauchamp and Childress 1989; Grisso and Appelbaum 1998; Brock 1993, and Manson and O’Neill 2007. As such, the demand is only that the patient receives an adequate amount of relevant information in order for her consent to be valid. There is no principled way of determining what information counts as adequate/relevant – but we do have a rough and ready idea. (See, for instance, English et al. 2004: 78)

  3. Many reasons have been given for this, including the importance of respecting the patient, obligations of fidelity and promise-keeping, and establishing trust between the doctor and patient (Beauchamp and Childress 1989)

  4. Discussion as to whether or not patients are permitted to give up their informed consent has been framed in terms of the patient’s possible ‘right not to know.’ (See for instance, Ost 1984 and Laurie 2014). In this paper I have opted not to refer to the patient’s decision to forgo medical information in terms of the ‘right not to know’ in order to avoid the orthogonal discussion as to whether such a right exists.

  5. A full discussion of the reasons why a patient might not want medical information is discussed in Section 4.

  6. This is an approach adopted by both the (Universal Declaration on the Human Genome and Human Rights (UNESCO) (1997) art. 10: 2) and the World Medical Association (WMA) Declaration of Lisbon on the Rights of the Patient 2005, art. 7: d.

  7. See also, Harris and Keywood 2001 and Rhodes 1998.

  8. The waiving of informed consent might be problematic for other reasons (see Beauchamp and Childress 1989). However, the focus of this paper is on the relationship between disclosure and the patient’s preferences for medical information. Given this focus, I will not discuss the ramifications of waiving informed consent here.

  9. It is not my intention in this paper to develop a full analysis of the necessary and sufficient conditions for epistemic paternalism. For this reason I adopt this recent definition without further criticism.

  10. Ahlstrom-Vij (2013) refers to this as the ‘burden-of-proof’ constraint on epistemic paternalism (2013: 135). Note that this does not amount to the more demanding condition that anyone actually benefits epistemically from the interference; the constraint is only that we have good reason for supposing that they will. Such a condition maps on to definitions of paternalism in general which identify the motive (rather than the outcome) of the interferences, as the appropriate criteria for it to count as paternalistic (Shiffrin 2000; Dworkin 1983; New 1999 and Bullock 2015a).

  11. I would like to thank Philip Goff for discussion of this point

  12. See also Angell 2004; Goldacre 2013 and Montori and Guyatt 2007.

  13. As emphasized, the aim of this paper is to object to the argument for mandatory disclosure on its own terms. I am therefore taking it for granted that the proponents of epistemic paternalism have a correct understanding of autonomy. Another approach would be to deny their conception of autonomy altogether (see for instance, Bortolotti 2013; Andorno 2004 and Husted 1997).

  14. This can be a common mistake, since: “[b]y definition, the diagnostic criteria of the moment are always right” (Davis 2010).

  15. For related claims see Manson and O’Neill 2007 and Lamb 1995.

  16. Other empirical studies disagree with this finding. See for instance Galaal et al. (2011) in which there was evidence that psychosexual dysfunction scores were sing significantly lower in women who received informative leaflets compared to those who did not. All this shows, however, is that there is variation in patient response to information. The fact that some patients have elevated anxiety levels is enough to dismiss the paternalistic disclosure of information in all cases.

  17. One could argue, with enough empirical evidence, that the majority of patients will be better off with a policy of mandatory disclosure of information. Since this paper has focuses on the impact of information on individual patients I will not discuss this option here.

  18. This is in part because the exercise of autonomy is plausibly in an individual’s best-interests.

  19. It might be argued that this distinction is not possible, and that patient best-interests are reducible to patient preferences (see Veatch 2000). This would be a separate objection to the mandatory disclosure of medical information. cf. Bullock 2014.

  20. These examples are intended to be illustrative. It should thus be noted that I am not suggesting that whenever a patient is in this situation they ought/ought not be informed. This would be antithetical to the project of varying the decision as to whether to inform patients on the basis of context.

  21. This caveat is needed to rule out the possibility that Bernadette would unwittingly harm herself without this information. We can allow that informing her potential carer might be a pre-condition of her refusing medical information.

  22. I am not suggesting that we have a definitive reason.

  23. These substantive goods need not stand apart. For instance, in some cases disrespect for patient preferences may negatively impact her psychological well-being. Equally, promoting patient autonomy can be directly linked to likely health improvements.

  24. Weighing goods is difficult, but a requirement of justified paternalism (Ahlstrom-Vij 2013)

  25. Protecting this good will rely upon important institutional changes in the procurement, dissemination and interpretation of medical information.

  26. Indeed, these are some of the reasons why paternalism is often found to be objectionable.

  27. In some cases the patient’s preference, let alone her reasons, will not be apparent. If not solicited, the patient’s history of preference for information ought to be taken into consideration.

  28. Classically, the adoption of a policy of disclosing information only when there is good news is self-defeating. This speaks in favor of considering the benefits of disclosure with reference to the other three goods.

  29. I would like to thank an anonymous reviewer for pointing me in this direction

  30. This is often referred to as the ‘disability paradox’ (Ahlbrecht and Devlieger 1999)

  31. I am open to the possibility that there may be other substantive goods to consider, and encourage further discussion along these lines. The suggestion that there are other substantive goods that need to be weighed in the balance does not undermine this account, but complements it.

  32. Thereby moving her scenario [D] to [B].

References

  • Ahlbrecht GL, Devlieger PJ (1999) The disability paradox: high quality of life against all odds. Soc Sci Med 48(8):977–988

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ahlstrom-Vij K (2013) Epistemic paternalism: a defence. Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Andorno R (2004) The right not to know: an autonomy based approach. J Med Ethics 30(5):435–439

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Angell M (2004) Excess in the pharmaceutical industry. Can Med Assoc J 171(12):1451–1453

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arneson RJ (1999) Human flourishing versus desire satisfaction. Soc Philos Policy 16:113–142

  • Beauchamp TL, Childress JF (1989) Principles of biomedical ethics, 3rd edn. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Blumenthal-Barby JS (2013) Choice architecture: a mechanism for improving decisions while preserving liberty. In: Coons C, Weber M (eds) Paternalism: theory and practice. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 178–196

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bortolotti L (2013) The relative importance of undesirable truths. Med Health Care Philos 16(4):683–690

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bortolotti L, Widdows H (2011) The right not to know: the case of psychiatric disorders. J Med Ethics 37(11):673–676

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Botti S, Iyengar SS (2006) The dark side of choice: when choice impairs social welfare. J Public Policy Market 25(1):24–38

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brock DW (1993) Life and death: philosophical essays in biomedical ethics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bullock EC (2014) Free choice and patient best interests. Health Care Anal :1–19. doi:10.1007/s10728-014-0281-8

  • Bullock EC (2015a) A normatively neutral definition of paternalism. Philol Q 65(258):1–21

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bullock EC (2015b) Assisted suicide and the proper role of patient autonomy. In: Cholbi M, Varelius J (ed) New directions in the ethics of assisted suicide and euthanasia. International Library of Ethics, Law, adn the New Medicine Series 64. Springer, Netherlands

  • Burton RA (2008) On being certain: believing you are right even when you're not. St. Martin’s Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Carel H (2007) Can I be ill and happy? Philosophia 35(2):95–110

  • Cohen F, Lazarus RS (1973) Active coping processes, coping dispositions, and recovery from surgery. Psychosom Med 35:375–389

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colloca L, Miller FG (2011) The nocebo effect and its relevance for clinical practice. Psychosom Med 73(7):598–603

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cosgrove L (2011) The DSM, big pharma, and clinical practice guidelines: protecting patient autonomy and informed consent. Int J Fem Approaches Bioethics 4(1):11–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis L (2010) The bioethics of diagnosis: a biocultural critique of certainty. J Bioethic Inq 7(2):227–235

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deakin T, McShane CE, Cade JE, Williams RD (2005) Group based training for self-management strategies in people with type 2 diabetes mellitus. Cochrane Database Syst Rev 2, CD003417

    Google Scholar 

  • Declaration of Helsinki: Ethical Principles for Research Involving Human Subjects (1964; amended 2008) http://www.wma.net/en/30publications/10policies/b3/. Accessed 10 Nov 2008

  • Dworkin G (1983) Paternalism. In: Sartorius R (ed) Paternalism. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, pp 19–34

    Google Scholar 

  • Ende J, Kazis L, Ash A, Moskowitz MA (1989) Measuring patients’ desire for autonomy: decision making and information seeking preferences among medical patients. J Gen Intern Med 4(1):23–30

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • English V, Romano-Critchley G, Sheather J, Sommerville A (2004) Medical ethics today: the BMA’s handbook of ethics and law, 2nd edn. BMJ Books, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan, SM (2012) Adverse outcomes after colposcopy. Dissertation, University of Birmingham

  • Frank JE (2008) The colposcopic examination. J Midwifery Womens Health 53(5):447–452

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galaal K, Bryant A, Deane KH, Al-Khaduri M, Lopes AD (2011) Interventions for reducing anxiety in women undergoing colposcopy. Cochrane Database Syst Rev 12, CD006013

    Google Scholar 

  • Gawande A (2003) Complications: a surgeon's notes on an imperfect science. Profile Books, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Germino BB, Mishel MH, Belyea M, Harris L, Ware A, Mohler J (1998) Uncertainty in prostate cancer: ethnic and family patterns. Cancer Pract 6(2):107–113

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghane A, Huynh HP, Andrews SE, Legg AM, Tabuenca A, Sweeny K (2014) The relative importance of patients’ decisional control preferences and experiences. Psychol Health 29(10):1–29

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldacre B (2013) Bad Pharma: how medicine is broken and how we can fix it. Fourth estate, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Gordon JS (2014) Medical paternalism and patient autonomy. In: Boylan M (ed) Medical ethics, 2nd edn. Wiley Blackwell, West Sussex, pp 72–83

    Google Scholar 

  • Grisso T, Appelbaum PS (1998) Assessing competence to consent to treatment: a guide for physicians and other health professionals. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris J, Keywood K (2001) Ignorance, information and autonomy. Theor Med Bioeth 22(5):415–436

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Higgs R (1999) On telling patients the truth. In: Kuhse H, Singer P (eds) Bioethics: an anthology. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 507–512

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodkinson K (2013) The need to know – therapeutic privilege, a way forward. Health Care Anal 21:105–129

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Husted J (1997) Autonomy and a right not to know. In: Chadwick R, Levitt M, Shickle D (eds) The right to know and the right not to know. Ashgate, Aldershot, pp 55–68

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson J (2001) Truth, trust and medicine. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones MA (1999) Informed consent and other fairy stories. Med Law Rev 7:103–134

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan RM (1991) Health‐related quality of life in patient decision making. J Soc Issues 47(4):69–90

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan SH, Greenfield S, Ware JE (1989) Assessing the effects of physician-patient interactions on the outcomes of chronic disease. Med Care 27(3):S110–S127

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Karkazis K (2008) Fixing sex: intersex, medical authority and lived experience. Duke University Press, Durham

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Katz J (2002) The silent world of doctor and patient. The John Hopkins University Press, Baltimore

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein G (1996) Sources of power: how people make decisions. MIT Press, USA

    Google Scholar 

  • Lamb D (1995) Therapy abatement, autonomy and futility: ethical decisions at the edge of life. Avebury, Aldershot

    Google Scholar 

  • Laurie G (2014) Recognizing the right not to know: conceptual, professional, and legal implications. J Law Med Ethics 42(1):53–63

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longtin Y, Sax H, Leape LL, Sheridan SE, Donaldson L, Pittet D (2010) Patient participation: current knowledge and applicability to patient safety. Mayo Clin Proc 85(1):53–62

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luce MF (2005) Decision making as coping. Health Psychol 24:S23–S28

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malpas P (2005) The right to remain in ignorance about genetic information--can such a right be defended in the name of autonomy? N Z Med J 118:71–78

    Google Scholar 

  • Manson NC, O’Neill O (2007) Rethinking informed consent in bioethics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Miller SM, Mangan CE (1983) Interacting effects of information and coping style in adapting to gynaecologic stress: should the doctor tell all? J Pers Soc Psychol 45(1):223–236

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mishel MH (1997) Uncertainty in acute illness. Ann Rev Nurs Res 15(1):57–80

  • Montori VM, Guyatt GH (2007) Corruption of the evidence as threat and opportunity for evidence-based medicine. Harv Health Policy Rev 8(1):145–155

    Google Scholar 

  • New B (1999) Paternalism and public policy. Econ Philos 15(1):63–83

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newbould M (2013) Intersex, medicine and pathologization. In: Carel H, Cooper R (eds) Health, illness and disease: philosophical essays. Acumen, Durham, pp 161–180

    Google Scholar 

  • Ost DE (1984) The ‘Right’ not to know. J Med Philos 9:201–312

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parascandola M, Hawkins J, Danis M (2002) Patient autonomy and the challenge of clinical uncertainty. Kennedy Inst Ethics J 12(3):245–264

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rhodes R (1998) Genetic links, family ties, and social bonds: rights and responsibilities in the face of genetic knowledge. J Med Philos 23:10–30

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robinson A, Thomson R (2001) Variability in patient preferences for participating in medical decision making: implication for the use of decision support tools. Qual Health Care 10:i34–i38

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon T (1993) Value, desire and quality of life. In: Nussbaum MC, Sen A (eds) The Quality of Life. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp. 185–200

  • Schneider C (1998) The practice of autonomy: patients, doctors, and medical decisions. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Shiffrin SV (2000) Paternalism, unconscionability doctrine, and accommodation. Philos Public Aff 29(3):205–250

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stewart MA (1995) Effective physician-patient communication and health outcomes: a review. Can Med Assoc J 152:1423–1433

    Google Scholar 

  • Takala T (2001) Genetic ignorance and reasonable paternalism. Theor Med Bioeth 22(5):485–491

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson C, Dowding D (2001) Responding to uncertainty in nursing practice. Int J Nurs Pract 38(5):609–615

    Google Scholar 

  • United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization (UNESCO) (1997) Universal Declaration on the human genome and human rights http://portal.unesco.org/en/ev.php-URL_ID=13177&URL_DO=DO_TOPIC&URL_SECTION=201.html. Accessed 4 Dec 2014

  • Veatch RM (2000) Doctor does not know best: why in the new century physicians must stop trying to benefit patients. J Med Philos 25(6):701–721

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Von Korff M, Katon W, Rutter C, Ludman E, Simon G, Lin E, Bush T (2003) Effect on disability outcomes of a depression relapse prevention program. Psychosom Med 65:938–943

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walker T (2013) Respecting autonomy without disclosing information. Bioethics 27(7):388–394

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weingarten SR, Henning JM, Badamgarav E, Knight K, Hasselblad V, Gano A Jr, Ofman JJ (2002) Interventions used in disease management programmes for patients with chronic illness—which ones work? Meta-analysis of published reports. Br Med J 325(7370):925–933

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wennberg JE (2010) Tracking medicine: a researcher’s quest to understand health care. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson J (2005) To know or not to know? Genetic ignorance, autonomy and paternalism. Bioethics 19(5–6):492–504

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • World Medical Association (WMA) (2005) Declaration of lisbon on the rights of the patient http://www.wma.net/en/30publications/10policies/l4/. Accessed 4 Dec 2014

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank my colleagues at Central European University for their comments on an earlier draft of this paper. Substantial revisions of the paper were carried out at the Ethox Centre, Oxford as part of the Caroline Miles visiting scholarship; many thanks, especially to Michael Parker, Michael Dunn and Mark Sheehan. I am also grateful to members of the Institut für Experimentelle Medizin department, Christian-Albrechts-Universität zu Kiel for their insightful comments, and to two anonymous reviewers for their encouragement and direction.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Emma C. Bullock.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bullock, E.C. Mandatory Disclosure and Medical Paternalism. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 19, 409–424 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-015-9632-2

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-015-9632-2

Keywords

Navigation