Skip to main content
Log in

Formal schemas of induction as models

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

What is the relation or connection between formalizations of induction and the actual inductive inferences of scientists? Building from recent works in the philosophy of logic, this paper argues that these formalizations of induction are best viewed as models and not literal descriptions of inductive inferences in science. Three arguments are put forward to support this claim. First, I argue that inductive support is the kind of phenomenon that can be justifiably modeled. Second, I argue that these formalizations have the features that define models—that they have representors, artefacts, and idealizations. Third, I argue that these formalizations being models explains their plurality and revisability.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Data availability

Not applicable.

Code availability

Not applicable.

Notes

  1. The terms ‘confirmation,’ ‘inductive support,’ ‘induction,’ and ‘inductive inference’ will be used almost interchangeably in this paper. They are of course different but related notions. ‘To confirm’ could be construed as synonymous to ‘to lend inductive support’. Moreover, the mental or psychological process of lending inductive support to a scientific theory is called induction or inductive inference. To be consistent, I will mostly employ the terms ‘inductive support,’ ‘induction,’ and ‘inductive inference’ instead of ‘confirmation’.

  2. For an in-depth discussion of these two senses of formality, see Dutilh-Novaes (2011).

  3. Given this, I will refer to these formalizations as formal schemas of induction beginning in Sect. 2.

  4. The summary is largely informed by Cook (2002).

  5. For a discussion of the desideratum of accuracy in the context of the sciences, see Chapter 6 of Weisberg (2013). For its discussion in the context of logic, see Baumgartner and Lampert (2008).

  6. This formulation of the desideratum of fruitfulness is informed by the discussion of Kitcher (2008) and Pinder (2022).

  7. Sharpening or precisification is a term of art used by philosophers to refer to the activity of making an inexact or imprecise concept (due to vagueness, indeterminacy, polysemy, etc.) more exact or precise. See Keefe (2014, p. 1378).

  8. To forestall misunderstanding, it should be noted that this claim is predicated on the traditional view of concepts which typically construe concepts as “beliefs about the concept’s referent” or as “representations of phenomena” (Brigandt & Rosario, 2020, pp. 102). This is why I take the polysemy, and hence the complexity, of the concept of inductive support as evidence or indication of the complexity of the phenomenon of inductive inference itself.

  9. I remain neutral on the issue of whether polysemous concepts require the stronger activities of improvement and replacement.

  10. To simplify the prose, I will drop the qualification ‘parameterized’ and continue to say that these intuitive notions are the target systems of these formal schemas. But when saying that, I should be construed as referring to their parameterized versions.

  11. The ceteris paribus clause here is meant to signal the fact that the admissibility of these formal schemas still depends on their satisfaction of the desiderata of adequacy discussed in Sect. 2. So, admissibility here should be understood as admissibility on account of the legitimacy of their target system.

  12. Bielik (2018) arrives at the same conclusion.

  13. I recognize that their admissibility still depends on how well they fair in the other desideratum of adequacy (e.g., accuracy, simplicity, and exactness). But if we accept, as many model-builders do, that fruitfulness is the primary desideratum of adequacy, then a plurality of models would still be expected.

  14. These arguments take inspiration from Russell’s reconstruction of purported arguments for the normativity of logic. See Russell (2020).

  15. This seems to be the upshot of the so called ‘accuracy’ argument provided by Joyce (1998) and Pettigrew (2016). This argument purports to show that agents who violate probabilism, and so logical omniscience, have less accurate attitudes compared to those who conform to probabilism.

  16. This argument closely follows Russell’s reconstruction of the argument from error for the normativity of logic. See Russell (2020).

  17. These various senses of the term ‘model’ are discussed by Thomson-Jones (2006, 2012).

References

  • Achinstein, P. (2001). The book of evidence. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balcerak Jackson, B. (2014). Verbal disputes and substantiveness. Erkenntnis, 79(1), 31–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baumgartner, M., & Lampert, T. (2008). Adequate formalization. Synthese, 164(1), 93–115.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bielik, L. (2018). Explication, H-D confirmation, and simplicity. Erkenntnis, 83(5), 1085–1104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, I., & Rosario, E. (2020). Strategic conceptual engineering for epistemic and social aims. In A. Burgess, H. Cappelen, & D. Plunkett (Eds.), Conceptual engineering and conceptual ethics (pp. 100–124). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. (2022). Conceptual role expressivism and defective concepts. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics (Vol. 17, pp. 225–253). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, H. (2018). Fixing language: An essay on conceptual engineering. Oxford University Press.

  • Cappelen, H., & Plunkett, D. (2020). A guided tour of conceptual engineering and conceptual ethics. In H. Cappelen, D. Plunkett, & A. Burgess (Eds.), Conceptual engineering and conceptual ethics (pp. 1–26). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1962). The logical foundations of probability. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2011). Verbal disputes. Philosophical Review, 120(4), 515–566.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, D. (2004). Putting logic in its place. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colyvan, M. (2013). Idealisations in normative models. Synthese, 190(8), 1337–13350.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cook, R. (2002). Vagueness and mathematical precision. Mind, 111(442), 225–247.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cook, R. (2010). Let a thousand flowers bloom: A tour of logical pluralism. Philosophy Compass, 5(6), 492–504.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dutilh-Novaes, C. (2011). The different ways in which logic is (said to be) formal. History and Philosophy of Logic, 32(4), 303–332.

    Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J. (1992). Bayes or bust? Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Easwaran, K. (2011). Bayesianism II: Applications and criticisms. Philosophy Compass, 6(5), 321–332.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edgington, D. (1992). Validity, uncertainty, and vagueness. Analysis, 52(4), 193–204.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edgington, D. (1996). Vagueness by degrees. In R. Keefe & P. Smith (Eds.), Vagueness: A reader (pp. 294–316). Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elliott-Graves, A. (2020). What is a target system? Biology and Philosophy, 35(2), 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garber, D. (1983). Old evidence and logical omniscience in the Bayesian confirmation theory. In J. Earman (Ed.), Testing scientific theories (pp. 99–132). University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gemes, K. (1993). Hypothetico-deductivism, content, and the natural axiomatization of theories. Philosophy of Science, 60(3), 477–487.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gemes, K. (1994). A new theory of content I: Basic content. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 23(6), 595–620.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gemes, K. (1998). Hypothetico-deductivism: The current state of the play; The criterion of empirical Significance: Endgame. Erkenntnis, 49(1), 1–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glymour, C. (1980). Theory and evidence. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grimes, T. (1990). Truth, content, and the hypothetico-deductive method. Philosophy of Science, 57(3), 514–522.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. (1945). Studies in the logic of confirmation part 1. Mind, 54(219), 1–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. (1966). Philosophy of natural science. Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horwich, P. (1986). Probability and evidence. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howson, C., & Urbach, P. (2006). Scientific reasoning: The Bayesian approach (3rd ed.). Carus Publishing Company.

  • Huber, F. (2008). The plausibility-informativeness theory. In V. Hendricks & D. Pritchard (Eds.), New waves in epistemology (pp. 164–191). Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jenkins, C. S. I. (2014). Merely verbal disputes. Erkenntnis, 79(1), 11–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, J. (1998). A nonpragmatic vindication of probabilism. Philosophy of Science, 65(4), 575–603.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, J. (2005). How probabilities reflect evidence. Philosophical Perspectives, 19(1), 153–178.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, M. (1996). Decision theory as philosophy. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keefe, R. (2012). Modelling vagueness: What can we ignore? Philosophical Studies, 161(3), 453–470.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keefe, R. (2014). What logical pluralism cannot be. Synthese, 191(7), 1375–1390.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2008). Carnap and the caterpillar. Philosophical Topics, 36(1), 111–127.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levi, I. (1980). The enterprise of knowledge. Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press.

  • Levins, R. (1966). The strategy of model building in population biology. In E. Sober (Ed.), Conceptual issues in evolutionary biology (pp. 18–27). Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maher, P. (1996). Subjective and objective confirmation. Philosophy of Science, 63(2), 149–174.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettigrew, R. (2016). Accuracy and laws of credence. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinder, M. (2022). What ought a fruitful explicatum to be? Erkenntnis, 87(2), 913–932.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1959). The logic of scientific discovery. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reiss, J. (2014). What’s wrong with our theories of evidence. Theoria, 29(2), 283–306.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1958). A theory of evidence. Philosophy of Science, 25(1), 83–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, G. (2020). Logic isn’t normative. Inquiry, 63(3–4), 371–388.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1975). Confirmation and relevance. In G. Maxwell & R. Anderson (Eds.), Induction, probability, and confirmation (pp. 3–32). The University of Minnesota.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scharp, K. (2013). Replacing truth. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scharp, K. (2020). Philosophy as the study of defective concepts. In H. Cappelen, D. Plunkett, & A. Burgess (Eds.), Conceptual engineering and conceptual ethics (pp. 396–416). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (1991). Relevant deduction: From solving paradoxes towards a general theory. Erkenntnis, 35(1–3), 391–437.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (1994). Relevant deduction and hypothetico-deductivism: A reply to Gemes. Erkenntnis, 41(2), 183–188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (2014). Philosophy of science: A unified approach. Routledge.

  • Shapiro, S. (1997). Philosophy of mathematics: Structure and ontology. Oxford University Press.

  • Shapiro, S. (2006a). Computability, proof, and open-texture. In A. Olszewski, J. Wolenski, & R. Janusz (Eds.), Church’s thesis after 70 years (pp. 420–455). Ontos Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, S. (2006b). Vagueness in context. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, S. (2014). Varieties of logic. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smithies, D. (2015). Ideal rationality and logical omniscience. Synthese, 192(9), 2769–2793.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sprenger, J. (2011). Hypothetico-deductive confirmation. Philosophy Compass, 6(7), 497–508.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sprenger, J. (2014). Confirmation and induction. In P. Humphreys (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of science (pp. 185–209). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Talbot, W. (2016). Bayesian epistemology. In E. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/epistemology-bayesian/

  • Thomson-Jones, M. (2006). Models and the semantic view. Philosophy of Science, 73(5), 524–535.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson-Jones, M. (2012). Modelling without mathematics. Philosophy of Science, 79(5), 761–772.

    Google Scholar 

  • Titelbaum, M. (2016). Normative modeling. In J. Horvath (Ed.), Methods in analytic philosophy: A contemporary reader. Bloomsbury Academic. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/18670/

  • van Fraassen, B. (1984). Belief and the will. The Journal of Philosophy, 81(5), 235–256.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vermeulen, I. (2018). Verbal disputes and the varieties of verbalness. Erkenntnis, 83(2), 331–348.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2007). Who is a modeler? British Journal for Philosophy of Science, 58(2), 207–233.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2013). Simulations and Similarity: Using models to understand the world. Oxford University Press.

  • Whewell, W. (1847). Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences, founded upon their history. Parker.

  • Williamson, J. (2010). In defense of objective Bayesianism. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2017). Model-building in philosophy. In R. Blackford & D. Broderick (Eds.), Philosophy’s future: The problem of philosophical progress (pp. 159–172). Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yap, A. (2014). Idealization, epistemic logic, and epistemology. Synthese, 191(14), 3351–3366.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zynda, L. (1996). Coherence as an ideal of rationality. Synthese, 109(2), 175–216.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zynda, L. (2000). Representation theorems and realism about degrees of belief. Philosophy of Science, 67(1), 45–69.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

My gratitude goes to my teachers and colleagues Kelly Louise Rexzy P. Agra, Ben Carlo N. Atim, Romulo T. Bañares, Karen D. De Castro, Gerald Pio M. Franco, Zosimo E. Lee, Julius D. Mendoza, Olivia Mendoza-Santos, Narcisa Paredes-Canilao, and Franz Joseph C. Yoshiy II for very helpful comments on earlier versions of this paper. My thanks also goes to two anonymous referees whose comments and suggestions greatly improved this paper. I dedicate this first publication of mine to my family and my Balaysian and UP junior faculty friends. Their company, support, and unconditional love made this work possible.

Funding

The author declares that this work received no funding from any institution.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Vlademire Kevin D. Bumatay.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author declares no conflicts of interest.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bumatay, V.K.D. Formal schemas of induction as models. Synthese 200, 470 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03921-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03921-6

Keywords

Navigation