Skip to main content
Log in

Classical and revisionary theism on the divine as personal: a rapprochement?

  • Article
  • Published:
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

To claim that the divine is a person or personal is, according to Swinburne, ‘the most elementary claim of theism’ (The coherence of theism, 1993, p. 101). I argue that, whether the classical theist’s concept of the divine as a person or personal is construed as an analogy or a metaphor, or a combination of the two, analysis necessitates qualification of that concept such that any differences between the classical theist’s concept of the divine as a person or personal and revisionary interpretations of that concept are merely superficial. Thus, either the classical theist has more in common with revisionary theism than he/she might care to admit, or classical theism is a multi-faceted position which encompasses interpretations which some might regard as revisionist. This article also explores and employs the use of a gender-neutral pronoun in talk about God.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I use the terms ‘revisionary’ and ‘revisionist’ interchangeably.

  2. Wynn uses the term ‘classical’ to describe versions of theism which claim that ‘God is pure being and therefore “simple”’ (1997, p. 91). Some scholars have argued that a timeless God could not be a person, a claim which is discussed by Deweese (2004, Chap. 8) and disputed by Helm (1988, Chap. 4).

  3. Deweese notes that ‘[t]he criteria of personhood are very much in debate in contemporary philosophy, from applied ethics, dealing with beginning- and end-of-life issues, to cognitive science, dealing with artificial intelligence’ (216).

  4. Wolf (1964, p. 28) notes that some of the earliest uses of the phrase ‘the personality of God’ may be found in Paley (1850), and the first edition of Schliermacher (1958) (Wolf 1964, p. 28). Hick notes that ‘person’ understood in the ‘modern’ sense—i.e., as an individual centre of consciousness and will—also features in “‘social” conceptions of the trinity as three personal centres so intimately united as to form a complex unity of three-in-one’ (2004, p. 270).

  5. Davies follows philosophers such as Ryle (1949), Wittgenstein (1968), Smart (1959), and Armstrong (1968).

  6. Jantzen offers a recent example of such a view (1984, esp. Chap. 5), although Levine notes that ‘Pantheists usually deny the existence of a “personal” God’ (1994, p. 2).

  7. For example, the teaching that Allah has two hands has been commonly interpreted by Muslim scholars as a symbol for divine power, while Ibn Arabi argued that it is a symbol for the polarities, the opposites, which exist within human beings. See Sells (1994), p. 86.

  8. There are, of course, other interpretations of analogy (see, e.g., White 2010). I discuss Swinburne here because he adopts an analogical interpretation of God as a person.

  9. Since few would argue that the divine is literally masculine, I adopt the gender-neutral pronoun ‘xe’ (pronounced ‘zi’). According to Mario Pei, Don Rickter notes the use of ‘xe, xen, xes’ (for ‘he/she’, ‘his/her’, ‘him/her’) in the United Nations World of 1 May 1973 (Pei 1978, p.  145). Others attribute the first use of ‘xe’ to the UU World (the Unitarian Universalist publication) of the same date, with an independent invention of the term by Jim Sinclair in 1992 (Wiktionary 2014), but I am unable to access the publications in question in order to check this. A gender-neutral pronoun may be employed to mean ‘he, she, or it’, but also to indicate a person of unspecified gender. While some languages already employ gender-neutral pronouns, and Sweden has recently (2012) adopted ‘hen’, there is no generally-accepted English term. From those which have been suggested, I have chosen ‘xe’ to refer to divinity conceived of as a person, or personal, on the grounds that the ‘x’ which replaces the first two letters of the gendered pronouns seems particularly appropriate in the context of an apophatic theology. There are some variations in use but, for the purposes of this article, ‘xe’ is formed as follows: xe (he/she/it), xem (him/her/it), xir (his/her/its—i.e., possessive determiner), xirs (his/hers/its—i.e., possessive pronoun), xemself (himself/herself/itself) (adapted from the table found at Wikipedia 2014).

  10. Thatcher claims that belief that God is a person is an impediment to Christian faith, but that belief in a personal God is essential to it (1985, p. 61), while Davies argues that God is personal on the grounds that God has knowledge and will and is active (2000, pp. 561–563).

  11. Pailin uses this word to describe the position of Jaspers (Jaspers 1967, p. 141ff; Pailin 1976, p. 149). See also Küng (1980, p. 633), quoted in Thatcher (1985, p. 72) and Ward (1992, p. 265).

  12. There are, of course, alternative interpretations of metaphor. For example, Harrison (2007) argues that, following the work of Lakoff and Johnson (1980), metaphor should be seen as reality-constituting, and therefore as reality-transforming—i.e., as changing the way in which we experience the world. Soskice rejects this example of what she terms ‘the metaphor-as-myth thesis’ (1985, pp. 81–82), while Stiver draws out the similarities between Lakoff and Johnson’s position on the one hand, and that of Soskice on the other (1996, p. 120, 126).

  13. Brümmer draws on McFague (1982, p. 13) here.

  14. This possibility had been previously mentioned but dismissed by Thatcher (1985, p. 67).

  15. There are, of course, other possible explanations which, for non-believers, represent a better fit with the observed phenomena.

  16. I use ‘non-realism’ to refer to agnosticism about a God who exists independently of human thought—as opposed to ‘anti-realism’ which claims that there is no God existing independently of human thought.

  17. Flew seems to have changed his mind about this at the end of his life (Flew 2007).

  18. Cf. Harrison’s recommendation that we should adopt a ‘family resemblance’ approach to differing interpretations of the same religion (2006, pp. 147–152).

  19. Phillips himself denies this, although he is almost as reluctant to describe himself as a realist—he sees the terms ‘non-realism’ and ‘realism’ as ‘battle-cries in a confused philosophical debate’ (1993, p. 35).

  20. I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for the observation that my argument depends upon the idea that it is ‘proper’ to treat ‘divine personhood’ and ‘divine agency’ as metaphors at least partially [properly] explained in terms of analogy, and the suggestion that some classical theists hold that God is a person and an agent in a straightforward literal sense, while some revisionist theists deny that God is a person and an agent in even a metaphorical sense. My argument, however, is that the reflective classical theist cannot hold that God is a person and an agent in a straightforward literal sense. And, while it is true that some revisionist theists deny that God is a person and an agent in even a metaphorical sense, I would argue that, at least for those whose beliefs are derived from the Abrahamic tradition, in which God as a personal agent features prominently, it is not necessary even for the revisionist to jettison this important aspect of religious belief.

References

  • Armstrong, D. (1968). A materialist theory of mind. New York: Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brümmer, V. (2005). Atonement, christology and the trinity: Making sense of Christian doctrine. Basingstoke: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brümmer, V. (2006). Brümmer on meaning and the Christian faith: Collected writings of Vincent Brümmer. Basingstoke: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cupitt, D. (1998). The revelation of being. London: SCM Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cupitt, D. (2001). Reforming christianity. London: SCM Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, B. (2000). A modern defence of divine simplicity. In B. Davies (Ed.), Philosophy of religion: A guide and anthology (pp. 549–564). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, B. (2006). The reality of God and the problem of evil. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deweese, G. J. (2004). God and the nature of time. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flew, A. (1990). Theology and falsification. In J. Hick (Ed.), Classical and contemporary readings in the philosophy of religion (pp. 367–390). Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flew, A. (2007). There is a God: How the world’s most notorious atheist changed his mind. New York: HarperCollins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaskin, J. (2000). Gods, ghosts and curious persons. Philosophical Writings, 13, 71–80.

  • Harrison, V. (2006). The pragmatics of defining religion in a multi-cultural world. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 59(3), 133–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harrison, V. (2007). Metaphor, religious language and religious experience. Sophia, 46(2), 127–145.

  • Helm, P. (1988). Eternal God: A study of God without time. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hepburn, R. W. (1970). Poetry and religious belief. In S. Toulmin, R. W. Hepburn, & A. MacIntyre (Eds.), Metaphysical beliefs (pp. 73–156). London: SCM Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hick, J. (2004). An Interpretation of religion: Human responses to the transcendent. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hick, J. (2006). The new frontier of religion and science: Religious experience, neuroscience and the transcendent. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jantzen, G. M. (1984). God’s world, God’s body. London: Darton, Longman and Todd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaspers, K. (1967). Philosophical faith and revelation. London: Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Küng, H. (1980). Does God exist? London: Collins.

  • Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1980). Metaphors we live by. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Legenhausen, G. (1986). Is God a person? Religious Studies, 22, 307–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levine, M. J. (1994). Pantheism: A non-theist concept of deity. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mander, W. J. (1997). God and personality. Heythrop Journal, 38, 401–412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McFague, S. (1982). Metaphorical theology. London: Fortress Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pailin, D. (1976). The humanity of the theologian and the personal nature of God. Religious Studies, 12, 141–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paley, W. (1850). Natural theology. Boston: Gould, Kendall and Lincoln.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pei, M. (1978). Weasel words: The art of saying what you don’t mean. New York: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, D. Z. (1993). Religion in Wittgenstein’s mirror. DZ Phillips, Wittgenstein and religion (pp. 237–255). New York: St Martin’s Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, D. Z. (2002). Propositions, pictures and practices. Ars disputandi, 2. Retrieved August 4, 2014, from http://www.tandfonline.com/doi/abs/10.1080/15665399.2002.10819746#.U99vgZUg_IU

  • Rice, H. (2000). God and Goodness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, J. A. T. (1963). Honest to God. London: SCM Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, J. A. T. (1967). Exploration into God. London: SCM Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. London: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schliermacher, F. (1958). On religion: Speeches to its cultured despisers (J. Oman, Trans.). New York: Harper

  • Sells, M. A. (1994). Mystical languages of unsaying. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smart, J. J. C. (1959). Sensations and brain processes. Philosophical Review, 68, 141–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Soskice, J. (1985). Metaphor and religious language. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stiver, D. R. (1996). The philosophy of religious language: Sign, symbol and story. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, R. (1993). The coherence of theism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Thatcher, A. (1985). The personal God and the God who is a person. Religious Studies, 21, 61–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tillich, P. (1978). Systematic theology volume I: Reason and revelation, being and god. London: SCM Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trigg, R. (1998). Rationality and religion: Does faith need reason?. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ward, K. (1992). Is God a person? In G. van den Brink, L. J. van den Bron, & M. Sarot (Eds.), Christian faith and philosophical theology: Essays in honour of Vincent Brümmer (pp. 258–266). Kampen: Kok Pharos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Webb, C. C. J. (1919). God and personality. London: George Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • White, R. M. (2010). Talking about God: The concept of analogy and the problem of religious language. Farnham: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wikipedia. (2014). Gender-specific and gender-neutral pronouns. Retrieved August 4, 2014, from http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Gender-specific_and_gender-neutral_pronouns

  • Wiktionary. (2014). Xe. Retrieved August 4, 2014, from http://en.wiktionary.org/wiki/xe

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1966). Lectures and conversations on aesthetics, psychology and religious belief. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1968). Philosophical investigations. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, H. C. (1964). An introduction to the idea of God as person. Journal of Bible and Religion, 32, 26–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wynn, M. (1997). Simplicity, personhood, and divinity. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 41, 91–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Vincent Brümmer and Victoria Harrison, who drew my attention to their own work on metaphor and religious language, and to Stephen Law and Keith Ward for their comments on an earlier draft of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Elizabeth Burns.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Burns, E. Classical and revisionary theism on the divine as personal: a rapprochement?. Int J Philos Relig 78, 151–165 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-014-9500-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-014-9500-3

Keywords

Navigation