Skip to main content
Log in

Religion and scientism: a shared cognitive conundrum

  • Article
  • Published:
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article challenges the claim that the rise of naturalism is devastating to religious belief. This claim hinges on an extreme interpretation of naturalism called scientism, the metaphysical view that science offers an exhaustive account of the real. For those committed to scientism, religious discourse is epistemically illegitimate, because it refers to matters that transcend—and so cannot be verified by—scientific inquiry. This article reconstructs arguments from the phenomenological tradition that seem to undercut this critique, viz., arguments that scientism itself cannot be justified without recourse to matters that transcend scientific inquiry. If this is true, then scientism and religion share a cognitive conundrum: a commitment to truths that cannot in principle be known from our current perspective.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This is a central theme in a number of popular books by the so-called ‘New Atheists’: Dennett (2006), Dawkins (2006), Harris (2004), and Hitchins (2007).

  2. Worrall (2004, p. 60).

  3. Papineau (2009).

  4. McDowell (1998, p. 173).

  5. This is J.J.C. Smart’s term. In his (1959), ‘Sensations and Brain Processes’, he argues that mental states must be identified with brain states if they are not to become “nomological danglers”, i.e., entities that play no role in the explanation of behavior.

  6. McDowell, op. cit., p. 173.

  7. Husserl (1965). Henceforth cited in the text as ‘PS’.

  8. Husserl never uses the term scientism, but what he has in his sights is pretty close to ‘bald’ or ‘hard naturalism’, so I will continue to use the term scientism.

  9. Greenberg and Arndt (2011).

  10. Heidegger (1998, p. 84).

  11. Husserl (2012, p. 118).

  12. Husserl’s argument against strong naturalism clearly bears a certain resemblance to Alvin Plantinga’s argument in “An evolutionary argument against naturalism” (1999).

  13. Nagel (1974).

  14. Chalmers (1995).

  15. Heidegger (1965, p. 42/68). [Henceforth cited as BT with German pagination followed by the English].

  16. For an in-depth discussion of the concept of mineness and the essential role that it plays in the possibility of consciousness, see Zahavi (1999).

  17. Husserl explores this feature of the first-person perspective in Meditation I of his Cartesian Meditations (1960) and in the Epilogue of his Ideas Pertaining to Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy, Book II (1990a).

  18. To my knowledge John Haugeland offers the best defense there is of the claim that existential commitment underwrites all scientific research. See his Having Thought: Essays in the Metaphysics of Mind (1998).

  19. My discussion of the concept of practical identity here is inspired by Christine Korsgaard’s work (especially The Sources of Normativity, 1996) and Heidegger’s account of the self as “being-in-the-world” Division I of Being and Time (1962). For an illuminating analysis of Heidegger and Korsgaard’s respective conceptions of practical identity, see Crowell (2007).

  20. McDowell (1998, p. 173).

  21. Crowell makes a start at formulating a phenomenological approach to soft naturalism in light of Husserl’s critique of scientism in “Philosophy as a Rigorous Science.” See his Normativity and Phenomenology in Husserl and Heidegger (2013).

  22. Yoshimi (2015).

  23. For a balanced perspective on this movement, see the following: Bornemark and Ruin (2010), Janicaud et al. (2001), Schunke (2009) and Tengelyi (2012).

  24. Marion (2002).

  25. Levinas (1987, p.59).

  26. I analyze Marion’s breach of phenomenological method in Burch (2010).

  27. Heidegger (1992, p. 80).

  28. Heidegger (1999, p. 22). [Henceforth cited as OHF].

  29. Husserl (1990b, p. 406).

  30. This is by no means an exhaustive list. Phenomenology has been clarifying first-person phenomena that undermine scientism for over a century now, and it has uncovered too many to address here.

References

  • Bornemark, J., & Ruin, H. (2010). Phenomenology and religion: New frontiers. Södertörn: Södertörn University Library Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burch, M. I. (2010). Blurred vision: Marion on the ‘Possibility’ of revelation. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 67(3), 157–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (1995). Facing up to the problem of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2(3), 200–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crowell, S. (2007). Sorge or Selbstbewusstsein? Heidegger and Korsgaard on the sources of normativity. European Journal of Philosophy, 15(3), 315–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crowell, S. (2013). Normativity and phenomenology in Husserl and Heidegger. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. (2006). The god delusion. New York: Mariner Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (2006). Breaking the spell: Religion as a natural phenomenon. New York: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenberg, J., & Arndt, J. (2011). Terror management theory. Handbook of Theories of Social Psychology, 1, 398–415.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, S. (2004). The end of faith. New York: Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland, J. (1998). Having thought: Essays in the metaphysics of mind. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and time (J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson, Trans.). New York: Harper and Row.

  • Heidegger, M. (1965) Being and time (J. Macquarrie and E. Robinso, Trans.). San Francisco: Harper & Row.

  • Heidegger, M. (1992). History of the Concept of Time: Prolegomena (Theodore Kisiel, Trans.). Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (1998). What is metaphysics. In W. McNeill (Ed.), Pathmarks. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1999). Ontology: The Hermeneutics of Facticity (John van Buren, Trans). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  • Hitchins, C. (2007). God is not great. New York: Twelve.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1960). Cartesian meditations. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1965). Philosophy as rigorous science. In Phenomenology and the crisis of philosophy (Quentin Lauer, Trans.). New York: Harper & Row.

  • Husserl, E. (1990a). Ideas pertaining to pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy, Book II (R. Rojcewicz and A. Schuwer, Trans.). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

  • Husserl, E. (1990b). Ideas II (R. Rojcewicz and A. Schuwer, Trans.). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

  • Husserl, E. (2012). Logical investigations (Vol. 1). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Janicaud, D., Courtine, J.-F., et al. (2001). Phenomenology and the theological turn: The French debate. New York: Fordham University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. (1996). The normative question. In O. O’Neill (Ed.), The sources of normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, E. (1987). Philosophy and the idea of infinity. In Collected Papers (A. Lingis, Trans.). Boston: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers.

  • Marion, J.-L. (2002). Being given: Toward a phenomenology of givenness. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1998). Mind, value, and reality. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? The Philosophical Review, 83(4), 435–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (2009). Naturalism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2009 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2009/entries/naturalism/.

  • Plantinga, A. (1999). An evolutionary argument against naturalism. Disputatio Philosophica, 1(1), 50–69.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schunke, M. (2009). Apophatic abuse. Philosophy Today, 53, 164–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smart, J. J. C. (1959). Sensations and brain processes. Philosophical Review, 68, 141–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tengelyi, L. (2012). New phenomenology in France. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 50(2), 295–303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J. (2004). Science discredits religion. In M. Peterson & R. VanArragon (Eds.), Contemporary debates in the philosophy of religion. Maldon: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yoshimi, J. (2015). The metaphysical neutrality of Husserlian phenomenology. Husserl Studies, 31(1), 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (1999). Self-awareness and alterity: A phenomenological investigation. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Matthew Burch.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Burch, M. Religion and scientism: a shared cognitive conundrum. Int J Philos Relig 80, 225–241 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-016-9571-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-016-9571-4

Keywords

Navigation