Skip to main content
Log in

Truth and Consciousness

  • Theoretical/Philosophical Paper
  • Published:
Human Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Many work on flushing out what our consciousness means in cognitive and phenomenological terms, but no one has yet connected the dots on how consciousness and truth intersect, much less how our phenomenal consciousness can form the ground for most of our models of truth. Here, I connect those dots and argue that the basic structure of our phenomenal consciousness grounds the nature of truth as concordance, to harmonize in agreement, and that most extant theories on truth are well explained in that grounding. Said another way, the unifying and bifurcating intentional structure of phenomenal consciousness is the non-epistemic ground of truth, such that most theories of truth can be explained as particular expressions of concordance based upon the differing aspects of that ground.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I am grateful to my anonymous reviewers for their time and valuable input on an earlier version of this manuscript.

  2. While I focus on human consciousness here, this does not mean that other conscious creatures are necessarily excluded. As far as we know, humans are the only conscious creatures to construct theories of truth, and so it makes sense to tailor the analysis to humans. But for the most part, the analysis of consciousness here would apply to other conscious creatures with the exception of reflective consciousness and self-consciousness, which may or may not be present in other species.

  3. I take the terms “pre-reflective” and “reflective” consciousness from Sartre (1960, 1992).

  4. The sense of the givenness of experience here does not conflict with Sellars’ (1997) critique of givenness. Sellars’ main point concerns epistemological accounts that grant certain immediacies in experience (e.g., sensing) as non-inferential knowledge by which to ground further knowledge and justifications. Sellars finds these accounts flawed, and I agree, but his interest lies in epistemology and normativity in relation to experience and the “space of reason”. The account of the givenness of experience here is not epistemological; it is merely descriptive. Sellars even appears to be quite content with descriptive accounts of experience (1997: 13).

  5. I use “representationalist” in the traditional manner of creating conceptual pictures or models in the mind of the experiencing person. More recently, representationalism has a more varied use, such as even allowing for non-conceptual representational content (e.g., Tye 1995; Crane 2003). Discussing how these more recent forms of representationalism match or conflict with the account of phenomenal consciousness I sketch here is beyond the scope of this paper, so I leave them be.

  6. Heidegger himself eschews talk of consciousness, for the most part, because he is trying to talk instead about the existence of “Da-sein”. He is not supplanting the term “consciousness” with a mere replacement of “Da-sein” (1998a: 283); rather, it is the phenomenon of Da-sein and its openness to beings that makes consciousness possible. “All consciousness presupposes existence, thought as ecstatic, as the essentia of the human being—essentia meaning that as which the being essentially prevails insofar as he is human. But consciousness does not itself create the openness of beings, nor is it consciousness that makes it possible for the human being to stand open for beings” (1998a: 284). If one accepts Heidegger’s point here, it may seem that talk of consciousness is overrated or even wrong, but Heidegger is more concerned with traditional phenomenology’s focus on intentionality than with the holistic aspect of consciousness I am emphasizing at the moment. He writes, “[w]hither and whence and in what free dimension could the intentionality of consciousness move, if in-standing were not the essence of the human being in the first instance?” (1998a: 284f.) Thus, while Heidegger is not smitten with talk about consciousness, it is fair to link this account of the unity of consciousness with Heidegger’s account of the there-ness of being; they amount to the same thing. They are both founded on the pre-reflective, holistic givenness of human existence. Nonetheless, I thereby avoid saddling Heidegger’s concept of Da-sein as another expression of intentional consciousness.

  7. Even if one directs one’s awareness to oneself such that one attempts to be present to oneself in a positional manner, this is still awareness of an other. One is aware of an objectification of oneself. This is why Sartre says that presence to oneself always implies a duality (1992: 124).

  8. It is worth noting that Michel Henry disagrees with traditional phenomenology’s insistence on intentionality in a manner akin to Heidegger. Rather than adhere to a phenomenology that only sees transcendence (an orientation towards the other), Henry argues that subjectivity should first be recognized as absolute and immanent, being fully self-sufficient as non-intentional, and hence, non-relational (1975, 2008). The transcendence of subjectivity is only made possible based upon the more originary “radical immanence” of subjectivity (2008: 81). There is no need to assess his claim though. Whether Henry is right that subjectivity sits in primordial, radical immanence, he acknowledges the irreducible facet of intentionality. “Certainly, subjectivity is always a life in the presence of a transcendent being” (1975: 187). So, while Henry argues that the “monistic” approach of traditional phenomenology must be supplanted by a more “dualistic” one to recognize both the immanence and transcendence of subjectivity, that does not discount the indispensability of intentionality in consciousness. Henry weakens the importance given to intentionality, but even if intentionality is derivative, it is still a vital aspect in the phenomenon of consciousness.

  9. Traditional representationalist theories of consciousness commit the error of only and ever esteeming the disunity in consciousness to the exclusion of any unity, and theorists like Taylor make the opposite error of emphasizing the unity of consciousness over any meaningful measure of disunity. Taylor is so insistent against mediational views that he formulates his “contact” theory in a way that situates humans in the embeddedness and unity of experience without adequate consideration for why such mediational views arise in the first place. In section “Some Implications,” I explain how this causes a problem for Taylor’s understanding of truth.

  10. I leave unexplained that concordance is sought after, but all theories of truth demonstrate this aspiration, and due to the structure of phenomenal consciousness, it is not surprising how these theories of truth become formulated.

  11. It may also be possible to list Kierkegaard’s explanation of “truth is subjectivity” (1992) here as a retention theory, but one could say that Heidegger “ontologizes” Kierkegaard’s metaethical account of subjectivity and that this offers a clearer example.

  12. As a sidenote, it is interesting that what James does differently than correspondence and coherence theories is that he also tries to answer why we want concordance—truth is useful for living. That theories of truth involve harmonizing disparate elements is undeniable, but it is a different matter to ask whether we should really care about concordance or not. This is one of Nietzsche’s questions as he was perplexed by the philosophers’ “will to truth” and asks “why not untruth instead” (2002: 5)? Perhaps the drive for truth as concordance is more of an issue for cultural studies than just philosophy. But as I mention above, I leave the drive for truth as concordance unexplained.

  13. Heidegger’s developed, though earlier, view of truth here is paradigmatic of a retention theory of truth. Yet, it is interesting to note that in his later years, Heidegger came to walk back this notion of truth, though not the notion of unconcealment. In “The End of Philosophy and the Task of Thinking,” he remarks, “[i]n any case, one thing becomes clear: to raise the question of alētheia, of unconcealment as such, is not the same as raising the question of truth. For this reason, it was inadequate and misleading to call alētheia in the sense of opening, truth” (1977: 389).

  14. This, of course, does not mean that particular theories of truth within the categories are unable to jockey for greater warrant.

References

  • Albahari, M. (2006). Analytical Buddhism: The two-tiered illusion of the self. New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. L. (1950). Truth, part 1. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary, Vol. 24, 111–128.

  • Barnes, H. (1992). Sartre’s ontology: The revealing and making of being. In C. Howells (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Sartre (pp. 13–38). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bermúdez, J. (1998). The paradox of self-consciousness. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blanshard, B. (1941). The nature of thought. New York, NY: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (1998). Two kinds of consciousness. In N. Block, O. Flanagan, G. Guzeldere, & G. Cambridge (Eds.), The nature of consciousness: Philosophical debates, 2nd part (pp. 427–433). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (2003). The intentional structure of consciousness. In Q. Smith & A. Jokic (Eds.), Consciousness: New philosophical perspectives (pp. 33–56). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1996). The folly of trying to define truth. Journal of Philosophy, 93(6), 263–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (2005). Truth and predication. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston, MA: Little, Brown and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dowden, B., & Norman, S. (2015). Truth. Internet encyclopedia of philosophy, http://www.iep.utm.edu/truth/. Accessed June 17, 2015.

  • Dreyfus, H. (2007). Response to McDowell. Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy, 50(4), 371–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1978). Truth and other enigmas. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edey, M. (1997). Subject and object. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 4(5–6), 526–531.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and time (J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson, Trans.). San Francisco, CA: Harper San Francisco.

  • Heidegger, M. (1977). The end of philosophy and the task of thinking. In D. F. Krell (Ed.), Basic writings (J. Stambaugh, Trans.) (pp. 373–392). San Francisco, CA: Harper San Francisco.

  • Heidegger, M. (1998a). Introduction to “What is metaphysics?”. In W. McNeill (Ed.), Pathmarks (J. Sallis, Trans.) (pp. 277–290). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (1998b). On the essence of truth. In W. McNeill (Ed.), Pathmarks (J. Sallis, Trans.) (pp. 136–154). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

  • Henry, M. (1975). Philosophy and phenomenology of the body (G. Etzkorn, Trans.). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Henry, M. (2008). Material phenomenology (S. Davidson, Trans.). New York, NY: Fordham University Press.

  • James, W. (1997). The meaning of truth. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kierkegaard, S. (1992). Concluding unscientific postscript to philosophical fragments (H. Hong & E. Hong, Trans.) (Vol. 1). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

  • Kriegel, U. (2003). Consciousness as intransitive self-consciousness: Two views and an argument. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 33(1), 103–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Legrand, D. (2007). Pre-reflective self-as-subject from experiential and empirical perspectives. Consciousness and Cognition, 16, 583–599.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962). Phenomenology of perception (C. Smith, Trans.). New York, NY: Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd.

  • Nietzsche, F. (2002). Beyond good and evil (J. Norman, Trans.). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1986). Philosophy of logic (2nd ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, F. (1927). Facts and propositions. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Suppl., 7(1), 153–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1964). The problems of philosophy, 10th part. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J.-P. (1960). The transcendence of the ego: An existentialist theory of consciousness (R. Williams & R. Kirkpatrick, Trans.). New York, NY: The Noonday Press.

  • Sartre, J.-P. (1992). Being and nothingness: A phenomenological essay on ontology (H. Barnes, Trans.). New York, NY: Washington Square Press.

  • Sellars, W. (1997). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (2005). Real intentionality V. 2: Why intentionality entails consciousness? Synthesis Philosophica, 20(2), 279–297.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tarski, A. (1944). The semantic conception of truth: And the foundations of semantics. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 4(3), 341–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (2013). Retrieving realism. In J. Schear (Ed.), Mind, reason, and being-in-the-world: The McDowell–Dreyfus debate (pp. 61–90). New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (1995). Ten problems of consciousness: A representational theory of the phenomenal mind. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2005a). Intentionality and experience. Synthesis Philosophica, 20(2), 299–318.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2005b). Subjectivity and selfhood: Investigating the first-person perspective. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2009). Is the self a social construct? Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy, 52(6), 551–573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2011). Unity of consciousness and the problem of self. In S. Gallagher (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of the self (pp. 316–335). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2013). Mindedness, mindlessness, and first-person authority. In J. Schear (Ed.), Mind, reason, and being-in-the-world: The McDowell–Dreyfus debate (pp. 320–343). New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Chris Calvert-Minor.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Calvert-Minor, C. Truth and Consciousness. Hum Stud 40, 663–679 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-017-9444-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-017-9444-6

Keywords

Navigation