Skip to main content
Log in

Toward a constructivist epistemology of thought experiments in science

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper presents a critical analysis of Tamar Szabó Gendler’s view of thought experiments, with the aim of developing further a constructivist epistemology of thought experiments in science. While the execution of a thought experiment cannot be reduced to standard forms of inductive and deductive inference, in the process of working though a thought experiment, a logical argument does emerge and take shape. Taking Gendler’s work as a point of departure, I argue that performing a thought experiment involves a process of self-interrogation, in which we are compelled to reflect on our pre-existing knowledge of the world. In doing so, we are forced to make judgments about what assumptions we see as relevant and how they apply to an imaginary scenario. This brings to light the extent to which certain forms of skill, beyond the ability to make valid logical inferences, are necessary to execute a thought experiment well.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This kind of logical reconstruction has been carried out on many TEs including Galileo famous falling bodies TE (Schrenk 2004).

  2. Gendler distinguishes between two ways in which we may take the logical reconstruction of a TE as equivalent to the execution of a TE: (a) the dispensability thesis, according to which “[a]ny good TE can be replaced without loss of demonstrative force, by a non-TE argument”, and (ii) the derivativity thesis, according to which “[t]he justificatory force of any good TE can only be explained by the fact that it can be replaced, without loss of demonstrative force, by a non-TE argument. Needless to say, Gendler rejects both theses (1998, p. 401).

  3. These conditions in brackets are often neglected in modern presentations of the TE, but we can skip over them for the sake of the reconstruction.

  4. Miklós Rédei has argued that this “assumption is indeed not self-evident and is in need of empirical testing” (Rédei 2003, p. 238).

  5. For the sake of simplicity we can assume that (i) the units of speed and weight are the same, and (ii) the natural speed of a unified body is the mean of the natural speeds of each of the two bodies.

  6. Gendler’s position is in many respects reminiscent of one we find in Lakatos’ well known work, Proofs and Refutations, in which the protagonists of the dialogue ponder the status of ‘hidden assumptions’ and ‘unconsciously held lemmas’ in the analysis of a mathematical proof (Lakatos 1976).

  7. Here we can compare the intuitions of Tycho Brahe and Galileo on what would occur aboard a moving ship. In his Episteolarum astronomicarum Tycho claimed: “Indeed certain men think that a missile hurled upwards from a ship, if this would occur inside of the vessel, would fall to the same place if the ship is moving as if it remained motionless. They offer these theories without any reflexion for it actually happens quite differently than they suppose. In fact the swifter the ships advance, the more differences will be discovered. The same thing results from the (supposed) revolution of the earth” (Overmann 1975, p. 14). We may contrast this with Galileo’s account in the Dialogue on the Two Chief World Systems, which considers almost exactly the same scenario, although arrives at an entirely different conclusion. “So long as the motion is uniform and not fluctuating this way and that”, Galileo maintains that objects moving around in the cabin of a ship would undergo no noticeable effects in their motions: “You will discover not the least change in all the effects named, nor could you tell from any of them whether the ship was moving or standing still... the ship’s motion is common to all the things contained in it, and to the air also. That is why I said you should be below decks; for if this took place above in the open air, which would not follow the course of the ship, more or less noticeable differences would be seen in some of the effects noted” (Galilei [1632] 1953, pp. 186–187).

  8. Alisa Bokulich, draws the conclusion that “(for TEs in physics) the very description of a TE requires a great many abstract symbolic expressions whose meaning and correspondence with the facts are indicated by theories” (Bokulich 2001, pp. 300–301).

  9. For Gendler, “How one goes about individuating TEs is a question on which I will allow myself to remain neutral: Is Einstein’s clock-in-the-box TE (which assumes classical spacetime) the same TE as Bohr’s (which assumes relativistic spacetime)? ... Is the TE that I perform when I read Galileo’s text the same as the TE Galileo performed when he wrote it? Nothing of what I will go on to say will turn on how these questions—to which it seems difficult to find principled answers—are dealt with” (Gendler 2004, p. 1161 fn 9).

  10. Here we might think of the different elaborations of the EPR TE by Einstein and Bohr, or the versions of Maxwell’s demon presented by Smoluchowski, Szillard and Brillouin, or Mach’s critical analysis of Newton’s spinning bucket TE.

  11. One might well question whether Bohr’s assumption (of employing a relativistic energy-time relation) was relevant, given that the TE was intended to show the incompleteness of non-relativistic quantum mechanics. It is not at all obvious why certain relativistic assumptions should be relevant, or even necessary, in this context. However, my point here is not to argue for the reevaluation of Bohr’s triumph over Einstein. I merely wish to point out that judgments about the relevance of certain assumptions are indispensable for TEs.

  12. In the years from 1911 to 1915, a number of leading physicists expressed some disagreement about precisely which aspect of relativity theory was relevant for the resolution of the paradox. While it was generally agreed that only one of the twins experienced a change in inertial reference frame, such noted physicists as Max von Laue, Max Born and Albert Einstein offered different explanations of the phenomenon (see Miller 1981, p. 261; Jammer 2006, p. 165).

  13. It is interesting to note that Humphreys argues that TEs are not well-defined problems. But this seems too restrictive, and would exclude many cases commonly considered to be good examples of TE, such as the ladder-barn paradox. It seems rather that knowing whether or not a TE is ‘well-defined’ in the sense of containing all the necessary and sufficient conditions for its resolution is precisely one of the skills of a good thought experimenter (Humphreys 1993).

  14. As de Regt and Dieks make clear: “It is possible to have technical proficiency in manipulating formulas and symbols in the theory, without possessing understanding” and conversely “it is possible to understand how a theory works without being able to do precise calculations with it” (De Regt and Dieks 2005, p. 151).

References

  • Arthur, R. (1999). On thought experiments as a priori science. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 13, 215–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Atkinson, D. (2003). Experiments and thought experiments in natural science. In M. C. Galavotti (Ed.), Observation and experiment in the natural and social sciences (pp. 209–225). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atkinson, D., & Pejnenburg, J. (2004). Galileo and prior philosophy. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 35, 115–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, M. (1998). An epistemological role for thought experiments. In N. Shanks (Ed.), Idealization IX: Idealization in contemporary phsyics (pp. 19–33). Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, M. (1999). Why thought experiments are not arguments. Philosophy of Science, 66, 534–541.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bokulich, A. (2001). Rethinking thought experiments. Perspectives on Science, 9, 285–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, H. I. (2000). Judgment, role in science. In W. H. Newton-Smith (Ed.), A companion to the philosophy of science (pp. 194–202). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. R. (1986). Thought experiments since the scientific revolution. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 1(1), 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. R. (1991). Laboratory of the mind: Thought experiments in the natural sciences. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Regt, H. (2009). The epistemic value of understanding. Philosophy of Science, 76, 585–597.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Regt, H., & Dieks, D. (2005). A contextual approach to scientific understanding. Synthese, 144, 137–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ehrenberg, W. (1967). Maxwell’s Demon, Reprinted from Scientific American. San Fransisco: W. H. Freeman and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galilei, G. ([1632] 1953). Dialogue on the great world systems (G. de Santillana, Trans.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Galilei, G. ([1638] 1968). Dialogues concerning two new sciences (H. Crew & A. d. Salvio, Trans.). Evanston, Chicago: Northwestern University Press.

  • Gendler, T. S. (1998). Galileo and the indispensability of scientific thought experiments. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 49, 397–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gendler, T. S. (2000). Thought experiment: On the powers and limits of imaginary cases. New York: Garland Press (now Routledge).

    Google Scholar 

  • Gendler, T. S. (2002). Thought experiment. Encyclopedia of cognitive science. New York; London: Nature; Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gendler, T. S. (2004). Thought experiments rethought—and reperceived. Philosophy of Science, 71, 1152–1164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gooding, D. (1993). What is experimental about thought experiments? PSA 1992, 2, 280–290.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gooding, D. (1994). Imaginary science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 45, 1029–1045.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys, P. (1993). Seven theses on thought experiments. In J. Earman (Ed.), Philosophical problems of the internal and external world: Essays on the philosophy of Adolf Grünbaum (pp. 205–227). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Irvine, A. D. (1991). Thought experiments in scientific reasoning. In T. Horowitz & G. Massey (Eds.), Thought experiments in science and philosophy (pp. 149–165). Savage, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jammer, M. (2006). Concepts of simultaneity: From antiquity to Einstein and beyond. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koyré, A. (1968). Galileo’s Treatise De motu gravium: The tse and abuse of imaginary experiment metaphysics and measurement: Essays in the scientific revolution (pp. 44–88). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. (1977). A function for thought experiments. The essential tension (pp. 240–265). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1976). Proofs and refutations: The logic of mathematical discovery. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mach, E. ([1883] 1960). The science of mechanics (J. McCormack, Trans.). LaSalle, IL: Open Court.

  • Matthews, M. (2005). Idealisation and Galileo’s penulum discoveries: Historical, philosophical and pedagogical considerations. In M. R. Matthews, C. F. Gauld, & A. Stinner (Eds.), The pendulum: Scientific, historical and educational perspectives (pp. 209–235). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, A. I. (1981). Albert Einstein’s special theory of relativity. Emergence (1905) and early interpretation (1905–1911). Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J. (1996). Are thought experiments just what you always thought? Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 26(3), 333–366.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J. (2004a). On thought experiments: Is there more to the argument? Proceedings of the 2002 biennial meeting of the philosophy of science association. Philosophy of Science, 71, 1139–1151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J. (2004b). Why thought experiments do not transcend empiricism contemporary debates in the philosophy of science (pp. 44–66). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Overmann, R. J. (1975). Theories of gravity in the seventeenth century. Unpublished PhD, Indiana University, Indiana.

  • Palmerino, C. R. (2011). Galileo’s use of medieval thought experiments. In K. Lerodiakonou & S. Roux (Eds.), Thought experiments in methodological and historical contexts (pp. 101–125). Leiden: Brill.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Palmieri, P. (2005). Spuntar lo scoglio più duro’: Did Galileo ever think the most beautiful thought experiment in the history of science? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 36(2), 223–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rédei, M. (2003). Thinking about thought experiments in physics: Comment on ’experiments and thought experiments in natural science’. In M. C. Galavotti (Ed.), Observation and experiment in the natural and social sciences (pp. 237–241). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schrenk, M. A. (2004). Galileo vs. Aristotle on free falling bodies. Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy, 7(1), 1–11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorensen, R. (1992). Thought experiments. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kristian Camilleri.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Camilleri, K. Toward a constructivist epistemology of thought experiments in science. Synthese 191, 1697–1716 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-013-0358-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-013-0358-1

Keywords

Navigation