Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-5nwft Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-26T13:11:39.456Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

OCCUPATIONAL CHOICE AND THE EGALITARIAN ETHOS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 April 2013

Paula Casal*
Affiliation:
ICREA–Universitat Pompeu Fabra, Spainpaula.casal@upf.edu

Abstract

G. A. Cohen proposes to eradicate inequality without loss of efficiency or freedom by relying on an egalitarian ethos requiring us to undertake socially useful occupations we would rather not take, and work hard at them, without requesting differential incentive payments. Since the ethos is not legally enforced, Cohen denies it threatens our occupational freedom. Drawing on the work of Joseph Raz, the paper argues that Cohen's proposal threatens our occupational autonomy even if it leaves our legal freedom intact. It also proposes a revised ethos which respects occupational autonomy.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2013

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Casal, P. 2007. Why sufficiency is not enough. Ethics 117: 296326.Google Scholar
Cohen, G. A. 2000. If You're an Egalitarian, How Come You Are So Rich? Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Cohen, G. A. 2008. Rescuing Justice and Equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Cohen, G. A. 2011. On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice and Other Essays in Political Philosophy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Cohen, J. 2000. Taking people as they are? Philosophy and Public Affairs 30: 363386.Google Scholar
Elster, J. 1986. The market and the forum. In Foundations of Social Choice Theory, ed. Elster, J. and Hyland, A., 103132. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Estlund, D. 1998. Liberalism, equality, and fraternity in Cohen's critique of Rawls. Journal of Political Philosophy 6: 99122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jencks, C., Perman, L. and Rainwater, L.. 1988. What is a good job? A new measure of labor-market success. American Journal of Sociology 93: 13221357.Google Scholar
Mill, J. S. 1991. On Liberty and Other Essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Otsuka, M. 2008. Freedom of occupational choice. Ratio 21: 440453.Google Scholar
Pogge, T. 2000. On the site of distributive justice. Philosophy and Public Affairs 29: 137169.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1986. The Morality of Freedom. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1993. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1999. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 2001. Justice as Fairness: A Restatement. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Robinson, J. C. 1988. Hazardous occupations within the job hierarchy. Industrial Relations 27: 241250.Google Scholar
Scheffler, S. 1982. The Rejection of Consequentialism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Shiffrin, S. 1991. Moral autonomy and agent-centred options. Analysis 51: 244254.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shiffrin, S. 2010. Incentives, motives, and talents. Philosophy and Public Affairs 38: 111142.Google Scholar
Van Parijs, P. 1995. Real Freedom for All. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Wilkinson, T. M. 2000. Freedom, Efficiency and Equality. London: Palgrave.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, A. 1998. Incentives, inequality, and publicity. Philosophy and Public Affairs 27: 225247.Google Scholar
Williams, A. 2006. Basic income and the value of occupational choice. Basic Income Studies 1: 15.Google Scholar