Skip to main content
Log in

Species are, at the same time, kinds and individuals: a causal argument based on an empirical approach to species identity

  • S.I. : Natural Kinds: Language, Science, and Metaphysics
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

After having reconstructed a minimal biological characterisation of species, we endorse an “empirical approach” based on the idea that it is the peculiar evolutionary history of the species at issue—its peculiar origination process, its peculiar metapopulation structure and the peculiar mixture and strength of homeostatic processes vis à vis heterostatic ones—that determines species’ identity at a time and through time. We then explore the consequences of the acceptance of the empirical approach in settling the individuals versus kinds dispute. In particular, while conceptual arguments have been proposed to show that species can be equally treated as individuals and kinds because mereology’s and set-theory’s languages are inter-translatable, we advance instead a causal argument to sustain the claim that each species is both a kind (i.e., a class whose members share some properties included in a cluster) and an individual (i.e., a whole made of parts).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Even though the general species concept is quite agreed upon when species of sexually reproducing organisms are at stake, its applicability to asexual species has been questioned (see for instance Doolittle and Zhaxybayeva 2009; and see Samadi and Barberousse 2006 for a possible way to overcome this problem).

  2. It is important to emphasise that the concepts of gene pool and gene-phene pool could be defined by taking into consideration the extant organisms of the species—like Mayr does—or by taking into account all its past, present and future members. This latter characterization clearly shows the indefiniteness of the concepts of gene pool and gene-phene pool. Furthermore, it is also important to note that, unlike Mayr, we prefer to use the term “genetic property” in order to define the concept of gene-phene pool; the reason is that this latter term is more general and neutral as it might also refer to sequences of DNA with not yet known functional role in development.

  3. de Queiroz (1995) admits the same possibility, on the basis of mainly semantic considerations.

  4. The historical roots of the thesis are much older, going back at least to Buffon (Gayon 1996).

  5. An alternative account taking Boyd’s HPC view as a departure point has been recently offered by Slater (2013, 2015), who suggests replacing the notion of homeostatic property clusters with the notion of stable property clusters (SPC).

  6. Whether all the extant (or even past and future) organisms of a species actually share a set of intrinsic properties remains an open empirical issue that cannot be settled philosophically (Devitt 2008; Barker 2010).

  7. We characterise a cluster in terms of intrinsic and relational properties. Wilson et al. 2007 argue that a cluster consists of both kinds of properties for the reason that “… the features that promote cohesion within a species [i.e., that keep the cluster homeostatic] are typically relational properties of conspecifics….” Our argument does not depend on privileging relational over intrinsic properties.

  8. It is interesting to note that no definite list of homeostatic mechanisms has been provided. In our opinion, the reason for this omission is simply that homeostasis is species-dependent: the homeostatic mechanisms at play depend on the peculiar speciation process and metapopulation structure and dynamics and thus may vary over time and/or space.

  9. We use the terms “class” and “set” as synonymous and as intensionally defined.

  10. This is called, by Kitcher (1984), “The fallacy of incomplete translation”. Kitcher reconstructs the argument in favour of SAI as follows: Sets cannot evolve; species evolve; hence species are not sets. In the argument, “species evolve” is, according to Kitcher, left untranslated. To complete the translation, we need to consider that a species, set-theoretically conceived, is a union of subsets—or stages. A stage is the set of organisms belonging to the species which are alive at a given time. Accordingly, the complete translation of “species evolve” would be something like: the frequency of the distribution of (genetic or genetic plus phenotypic) properties at one stage will differ from the frequency of the distribution of (genetic or genetic plus phenotypic) properties at a later stage. Kitcher argues that, proceeding in this way, claims about the evolutionary behaviour of species—such as for instance speciation or extinction—may be easily expressed in set-theoretical terms.

  11. It may be objected that the kind of cohesiveness Elredge and Gould are talking about here is response cohesion. However, their reference to a homeostatic system implies the existence of causal interactions among the members of the population beyond gene flow.

  12. We thank a reviewer for raising this objection.

References

  • Assis, L. C. S., & Brigandt, I. (2009). Homology: Homeostatic property cluster kinds in systematics and evolution. Evolutionary Biology, 36, 248–255.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barker, M. J. (2010). Specious intrinsicalism. Philosophy of Science, 77, 73–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barker, M. J., & Wilson, R. A. (2010). Cohesion, gene flow, and the nature of species. The Journal of Philosophy, 107(2), 61–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1999). Homeostasis, species, and higher taxa. In R. A. Wilson (Ed.), Species. New interdisciplinary essays (pp. 141–186). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, I. (2009). Natural kinds in evolution and systematics: Metaphysical and epistemological considerations. Acta Biotheoretica, 57, 77–97. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10441-008-9056-7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B. O. (2004). Species as individuals. Biology and Philosophy, 19, 223–242.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burggren, W. (2016). Epigenetic inheritance and its role in evolutionary biology: Re-evaluation and new perspectives. Biology, 5, 24. https://doi.org/10.3390/biology5020024.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colless, D. H. (2006). Taxa, individuals, clusters and a few other things. Biology and Philosophy, 21, 353–367.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Queiroz, K. (1995). The definitions of species and clade names: A reply to Ghiselin. Biology and Philosophy, 10, 223–228.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Queiroz, K. (1999). The general lineage concept of species and the defining properties of the species category. In R. A. Wilson (Ed.), Species: New interdisciplinary essays (pp. 49–89). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Queiroz, K. (2005a). Ernst Mayr and the modern concept of species. PNAS, 3(102), 6600–6607.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Queiroz, K. (2005b). Different species problems and their resolution. BioEssays, 27, 1263–1269.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Queiroz, K. (2007). Species concepts and species delimitation. Systematic, 56(6), 879–886.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2008). Resurrecting biological essentialism. Philosophy of Science, 75, 344–382.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dobzhansky, T. (1950). Mendelian populations and their evolution. The American Naturalist, 84(819), 401–418.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doolittle, W. F., & Zhaxybayeva, O. (2009). On the origin of prokaryotic species. Genome Research, 19, 744–756.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (1995). The disorder of things: Metaphysical foundations of the disunity of science. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eldredge, N., & Gould, S. J. (1972). Punctuated equilibria: An alternative to phyletic gradualism. In T. J. M. Schopf (Ed.), Models in paleobiology (pp. 82–115). San Francisco: Freeman Cooper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky, M. (2010). Microbiology and the species problem. Biology and Philosophy, 25, 553–568. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-010-9211-9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky, M. (2014). Species, historicity and path dependency. Philosophy of Science, 81(5), 714–726.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky, M., & Matthen, M. (2005). Taxonomy, polymorphism, and history: An introduction to population structure theory. Philosophy of Science, 72(1), 1–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gayon, J. (1996). The individuality of the species: A Darwinian theory? From Buffon to Ghiselin, and back to Darwin. Biology and Philosophy, 11, 193–204.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghiselin, M. T. (1974). A radical solution to the species problem. Systematic Zoology, 23, 436–444.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (2002). The structure of evolutionary theory. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. (1976). Are species really individuals? Systematic Zoology, 25(2), 174–191.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. (1978). A matter of individuality. Philosophy of Science, 45(3), 335–360.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. L. (1992). Individual. In E. Fox Keller & E. A. Lloyd (Eds.), Keywords in evolutionary biology (pp. 181–187). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1984). Species. Philosophy of Science, 51, 308–333.

    Google Scholar 

  • LaPorte, J. (2004). Natural kinds and conceptual change. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • LaPorte, J. (2007). In defense of species. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 38(1), 255–269.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levins, R. (1970). Extinction. Lectures on Mathematics in the Life Sciences, 2, 75–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mallet, J. (1995). A species definition for the modern synthesis. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 10, 294–299.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1963). Animal species and evolution. London: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1970). Populations, species, and evolution. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1988). The why and how of species. Biology and Philosophy, 3, 431–441.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (2001). What evolution is. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Okasha, S. (2002). Darwinian metaphysics. Species and the question of essentialism. Synthese, 131, 191–213.

    Google Scholar 

  • Queller, D. C., & Strassman, J. W. (2009). Beyond society: The evolution of organismality. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 2009(364), 3143–3155.

    Google Scholar 

  • Relethford, J. H. (2008). Genetic evidence and the modern human origins debate. Heredity, 100, 555–563.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reydon, T. (2009). Species and kinds: A critique of Rieppel’s “one of a kind” account of species. Cladistics, 25, 660–667.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richards, R. (2010). The species problem. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ridley, M. (2004). Evolution. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel, O. (2007). Species: Kinds of individuals or individuals of a kind. Cladistics, 23, 373–384.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel, O. (2009). Species as a process. Acta Biotheoretica, 57, 33–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samadi, S., & Barberousse, A. (2006). The tree, the network, and the species. Biological Journal of the Linnean Society, 89, 509–521.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slater, M. H. (2013). Are species real? An essay on the metaphysics of species. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slater, M. H. (2015). Natural kindness. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 66(2), 375–411.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stamos, D. (2003). The species problem. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Templeton, A. R. (1989). The meaning of species and speciation: A genetic perspective. In D. Otte & J. A. Endler (Eds.), Speciation and its consequences (pp. 3–27). Sunderland: Sinauer Associates Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tishkoff, S. A., et al. (2007). Convergent adaptation of human lactase persistence in Africa and Europe. Nature Genetics, 39, 31–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varzi, A. (2016). Mereology. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2016 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/mereology/. Accessed April 2018.

  • West-Eberhard, M. J. (2003). Developmental plasticity and evolution. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkins, J. S. (2009). Defining species. A sourcebook from antiquity to today. New York: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, E. O. (1975). Sociobiology: The new synthesis. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A. (1996). Promiscuous realism. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 47, 303–316.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A., Barker, M. J., & Brigandt, I. (2007). When traditional essentialism fails: Biological natural kinds. Philosophical Topics, 35, 189–215.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, S. (1931). Evolution in Mendelian populations. Genetics, 16, 97–159.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We thank Ingo Brigandt, Kevin de Queiroz, Matthew Slater, and Achille Varzi for incisive feedback and suggestions. We also thank the anonymous reviewers for their stimulating feedback, and the audience at the EPILOG seminar (in particular Cristina Amoretti and Marcello Frixione) of the University of Genoa, Italy, where the ideas proposed in this article starting to take shape. We acknowledge the financial support of the Fundação para a Ciência e a Tecnologia (BIODECON R&D Project Grant PTDC/IVC-HFC/1817/2014). Davide Vecchi also acknowledges the financial support of the Fundação para a Ciência e a Tecnologia (Grant No. SFRH/BPD/99879/2014; Grant No. UID/FIL/00678/2019).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Elena Casetta.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Casetta, E., Vecchi, D. Species are, at the same time, kinds and individuals: a causal argument based on an empirical approach to species identity. Synthese 198 (Suppl 12), 3007–3025 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02199-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02199-5

Keywords

Navigation