Skip to main content
Log in

Social Cognition: a Normative Approach

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The main aim of this paper is to introduce an approach for understanding social cognition that we call the normative approach to social cognition. Such an approach, which results from a systematization of previous arguments and ideas from authors such as Ryle, Dewey, or Wittgenstein, is an alternative to the classic model (by which we infer others’ mental states via sub-personal mechanisms) and the direct social perception model (by which we directly perceive others’ mental states). In section 2, we evaluate the virtues and flaws of these two models. In section 3, we introduce the normative approach, according to which human, socio-cognitive competences rely on a myriad of social norms and routines that mediate our social interactions in such a way that we can make sense of each other without taking into consideration their mental states. In sections 4 and 5, we find some common premises shared by the two prior models and offer some arguments against them. In section 6, we advance some possible arguments against our approach and offer some responses against them.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Supporters of both the CM and the DSPM might reply that there is no way to track social norms unless you track first the psychological attitudes or states of individuals. Nevertheless, empirical evidence offered throughout this paper (recall Uttich & Lombrozo 2010, for example) goes against this view. Furthermore, if such claim is raised by supporters of CM and DSPM, then they acquire the responsibility to provide the suitable empirical evidence that supports that claim.

  2. In spite of this, DSPM does not seem to account for the fact that social practices influence not only the interpreter’s individual capacities but also the interpretee’s action (see section 4).

  3. The idea that humans evolved in a context where hunting megafauna was rewarded, and this promoted cooperative hunting strategies is not new. See Sterelny (2012) and Zawidzki (2013).

References

  • Andrews, K. (2009). Understanding norms without a theory of mind. Inquiry, 52(5), 433–448.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andrews, K. (2012). Do apes read minds? Toward a new folk psychology. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ayala-López, S. (2018). A structural explanation of injustice in conversations: it’s about norms. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 99(4), 726–748.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen, S. (1995). Mindblindness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Berkeley, G. (1710/1970). A treatise concerning the principles of human knowledge. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohl, V., & van den Bos, W. (2012). Toward an integrative account of social cognition: marrying theory of mind and interactionism to study the interplay of type 1 and type 2 processes. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 6, 274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borg, E. (2007). If mirror neurons are the answer, what was the question? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 14, 5–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butterfill, S. A. & Pacherie, E. (Forthcoming). Towards a blueprint for a social animal. In A. Fiebich (ed.). Minimal Cooperation and Shared Agency. Springer.

  • Carruthers, P. (2006). The architecture of the mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2017). Mindreading in adults: evaluating two-systems views. Synthese, 192, 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Currie, G., & Sterelny, K. (2000). How to think of the modularity of mind-reading. The Philosophical Quarterly, 50, 145–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1991). Three varieties of knowledge. In A. P. Griffiths (Ed.), Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement (pp. 153–166). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Jaegher, H. (2009). Social understanding through direct perception? Yes, by interacting. Consciousness & Cognition, 18(2), 535–542.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Jaegher, H., & Di Paolo, E. (2007). Participatory sense-making: an enactive approach to social cognition. Phenomenology & the Cognitive Sciences, 6, 485–507.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1896). Te refex arc concept in psychology. Psychological Review, 3(4), 357.

  • Dewey, J. (1922/2007). Human nature and conduct. An introduction to social psychology. New York: Cosimo Classics.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, M., & Shah, N. (2012). Mental agency and metaethics. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics vol. 7 (pp. 80–109). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fernández Castro, V. (2017a). Regulation, normativity and folk psychology. An International Review of Philosophy. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-017-9511-7.

  • Fernández Castro, V. (2017b). The expressive function of folk psychology. Journal of Philosophy, 18(1), 36–46. https://doi.org/10.4013/fsu.2017.181.05.

  • Fernández Castro, V. (2019). Justification, conversation and folk psychology. An International Journal of Theory, History and Foundations of Science, 34(1), 75–91. https://doi.org/10.1387/theoria.18022.

  • Fuchs, T., & De Jaegher, H. (2009). Enactive intersubjectivity: participatory sense-making and mutual incorporation. Phenomenology & the Cognitive Sciences, 8, 465–486.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2001). The practice of mind: theory, simulation or primary interaction? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8, 83–108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2008a). Direct perception in the intersubjective context. Consciousness & Cognition, 17, 535–543.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2008b). Inference or interaction: social cognition without precursors. Philosophical Explorations, 11(3), 163–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Zahavi, D. (2008). The phenomenological mind. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, A. (2012). Meaning and normativity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (1989). Interpretation psychologized. Mind & Language, 4, 161–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (2006). Simulating minds. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (2012). Theory of mind. In E. Margolis, R. Samuels, & S. P. Stich (Eds.), Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Cognitive Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A., & Sripada, C. S. (2005). Simulationist models of face-based emotion recognition. Cognition, 94, 193–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., & Meltzoff, A. (1997). Words, thoughts, and theories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., & Wellman, H. M. (1994). The theory theory. In L. A. Hirschfield & S. A. Gellman (Eds.), Mapping the mind: Domain specificity in culture and cognition (pp. 257–293). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, R. M. (1996). “Radical” simulationism. In P. Carruthers & P. K. Smith (Eds.), Theories of theories of mind (pp. 11–21). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gray, R. D. (2001). Selfish genes of developmental systems? In R. Singh, K. Krimbas, J. Paul, & J. Beatty (Eds.), Thinking about evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, P. (1974). Method in philosophical psychology (from the banal to the bizarre). Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 68, 23–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gutchess, A. H., Welsh, R. C., Boduroĝlu, A., & Park, D. C. (2006). Cultural differences in neural function associated with object processing. Cognitive, Affective, & Behavioral Neuroscience, 6(2), 102–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, S. (2016). What is a (social) structural explanation? Philosophical Studies, 173(1), 113–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland, J. (2000). Having thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heras-Escribano, M. (2019). The philosophy of affordances. Cham: Palgrave Macmillan.

  • Heras-Escribano, M., & De Pinedo, M. (2016). Are affordances normative?. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 15(4): 565–589.

  • Heal, J. (1998). Co-cognition and off-line simulation: two ways of understanding the simulation approach. Mind & Language, 13, 477–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heath, J. (2015). Methodological individualism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. URL=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/methodological-individualism/.

  • Heyes, C. (2016). Born pupils? Natural pedagogy and cultural pedagogy. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 11(2), 280–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1960/1982). Cartesian meditations. London: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. (2004). The limits of spectatorial folk psychology. Mind & Language, 19, 548–573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D., & Ratcliffe, M. (Eds.). (2007). Folk psychology re-assessed. Dordrecht: Kluwer/Springer Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., & Satne, G. (2015). The natural origins of content. Philosophia, 43(3), 521–536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, P. (2011). The direct-perception model of empathy: a critique. Review of Philosophy & Psychology, 2(3), 519–540.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, K. L., Pollick, F. E., & McKay, L. S. (2010). Social constraints on the visual perception of biological motion. In R. B. Adams, N. Ambady, K. Nakayama, & S. Shimojo (Eds.), The Science of Social Vision. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitayama, S., Park, J., & Cho, Y. H. (2015). Culture and neuroplasticity. In M. J. Gelfand, C. Y. Chiu, & Y.-Y. Hong (Eds.), Advances in culture and psychology (Vol. 5). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korman, J., & Malle, B. (2016). Grasping for traits or reasons? How people grapple with puzzling social behaviors. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 42(11), 1451–1465.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kozlowski, L. T., & Cutting, J. E. (1977). Recognizing the sex of a walker from a dynamic point-light display. Perception & Psychophysics, 21(6), 575–580.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krueger, J., & Overgaard, S. (2012). Seeing subjectivity: Defending a perceptual account of other minds. In S. Miguens & G. Preyer (Eds.), Consciousness and subjectivity (pp. 239–262). Heusenstamm: Ontos Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leudar, I., & Costall, A. (Eds.). (2009). Against theory of mind. Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leudar, I., Costall, A., & Francis, D. (2004). Theory of mind: a critical assessment. Theory and Psychology, 14(5):571–578.

  • Maibom, H. (2007). Social systems. Philosophical Psychology, 20(5), 557–578.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mameli, M. (2001). Mindreading, mindshaping, and evolution. Biology and Philosophy, 16, 597–628.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1996). Mind and world. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (2007). Response to Dreyfus. Inquiry, 50(4), 366–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGeer, V. (2007). The regulative dimension of folk psychology. In D. D. Hutto & M. Ratcliffe (Eds.), Folk psychology re-assessed (pp. 137–156). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McGeer, V. (2015). Mind-making practices: the social infrastructure of self-knowing agency and responsibility. Philosophical Explorations, 18(2), 259–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff, A. N., Gopnik, A., & Repacholi, B. (1999). Toddlers’ understanding of intentions, desires, and emotions: Explorations of the dark ages. In P. D. Zelazo, J. W. Astington, & D. R. Olson (Eds.), Developing theories of intention (pp. 17–41). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1945/2012). Phenomenology of perception. London: Routledge.

  • Michael, J. (2011). Interactionism and mindreading. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 2, 559–578.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1889). An examination of sir William Hamilton’s philosophy. London: Longsman Greene.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morris, M. W., & Peng, K. (1994). Culture and cause: American and Chinese attributions for social and physical events. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 67(6), 949–971.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2003). Mindreading: An integrated account of pretence, self-awareness, and understanding other minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Overgaard, S., & Michael, J. (2015). The interactive turn in social cognition research: a critique. Philosophical Psychology, 28(2), 160–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Penn, D. C., & Povinelli, D. J. (2008). On the lack of evidence that non-human animals possess anything remotely resembling a ‘theory of mind’. In N. Emery, N. Clayton, & C. Frith (Eds.), Social Intelligence: From Brain to Culture (pp. 415–430). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perner, J. (1991). Understanding the representational mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Premack, D., & Woodruff, G. (1978). Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 4, 515–526.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ramberg, B. (2000). Post-ontological philosophy of mind: Rorty versus Davidson. In R. Brandom (Ed.), Rorty and his Critics (pp. 351–369). Massachusetts: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rietveld, E. (2008). Situated normativity: The normative aspect of embodied cognition in unrefective action. Mind, 117(468), 973–1001.

  • Rietveld, E., & Kiverstein, J. (2014). A rich landscape of affordances. Ecological Psychology, 26(4), 325–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1949/2009). The concept of mind. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Satne, G. (2015). The social roots of normativity. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 14(4), 673–668.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spaulding, S. (2015). On direct social perception. Consciousness and Cognition, 36, 472–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2001). Niche construction, developmental systems and the extended replicator. In S. Oyama, P. E. Griffiths, & R. D. Gray (Eds.), Cycles of Contingency. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2012). The evolved apprentice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1959). Individuals. London: Meuthen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tanney, J. (2013). Rules, reason and self-knowledge. London: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tanney, J. (2015). Gilbert Ryle, in E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. URL=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ryle/.

  • Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (1995). Foreword. In S. Baron-Cohen (Ed.), Mindblindness (pp. xi–xviii). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Troje, N. F. (2013). What is biological motion? Definition, stimuli and paradigms. In M. D. Rutherford & V. A. Kuhlmeier (Eds.), Social perception: Detection and interpretation of animacy, agency, and intention (pp. 13–36). London: MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Uttich, K., & Lombrozo, T. (2010). Norms inform mental state ascriptions: a rational explanation for the side-effect effect. Cognition, 116(1), 87–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Von Eckardt, B. (1994). Folk psychology. In A companion to the philosophy of mind (pp. 300–307). Cambridge: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (1922/1978). Economy and society: an outline of interpretative sociology. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, H. M. (1990). The child’s theory of mind. Cambridge, MA: A Bradford book MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations. Philosophische Untersuchungen. Oxford: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1980). Remarks on the philosophy of psychology. London: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, I. M. (2011). Responsibility for justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2001). Empathy and direct social perception: a phenomenological proposal. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 2(3), 541–558.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zawidzki, T. W. (2008). The function of folk psychology: mind reading or mind shaping? Philosophical Explorations, 11(3), 193–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zawidzki, T. (2013). Mindshaping: A new framework for understanding human social cognition. Cambridge, MA: A Bradford Book MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We are thankful to two anonymous reviewers for their fruitful comments and suggestions.

Funding

This paper has been funded thanks to a 2018 Leonardo Grant for Researchers and Cultural Creators, BBVA Foundation (The Foundation accepts no responsibility for the opinions, statements, and contents included in the project and/or the results thereof, which are entirely the responsibility of the authors), the Projects FFI2015-65953-P and FFI2016-80088-P funded by the Spanish Ministry of Science, the project “Joint Action for Human-Robot Interaction” (ANR-16-CE33-0017) funded by The French National Research Agency and the FiloLab Group of Excellence funded by the Universidad de Granada, Spain.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Víctor Fernández Castro.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Fernández Castro, V., Heras-Escribano, M. Social Cognition: a Normative Approach. Acta Anal 35, 75–100 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-019-00388-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-019-00388-y

Keywords

Navigation