Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Metaepistemic Injustice and Intellectual Disability: a Pluralist Account of Epistemic Agency

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The literature on epistemic injustice currently displays a logocentric or propositional bias that excludes people with intellectual disabilities from the scope of epistemic agency and the demands of epistemic justice. This paper develops an account of epistemic agency and injustice that is inclusive of both people with and people without intellectual disabilities. I begin by specifying the hitherto undertheorized notion of epistemic agency. I develop a broader, pluralist account of epistemic agency, which relies on a conception of knowledge that accounts not only for propositional knowing, but also for other types of knowing that have been largely neglected in debates on epistemic injustice and agency. Based on this pluralist account of epistemic agency, I then show that people with intellectual disabilities qualify as epistemic agents and therefore as subjects of epistemic justice. Finally, I argue that this pluralist account of epistemic agency pushes us to revisit the current conception of epistemic injustice and to expand its taxonomy in two important ways.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. To avoid equivocation, it should be noted that the concept of epistemic agency as defined here and in the literature on epistemic injustice is to be distinguished from the concept of epistemic agency as it is found in traditional epistemology, where it refers, for example, to individuals’ capacities to form beliefs and where it is not connected to the concept of epistemic injustice.

  2. For an exception to this logocentric focus in discussions of epistemic injustice, see Shotwell 2017.

  3. The logocentric conception of epistemic agency can even more broadly exclude the category of people Thomas Schramme (2019) has insightfully termed ‘minority minds’, which includes people with cognitive disabilities (including intellectual disabilities) as well as psychiatrized and neurodivergent individuals.

  4. AAID website: https://www.aaidd.org/intellectual-disability/definition/faqs-on-intellectual-disability.

  5. As is often emphasized, cognitive and intellectual disability are not natural kinds: see, e.g., Brady et al. 2016; Brosco 2010; Carlson 2010a, 2016; Danforth 2019; Harris 2010; Ogletree et al. 2011.

  6. See, e.g., Boardman et al. 2014; Brady et al. 2016; Ogletree et al. 2011; and the numerous studies cited therein.

  7. While the incisive concept of epistemic injustice is owed to Fricker, it captures some of the power dynamics that had previously been insightfully identified and analyzed, if not as succinctly labeled, by feminist epistemologists, including black feminists (e.g., Hill Collins 1990; Crenshaw 1991) and standpoint theorists (e.g., Harding 1986; Hartsock 1983).

  8. Though it should be noted here that the extent to which existing models of disability, which have focused mostly on physical disability, are useful to, or indeed inclusive of, people with cognitive disabilities, including ID, remains a disputed question in disability studies (see, e.g., Bigby 2019, 493; Kittay and Carlson 2010, 6; Mckenzie 2013, 370–1; Paterson 2019, 206; Stalker 2019, 159–61, 167).

  9. Shotwell often uses the term ‘implicit understanding’ to refer to non-propositional knowing or knowledge. I choose to use the terms ‘knowing’ or ‘knowledge’ to indicate more directly the relevance of the elements thus designated to the properly epistemic realm of what we know. While I grant that implicit, non-propositional types of knowing are importantly different from explicit, propositional knowledge (as this expanded typology of knowing makes clear), I use ‘knowing’ and ‘knowledge’ interchangeably for both analytical and normative reasons: because of the similar relevance of all elements thus designated to the properly epistemic realm of what we know, and because to reserve the term ‘knowledge’ solely for propositional knowledge reinforces exclusionary biases, as argued below. I also wish to acknowledge, as Shotwell (Shotwell 2014) does, the significant literature in feminist philosophy that has long recognized both the body and emotions as valuable epistemic resources.

  10. Indeed, this is in general true for privileged/dominant groups with regard to many experiences of oppressed/non-dominant groups, and vice versa. Members of each group might share the propositional knowledge that corresponds to, say, heteronormativity or white supremacy, while having diametrically opposed embodied and affective experiences and knowings of these systems of oppression/domination (e.g., homosexual vs heterosexual attraction, or utter discomfort vs utter comfort in all-white spaces).

  11. While arrived at in a different theoretical context, there is a sense in which this third component of my proposed account of epistemic agency could be framed as providing, in the more specific realm of epistemic agency, a mirror or positive counterpart (focusing on (epistemic) agency rather than (physical) disability) to those disability models that variously highlight the multidimensional and interactive nature of processes of disablement that involve similar contributing factors. Without going into an extensive survey or exegesis of existing taxonomies, one might think of the social model, the ICF, critical realism, and other interactive models (see, e.g., Barnes 2019, Bickenbach 2019, Boardman et al. 2014, Brady et al. 2016, Brosco 2010, Brunner 2019, Fougeyrollas and Beauregard 2001, Hacking 1999, Harris 2010, Mckenzie 2013, Ogletree et al. 2011, Oliver 1990, UPIAS 1976, Verbrugge and Jette 1994, Watson 2019, WHO 2001).

  12. For more on this point in disability studies, policy, and practice, see also Boardman et al. 2014, Brady et al. 2016, Carlson 2016, Kittay 1999, Ogletree et al. 2011, Francis and Silvers 2007.

  13. Or, indeed, whether we are human or non-human animals. I view it as a welcome implication of my account of epistemic agency that (at least some) non-human animals qualify as epistemic agents (e.g., to the extent that they have practical epistemic agency and are able to communicate non-verbally). Note that pointing out that members of these different types of group (people with and without ID as well as non-human animals) variously qualify as epistemic agents on my pluralist account does not imply that their respective experiences, needs, or statuses with regard to other questions are the same. These groups are both internally and externally heterogeneous and highlighting a common feature they share need not entail drawing further comparisons.

  14. As mentioned above, the mainstream distinction between knowing-how (practical knowing) and knowing-that (propositional knowing) is well-known. Moreover, tacit knowing captures something similar to another established notion, called the common ground (Stalnaker 2002; Haslanger 2012; Stanley 2015). Finally, in addition to feminist, critical race, disability, and Indigenous theorists who have long emphasized the role of the body and emotions in the production and acquisition of knowledge, one might also point to the recent literature on transformative experience (Paul 2014), which often uses examples that rely on embodied and affective forms of experiential knowing (embodied and affective knowing), like becoming a vampire, being pregnant, or tasting a new kind of fruit.

  15. Recall that my focus here is on people with severe to profound ID. It is clear that some people with milder types of ID or cognitive disability (e.g., certain people with milder forms of Down Syndrome or of Alzheimer’s) can and do also exercise propositional epistemic agency.

  16. Due to space limitations, I include only one concrete illustration below, but for other examples, see, e.g., Ogletree et al. 2011 and Vorhaus 2015. As noted above, people with severe to profound ID are a heterogeneous group who nonetheless share a common feature relevant for the purposes of theorizing their epistemic agency, namely that they do not communicate through articulated speech.

  17. See, e.g., the epigraph of this article. For other explicit links between epistemic injustice and rationality, see Giladi 2018, Goguen 2016. For a similar logocentric/propositional focus, see most of the literature on epistemic injustice, as noted in the Introduction.

  18. I thank an anonymous reviewer for raising this worry.

  19. In this sense, my contribution here is different from recent arguments aiming to show that minority minds suffer epistemic injustice (see, e.g., Bueter 2019, Jackson 2017, Li 2016, Scrutton 2017).

References

  • Barnes C (2019) Understanding the social model of disability: past, present and future. In: Watson N, Vehmas S (eds) Routledge handbook of disability studies, 2nd edn. Routledge, New York, pp 14–31

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bickenbach JE (2019) The ICF and its relationship to disability studies. In: Watson N, Vehmas S (eds) Routledge handbook of disability studies, 2nd edn. Routledge, New York, pp 55–71

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bigby C (2019) ‘I Hope he dies before me’: Unravelling the debates about ageing and people with intellectual disability. In: Watson N, Vehmas S (eds) Routledge handbook of disability studies, 2nd edn. Routledge, New York, pp 492–506

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Boardman L, Bernal J, Hollins S (2014) Communicating with people with intellectual disabilities: a guide for general psychiatrists. Adv Psychiatr Treat 20:27–36. https://doi.org/10.1192/apt.bp.110.008664

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brady NC, Bruce S, Goldman A, Erickson K, Mineo B, Ogletree BT, Paul D, Romski MA, Sevcik R, Siegel E, Schoonover J, Snell M, Sylvester L, Wilkinson K (2016) Communication services and supports for individuals with severe disabilities: guidance for assessment and intervention. Am J Intellect Dev Disabil 121:121–138. https://doi.org/10.1352/1944-7558-121.2.121

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brosco JP (2010) The limits of the medical model: historical epidemiology of intellectual disability in the United States. In: Kittay EF, Carlson L (eds) Cognitive disability and its challenge to moral philosophy. Wiley-Blackwell, Oxford, pp 26–54

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brunner R (2019) Critical realism as the fourth ‘wave’: deepening and broadening social perspectives on mental distress. In: Watson N, Vehmas S (eds) Routledge handbook of disability studies, 2nd edn. Routledge, New York, pp 189–205

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bueter A (2019) Epistemic injustice and psychiatric classification. Philos Sci 86:1064–1074. https://doi.org/10.1086/705443

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carlson L (2016) Feminist approaches to cognitive disability. Philos Compass 11:541–553. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12350

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carlson L (2010a) The faces of intellectual disability: philosophical reflections. Indiana University Press

  • Carlson L (2010b) Philosophers of intellectual disability: a taxonomy. In: Kittay EF, Carlson L (eds) Cognitive disability and its challenge to moral philosophy. Wiley-Blackwell, Oxford, pp 315–329

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Catala A (2015) Democracy, trust, and epistemic justice. Monist 98:424–440. https://doi.org/10.1093/monist/onv022

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Catala A (2019) Multicultural literacy, epistemic injustice, and white ignorance. Fem Philos Q 5:1–23. https://doi.org/10.5206/fpq/2019.2.7289

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crenshaw K (1991) Mapping the margins: Intersectionality, identity politics, and violence against women of color. Stanford Law Rev 43:1241–1299. https://doi.org/10.2307/1229039

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Danforth S (2019) Diagnosis as social practice and the possibility of interruption. In: Watson N, Vehmas S (eds) Routledge handbook of disability studies, 2nd edn. Routledge, New York, pp 295–304

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dotson K (2011) Tracking epistemic violence, tracking practices of silencing. Hypatia 26:236–257. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1527-2001.2011.01177.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dotson K (2012) A cautionary tale: on limiting epistemic oppression. Front J Women Stud 33:24–47. https://doi.org/10.5250/fronjwomestud.33.1.0024

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fougeyrollas P, Beauregard L (2001) Disability: an interactive person-environment social creation. In: Handbook of disability studies. Sage, Thousand Oaks, pp 171–194

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Francis LP, Silvers A (2007) Liberalism and individually scripted ideas of the good: meeting the challenge of dependent agency. Soc Theory Pract 33:311–334. https://doi.org/10.5840/soctheorpract200733229

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fricker M (2007) Epistemic injustice: power and the ethics of knowing. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fricker M (2013) Epistemic justice as a condition of political freedom? Synthese 190:1317–1332. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-012-0227-3

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giladi P (2018) Epistemic injustice: a role for recognition? Philos Soc Crit 44:141–158. https://doi.org/10.1177/0191453717707237

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilligan C (1982) In a different voice: psychological theory and Women’s development. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Goguen S (2016) Stereotype threat, epistemic injustice, and rationality. In: Brownstein M, Saul J (eds) Implicit Bias and philosophy, vol 1. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 216–237

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Goldin C, Rouse C (2000) Orchestrating impartiality: the impact of “blind” auditions on female musicians. Am Econ Rev 90:715–741. https://doi.org/10.1257/aer.90.4.715

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking I (1999) The social construction of what? Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Harding SG (1986) The science question in feminism. Cornell University Press, Ithaca

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris JC (2010) Developmental perspective on the emergence of moral personhood. In: Kittay EF, Carlson L (eds) Cognitive disability and its challenge to moral philosophy. Wiley-Blackwell, Oxford, pp 55–73

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hartsock NCM (1983) The feminist standpoint: developing the ground for a specifically feminist historical materialism. In: Harding S, Hintikka MB (eds) Discovering reality. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, pp 283–310

    Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger S (2012) Ideology, generics, and common ground. In: resisting reality: social construction and social critique. Oxford University press, Oxford

  • Hill Collins P (1990) Black feminist thought: knowledge, consciousness, and the politics of empowerment. Unwin Hyman, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson J (2017) Patronizing depression: epistemic injustice, stigmatizing attitudes, and the need for empathy: patronizing depression. J Soc Philos 48:359–376. https://doi.org/10.1111/josp.12194

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaggar AM (1989) Love and knowledge: emotion in feminist epistemology. Inquiry 32:151–176. https://doi.org/10.1080/00201748908602185

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kittay EF (1999) Love’s labor: essays on women, equality, and dependency. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kittay EF (2008) Ideal theory bioethics and the exclusion of people with severe cognitive disabilities. In: Lindemann H, Urban Walker M, Verkerk M (eds) Naturalized bioethics: toward responsible knowing and practice. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 218–237

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kittay EF (2010) The personal is philosophical is political: a philosopher and mother of a cognitively disabled person sends notes from the battlefield. In: Kittay EF, Carlson L (eds) Cognitive disability and its challenge to moral philosophy. Wiley-Blackwell, Oxford, pp 393–413

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kittay EF (2005) At the margins of moral personhood. Ethics 116:100–131. https://doi.org/10.1086/454366

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kittay EF, Carlson L (eds) (2010) Cognitive disability and its challenge to moral philosophy. Wiley-Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Li Y (2016) Testimonial injustice without prejudice: considering cases of cognitive or psychological impairment: testimonial injustice without prejudice. J Soc Philos 47:457–469. https://doi.org/10.1111/josp.12175

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mason R (2011) Two kinds of unknowing. Hypatia 26:294–307. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1527-2001.2011.01175.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mckenzie JA (2013) Models of intellectual disability: towards a perspective of (poss)ability. J Intellect Disabil Res 57:370–379. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1365-2788.2012.01547.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Medina J (2013) The epistemology of resistance: gender and racial oppression, epistemic injustice, and the social imagination. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Million D (2013) Therapeutic nations: healing in an age of indigenous human rights. The University of Arizona Press, Tucson

    Google Scholar 

  • Ogletree BT, Bruce SM, Finch A, Fahey R, McLean L (2011) Recommended communication-based interventions for individuals with severe intellectual disabilities. Commun Disord Q 32:164–175. https://doi.org/10.1177/1525740109348791

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oliver M (1990) The politics of disablement. Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Paterson K (2019) It’s about time! Understanding the experience of speech impairment. In: Watson N, Vehmas S (eds) Routledge handbook of disability studies, 2nd edn. Routledge, New York, pp 206–218

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Paul LA (2014) Transformative experience. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pohlhaus G (2012) Relational knowing and epistemic injustice: toward a theory of willful hermeneutical ignorance. Hypatia 27:715–735. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1527-2001.2011.01222.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schramme T (2019) Capable deliberators: towards inclusion of people with mental disabilities in discourse practices

  • Scrutton AP (2017) Epistemic injustice and mental illness. In: Kidd IJ, Medina J, Pohlhaus G (eds) The Routledge handbook of epistemic injustice, 1st edn. Routledge, New York, pp 347–355

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Shotwell A (2011) Knowing otherwise: race, gender, and implicit understanding. Pennsylvania State University Press

  • Shotwell A (2014) Implicit knowledge: how it is understood and used in feminist theory: implicit knowledge. Philos Compass 9:315–324. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12130

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shotwell A (2017) Forms of knowing and epistemic resources. In: Kidd IJ, Medina J, Pohlhaus G (eds) The Routledge handbook of epistemic injustice, 1st edn. Routledge, New York, pp 79–88

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Stalker K (2019) Theorising the position of people with learning difficulties within disability studies: Progress and pitfalls. In: Watson N, Vehmas S (eds) Routledge handbook of disability studies, 2nd edn. Routledge, New York, pp 158–171

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker R (2002) Common ground. Linguistics and Philosophy 25:701–721. https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1020867916902

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley J (2015) How propaganda works. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Union of the Physically Impaired Against Segregation (UPIAS) (1976) Fundamental principles of disability. UPIAS, London

    Google Scholar 

  • United Nations (2006) Comment on Article 12 of the Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities

  • Verbrugge LM, Jette AM (1994) The disablement process. Soc Sci Med 38:1–14. https://doi.org/10.1016/0277-9536(94)90294-1

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vorhaus J (2015) Giving voice to profound disability: dignity, dependence and human capabilities. Routledge, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Watson N (2019) Agency, structure and emancipatory research: researching disablement and impairment. In: Watson N, Vehmas S (eds) Routledge handbook of disability studies, 2nd edn. Routledge, New York, pp 127–141

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Welch S (2019) The phenomenology of a Performative knowledge system: dancing with native American epistemology. Palgrave Macmillan, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • World Health Organization (2001) International classification of functioning. Health, Disability and

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Previous versions of parts of this paper were presented at the Canadian Philosophical Association (Montreal, 2018), at a work-in-progress session in the Philosophy Department at the Université du Québec à Montréal (Montreal, 2018), at a Society for Analytical Feminism session at the Central meeting of the American Philosophical Association (Denver, 2019), and at the SWIP-UK annual conference on Epistemic Injustice, Reasons, and Agency at the University of Kent (Canterbury, 2019). I am thankful to audiences at these events for the opportunity to discuss some of the ideas contained in this paper. For helpful conversations or comments, I am particularly thankful to Sonia Alarie, Matthew Andler, Cory Aragon, Magali Bessone, Bénédicte D’Anjou, Barrett Emerick, Luc Faucher, Audrey Ghali-Lachapelle, Abigail Gosselin, Robert Kopperud, Kimberly Lanthier, Stephen Masson, José Medina, Veli Mitova, Angie Pepper, Pierre Poirier, Lubomira Radoilska, Mauro Rossi, Thomas Schramme, Alessandra Tanesini, Léa Turbide, Kacey Warren, Camille Zimmermann, and two anonymous reviewers for Ethical Theory and Moral Practice. For tremendous research assistance at different stages of this project, I am grateful to Sarah Arnaud, Anne-Marie Gagné-Julien, Simon Goyer, and Mylène Legault.

Funding

This research was undertaken, in part, thanks to funding from the Canada Research Chairs program. This research was also supported by a grant from the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada (SSHRC) and by a grant from the College of Humanities (FSH) at the Université du Québec à Montréal. The current version of this paper was written while on a Faculty Fellowship at the Center for Ethics and Public Affairs at the Murphy Institute at Tulane University.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Amandine Catala.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Catala, A. Metaepistemic Injustice and Intellectual Disability: a Pluralist Account of Epistemic Agency. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 23, 755–776 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-020-10120-0

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-020-10120-0

Keywords

Navigation