Skip to main content
Log in

Integrity and Demandingness

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I discuss Bernard Williams’ ‘integrity objection’ – his version of the demandingness objection to unreasonably demanding ‘extremist’ moral theories such as consequentialism – and argue that it is best understood as presupposing the internal reasons thesis. However, since the internal reasons thesis is questionable, so is Williams’ integrity objection. I propose an alternative way of bringing out the unreasonableness of extremism, based on the notion of the agent’s autonomy, and show how an objection to this proposal can be outflanked by a strategy that also outflanks the ‘paradox of deontology.’

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We cannot ever demonstrate that any option O is literally “the best available to us.” To prove this, we would have to prove that, for every other available option N, O was better than N. But quite generally, this cannot be proved: there is no way of quantifying over ranges of available options. I pass over this argument here; I develop it in Chappell (2001). A similar view is now argued in Wiland (2005).

  2. My aim in this paper is not mainly Williams exegesis; for that see Chappell (2005).

  3. One author who apparently falls into this error is Honderich (online), though his treatment of integrity is very much en passant. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/integrity/ is a useful (though apparently unintentional) survey of the main misinterpretations.

  4. Pace Korsgaard 1996: 101–2, who says that your “practical identity” is “a description under which you value yourself, under which you find your life worth living and your actions to be worth undertaking,” and infers from this that for you to violate your deepest obligations is “to lose your integrity and so your identity, and to no longer be who you are... It is to no longer be able to think of yourself under the description under which you value yourself and find your life to be worth living and your actions to be worth undertaking. It is to be for all practical purposes dead or worse than dead.” Korsgaard’s claim seems exaggerated. It is a matter of common experience that people can and do recover from violating their own deepest obligations; it is rather less of a commonplace that they can recover from death.Rather similarly, Ashford 2003 reads Williams as offering an argument that, for George and Jim, “performing the right action will involve their acting against their conscience, as a result of which their moral identity will be threatened,” and that utilitarianism requires “agents to act in a way which contravenes their present self-conception.” If this was Williams’ key point, it would be wide open to the familiar charge of self-indulgence.

  5. UFA: 90: “[Moral absolutism] is a much stronger position than any involved, as I have defined the issues, in the denial of consequentialism... It is perfectly consistent, and it might be thought a mark of sense, to believe, while not being a consequentialist, that there was no type of action which satisfied [the conditions for counting as morally prohibited no matter what].” Contrast Anscombe 1958, who makes it a defining feature of non-consequentialism to believe in such absolute prohibitions, and so must presumably count Williams, of all people, as a consequentialist.

  6. “But we should distinguish the ability (a) to enumerate all of some agent’s motives from the ability (b) to say, of any motive, whether some agent has that motive. (b) is much less difficult to imagine than (a)!” Indeed it is, but this doesn’t help; the point is that we often don’t have even (b).

  7. Cp. Williams 1985: 54–64 for Williams’ “simplified” and “concretised” account of Kant’s argument, which begins from the question “Is there anything that rational agents necessarily want?”; see also Skorupski (2006) for further discussion.

  8. For this paradox, see Pettit (2000). My discussion here takes further the strategy of response to Pettit sketched in Chappell (2001).

  9. The exact nature of the non-consequentialist’s moral ban is beside the point; it does not matter here whether it is supposed to be (e.g.) an absolute ban, as in Anscombe 1958, or merely a threshold constraint, as in Slote 1985.

  10. Or indeed by performing any number of murders, provided doing these murders prevents even more murders. “Consequentialist rationality... will have something to say even on the difference between massacring seven million, and massacring seven million and one” (Williams UFA: 93).

  11. I offer fuller defences of my sort of value pluralism (there are of course plenty of others, some of them consequentialist) in Chappell (1998), (2003), and (online).

  12. In fact, the non-consequentialist might not claim that the non-breaching of the constraint is itself a good, as opposed to saying that whatever the constraint protects is a good. This would be my own view. However, the distinction makes no difference to the present argument except to add a complication, so I leave it out of the main text.

  13. For the idea that non-consequentialism is essentially agent-relativist see e.g. McNaughton and Rawling 1993.

  14. Strictly speaking value pluralism does not even share the consequentialist commitment to promote goods, since value pluralism is not a maximising theory and consequentialism is; value pluralism’s strong commitment might better be called pursuit of a good than promotion or maximisation of it. For simplicity I pass over this here.

References

  • Anscombe GEM (1958) Modern moral philosophy. Philosophy 33:1–19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arthur J (2002). Famine relief and the ideal moral code. In: LaFollette H (ed) Ethics in practice, 2nd edn. Blackwell’s, Oxford, pp. 582–590

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashford E (2003) The demandingness of Scanlon’s contractualism. Ethics 113:273–302

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chappell T (1998) Understanding human goods. Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Chappell T (2001) A way out of Pettit’s dilemma. Philos Q 51:95–99

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chappell T (2003) Practical rationality for pluralists about the good. Ethical Theory Moral Pract 6:161–177

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chappell T (2005) Stanford encyclopaedia of philosophy entry on “Bernard Williams” (http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/williams-bernard/)

  • Chappell T (online). Ethics and the vision of value. Unpublished book typescript. Online at http://www.open.ac.uk/Arts/philos/chappell-drafts.htm

  • Honderich T (online) Consequentialism, moralities of concern, and selfishness. Online at http://www.ucl.ac.uk/~uctytho/ted9.htm

  • Kagan S (1989) The limits of morality. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard C (1996) The sources of normativity. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • McNaughton D, Rawling P (1993) Deontology and agency. Monist 76:81–100

    Google Scholar 

  • Mulgan T (2001) The demands of consequentialism. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit P (2000) Non-consequentialism and universalisability. Philos Q 50:175–190

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Singer P (1972) Famine, affluence, and morality. Philos Public Aff 1:229–243

    Google Scholar 

  • Skorupski J (2006) Internal reasons and the scope of blame. In: Thomas A (ed) Bernard Williams: contemporary philosophers in focus. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Slote M (1985) Commonsense morality and consequentialism. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Tollefsen C (2004) Basic goods, practical insight, and external reasons. In: Chappell T, Oderberg D (eds) Human values. Routledge, London, pp. 32–51

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiland E (2005) Monkeys, typewriters, and objective consequentialism. Ratio 18:352–360

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Willams B (1985) Ethics and the limits of philosophy. Fontana, London

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgement

Thanks for helpful discussion to Liz Ashford, John Cottingham, Garrett Cullity, Brian Feltham, Brad Hooker, Jussi Jaskelainen, Michelle Mason, Adrian Moore, Tim Mulgan, David Oderberg, Michael Ridge, Philip Stratton-Lake, and Andrew Williams.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Timothy Chappell.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Chappell, T. Integrity and Demandingness. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 10, 255–265 (2007). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-007-9073-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-007-9073-7

Keywords

Navigation