Skip to main content
Log in

Russellian physicalism and its dilemma

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Russellian monism—an influential doctrine proposed by Russell (The analysis of matter, Routledge, London, 1927/1992)—is roughly the view that the natural sciences can only ever tell us about the causal, dispositional, and structural properties of physical entities and not about their categorical properties, and, moreover, that our qualia are constituted by categorical properties. Recently, Stoljar (Philos Phenomenol Res 62:253–281, 2001a), Stoljar (Philos Perspect 15:393–413, 2001b), Strawson (Real materialism: and other essays, Oxford, New York, 2008), Montero (J Conscious Stud 17:70–83, 2010), Montero (in: Alter and Nagasawa (eds) Consciousness in the physical world: perspectives on Russellian monism, Oxford University Press, New York, 2015), Alter and Nagasawa (J Conscious Stud 19:67–95, 2012), and Chalmers (in: Alter and Nagasawa (eds) Consciousness in the physical world: perspectives on Russellian monism, Oxford University Press, New York, 2015) have attempted to develop this doctrine into a version of physicalism. Russellian monism faces the so-called combination problem, according to which it is difficult to see how categorical properties could collectively constitute qualia. In this paper, I suggest that there is an insufficiently discussed aspect of the combination problem which I call the difference-maker problem. Taking the difference-maker problem into account, I argue that the combination problem—whether or not it can be solved—results in a dilemma for the project of developing Russellian physicalism. That is, Russellian monism is either physicalistically unacceptable or it is implausible; hence, Russellian monism and physicalism are incompatible.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Some philosophers use the term ‘intrinsic properties’ here instead. But this terminological difference does not affect the substance of Russellian monism nor the argument I will put forward.

  2. See also Chalmers (2015) and Maxwell (1978) for brief discussions.

  3. Note that I am saying that existing conceptions of physicalism and the physical can be divided into the two families according to their strategies, not that any idea that shares one of the two strategies automatically counts as a conception of physicalism. A related distinction is found in Stoljar (2001a, b), in which he distinguishes between a ‘theory-based conception’ and an ‘object-based conception’. The two families of conceptions I identify are, however, much more inclusive than the two conceptions Stoljar identifies.

  4. This is a variant of Copp’s (2012, p. 28) term, ‘the disciplinary characterisation’.

  5. For a seminal formulation of the problem, see James (1890/1918). For recent formulations, see Hohwy (2005); Goff (2006); Chalmers (2017).

  6. Of course, a quale cannot literally be purple. By a purple quale, I mean a quale of sensing purple.

  7. For a different but related problem, see Chalmers (2017). Chalmers classifies several versions of the combination problem, one of which is the palette problem, namely the problem of how our wide variety of qualia can be generated using relatively few constituents. While the difference-maker problem is related to the palette problem and may even be considered a version of it, the two problems are not identical. The palette problem, just like the combination problem, is wide-ranging and does not particularly concern differences in underlying material composition, even though a comprehensive solution to the palette problem should consist of a solution to the difference-maker problem. For example, Roelofs (2014) discusses the palette problem of, say, how a blue quale and a red quale can be ‘mixed’ into a purple quale. This kind of palette problem is not directly relevant to our discussion here.

  8. See Leibniz 1714/1989, Sect. 17. For similar or related views, see also Alter 2009, 2016; cf. Block 1995; Tse 2019.

  9. There are at least two ways to understand the idea of the Leibnizian gap. Levine's (1983, 2001) concerns an epistemic, explanatory gap between qualia and the physical, whereas Chalmers's (1996, 2010) concerns a metaphysical, constitutional gap between the two. According to the idea of the epistemic, explanatory gap, we cannot possibly know how structures and dynamics can constitute qualia; according to the idea of the metaphysical, constitutional gap, structures and dynamics cannot possibly constitute qualia. These ideas are closely related and may support each other—for example, Chalmers uses the former to support the latter—but they are nonetheless different. In what follows, I will focus on the idea of a metaphysical, constitutional gap, since this is the gap that really counts against classical physicalism.

  10. See also Alter 2009, 2016.

  11. It is debatable whether there are some common, universally shared phenomenal features, such as some phenomenal subjectivity or ‘for-me-ness’, among the variety of ‘what-is-it-likeness’ (see, e.g. Block 1995; Kriegel 2007; but see Liang 2015; Chadha 2018). However, my argument still proceeds as long as there are some distinctive phenomenal features to be found in each kind of quale.

  12. Alter and Nagasawa (2012) offer a similar argument for the conclusion that Russellian emergentism is not theoretically virtuous. However, their argument should not be taken to be identical to mine: it is one thing to say that Russellian emergentism is physicalistically unacceptable and another to say that it is not theoretically virtuous.

  13. Seager (2010, 2017) and Rosenberg (2015) attempt to show that the emergence of qualia is much less idiosyncratic than many believe by appealing to the (alleged) existence of some emergent physical phenomena.

  14. For a related discussion, see Braddon-Mitchell and Jackson (2007).

References

  • Alter, T. (2009). Does the ignorance hypothesis undermine the conceivability and knowledge arguments? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 79(3), 756–765.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alter, T. (2016). The structure and dynamics argument against materialism. Noûs, 50(4), 794–815.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alter, T., & Nagasawa, Y. (2012). What is Russellian monism? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 19(9–10), 67–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. (1961). Perception and the physical world. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (1995). On a confusion about a function of consciousness. Brain and Behavioral Sciences, 18(2), 227–247.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braddon-Mitchell, D. (2007). Against ontologically emergent consciousness. In B. McLaughlin & J. Cohen (Eds.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of mind (pp. 287–300). Malden: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braddon-Mitchell, D., & Jackson, F. (2007). The philosophy of mind and cognition (2nd ed.). Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broad, C. D. (1925). The mind and its place in nature. London: Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chan, L. C. (2018). Emergentism and the contingent solubility of salt. Theoria, 84, 309–324.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chan, L. C., & Latham, A. J. (2019). Four meta-methods for the study of qualia. Erkenntnis, 84(1), 145–167.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chan, L. C. (forthcoming a). Can the russellian monist escape the epiphenomenalist’s paradox? Topoi, special issue on mental powers.

  • Chan, L. C. (forthcoming b). On characterising metaphysical naturalism. Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Mind, 1.

  • Chadha, M. (2018). No-self and the phenomenology of ownership. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 96(1), 14–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind: in search of a fundamental theory. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2010). The character of consciousness. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2015). Panpsychism and panprotopsychism. In T. Alter & Y. Nagasawa (Eds.), Consciousness in the physical world: Perspectives on Russellian monism (pp. 246–276). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2017). The combination problem for panpsychism. In G. Brüntrup & L. Jaskolla (Eds.), Panpsychism: Contemporary perspectives (pp. 179–214). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. S. (1996). The hornswoggle problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 3(5–6), 402–408.

    Google Scholar 

  • Copp, D. (2012). Normativity and reasons: five arguments from Parfit against normative naturalism. In S. Nuccetelli & G. Seay (Eds.), Ethical naturalism: Current debates (pp. 24–57). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edelman, G., & Tononi, G. (2001). A universe of consciousness: How matter becomes imagination. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, M. (2015). Quantum cognition: The possibility of processing with nuclear spins in the brain. Annals of Physics, 362, 593–602.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foster, J. (1993). The succinct case for idealism. In H. Robinson (Ed.), Objections to physicalism (pp. 293–313). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goff, P. (2006). Experiences don’t sum. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 13, 53–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goff, P. (2017). The phenomenal bonding solution to the combination problem. In G. Bruntrup & L. Jaskolla (Eds.), Panpsychism: Contemporary perspectives (pp. 283–303). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J. (2005). Explanation and two conceptions of the physical. Erkenntnis, 62(1), 71–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J., & Frith, C. (2004). Can neuroscience explain consciousness? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 11(7/8), 180–198.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1739/1978). A treatise of human nature, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

  • Jackson, F. (1982). Epiphenomenal qualia. Philosophical Quarterly, 32, 127–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1998). From metaphysics to ethics: A defence of conceptual analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1890/1918). The principles of psychology, vol. 1, Dover Publications, New York.

  • Kriegel, U. (2007). Consciousness: Phenomenal consciousness, access consciousness, and scientific practice. In P. Thagard (Ed.), Handbook of psychology and cognitive science (pp. 195–218). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langton, R. (1998). Kantian humility: Our ignorance of things in themselves. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langton, R., & Robichaud, C. (2010). Ghosts in the world machine? Humility and its alternatives. In A. Hazlett (Ed.), New waves in metaphysics (pp. 156–178). New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, G. (1714/1989). The monadology. In R. Ariew & D. Garber (trans. and Eds.), Philosophical essays, Indianapolis, Hackett.

  • Levine, J. (1983). Materialism and qualia: The explanatory gap. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64, 354–361.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine, J. (2001). Purple Haze: The puzzle of consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1983). New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61(4), 343–377.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (2009). Ramseyan humility. In D. Braddon-Mitchell & R. Nola (Eds.), Conceptual analysis and philosophical naturalism (pp. 203–222). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liang, C. (2015). Self-as-subject and experiential ownership. In J. Windt & T. Metzinger (Eds.), Open MIND. Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maxwell, G. (1978). Rigid designators and mind-brain identity. In W. Savage (Ed.), Perception and cognition: Issues in the foundations of psychology (pp. 365–403). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montero, B. (2010). A Russellian response to the structural argument against physicalism. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 17(3–4), 70–83.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montero, B. (2015). Russellian physicalism. In T. Alter & Y. Nagasawa (Eds.), Consciousness in the physical world: Perspectives on Russellian monism (pp. 209–223). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ney, A. (2008). Physicalism as an attitude. Philosophical Studies, 138(1), 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, R. (1989). The emperor’s new mind: Concerning computers, minds, and the laws of physics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. (1993). A definition of physicalism. Analysis, 53(4), 213–223.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roelofs, L. (2014). Phenomenal blending and the palette problem. Thought, 3(1), 59–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, G. (2015). Causality and the combination problem. In T. Alter & Y. Nagasawa (Eds.), Consciousness in the physical world: Perspectives on Russellian monism (pp. 224–245). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1927/1992). The analysis of matter, Routledge, London.

  • Russell, B. (1927b). An outline of philosophy. London: George Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seager, W. (1995). Consciousness, information, and panpsychism. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2(3), 272–288.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seager, W. (2010). Panpsychism, aggregation and combinatorial infusion. Mind and Matter, 8(2), 167–184.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seager, W. (2017). Panpsychist infusion. In G. Brüntrup & L. Jaskolla (Eds.), Panpsychism: Contemporary perspectives (pp. 229–248). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smart, J. J. C. (1978). The content of physicalism. Philosophical Quarterly, 28, 339–341.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stenger, V. (1995). The unconscious quantum. New York: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar, D. (2001a). Two conceptions of the physical. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 62(2), 253–281.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar, D. (2001b). The conceivability argument and two conceptions of the physical. Philosophical Perspectives, 15(s15), 393–413.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar, D. (2015). Physicalism. In Zalta. E, (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Retrieved from 8 August 2018, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/physicalism/.

  • Strawson, G. (2008). Real materialism: And other essays. New York: Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tse, P. (2019). Fichte’s critique of physicalism—towards an idealist alternative. Inquiry, 62(5), 527–545.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Cleve, J. (1990). Mind—dust or magic? Panpsychism versus emergence. Philosophical Perspectives, 4, 215–226.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I presented this paper at Nanjing University, National Chung Cheng University, National Tsing Hua University, the 2nd Joint Workshop of NTU-Kyoto at National Taiwan University, Artificial Intelligence Beyond Now at Nagoya University of Foreign Studies, and Workshop on Phenomenology and Philosophy of Mind at Huaqiao University. I would like to thank the participants for helpful discussions. For further comments, I am grateful to Eran Asoulin, Tim Bayne, David Braddon-Mitchell, Belinda Calderone, Duen-min Deng, Michael Duncan, Nihel Jhou, Kok-Yong Lee, James Norton, Graham Oppy, Ryoji Sato, Simon Varey, Christian Wenzel, Wai-hung Wong, and an anonymous reviewer. I am also grateful to Caleb Liang and Jeu-Jeng Yuann for their helpful administrative support to this research project. Special thanks are due to Belinda Rickard.

Funding

Funding was provided by Ministry of Science and Technology, Taiwan (Grant Number MOST108-2410-H-002-241-MY3).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lok-Chi Chan.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Chan, LC. Russellian physicalism and its dilemma. Philos Stud 178, 2043–2062 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-020-01522-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-020-01522-y

Keywords

Navigation