The cognitive life of mechanical molecular models

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsc.2013.06.007Get rights and content

Highlights

  • Material molecular models are claimed to be cognitive augmentations.

  • The material and representational properties of such models are examined.

  • The use of these models as research tools is compared to paper-and-pencil strategies.

  • The modeling strategy exploiting the materiality of these models is analyzed as a form of haptic reasoning.

  • The cognitive enhancements allowed by the intelligent use of these models are examined.

Abstract

The use of physical models of molecular structures as research tools has been central to the development of biochemistry and molecular biology. Intriguingly, it has received little attention from scholars of science. In this paper, I argue that these physical models are not mere three-dimensional representations but that they are in fact very special research tools: they are cognitive augmentations. Despite the fact that they are external props, these models serve as cognitive tools that augment and extend the modeler’s cognitive capacities and performance in molecular modeling tasks. This cognitive enhancement is obtained because of the way the modeler interacts with these models, the models’ materiality contributing to the solving of the molecule’s structure. Furthermore, I argue that these material models and their component parts were designed, built and used specifically to serve as cognitive facilitators and cognitive augmentations.

Introduction

Up to the 1960s, biochemistry and molecular biology were profoundly influenced by the deployment and diversity of a peculiar kind of research tool: mechanical molecular models1 (Francoeur, 1997, Francoeur, 2000). Although such physical models of molecular structures have been replaced by simulated or virtual models in modeling tasks (Francoeur & Segal, 2004), the building of scale models of molecular structures from tangible components was once an important part of the practice of biologically oriented chemists. This model-building strategy directly served the scientist’s research interests. The construction and manipulation of plastic, wooden and metallic models of possible molecular structures played a central part in an informed trial-and-error research strategy that proved especially useful in elucidating complex molecular structures such as those of organic macromolecules. In the late 1940s and early 1950s, chemist and biochemist Linus Pauling pioneered the systematic use of these “tinker toys” for the structural determination of compounds (e.g. Corey & Pauling, 1953), a research strategy historian of science Lily Kay has characterized as a “molecular architecture epistemology” (Kay, 1993, p. 262). This pervasive research strategy led to new scientific knowledge, including major breakthroughs, by stimulating the scientist’s imagination and pointing to new research avenues (Laszlo, 1993, Laszlo, 2000). Certainly the most famous example of such successful use of molecular models is James Watson’s and Francis Crick’s use of this research strategy in discovering the basic structure of the DNA molecule. The metallic model they used was not simply a dramatic display in an extravagant showcase: it was itself a tool for research and served as a locus for discovery. And this case is no anomaly—the use of such models for complex structural determination was typical rather than exceptional (Francoeur, 1997).

Although nowadays these tangible models are seldom encountered outside undergraduate biochemistry courses, their historical importance as research tools guarantees their place in the standard iconography of science, making them familiar even to the layman. The role these physical models have played in scientific discovery has received little attention,2 with most scholarly focus being aimed to their supporting roles as pedagogical devices manipulated for better learning/memorization of a selected molecule’s structure or used as visual support in classrooms (e.g. Coll, 2006). Though the historian Olby (1974) does mention here and there the use of such models, and describes in detail Pauling’s paper-made alpha-helix model (Olby, 1974, pp. 208–201; see Section 3.2.1 below), there is no systematic discussion of the importance and role these physical models played—even though they did play a central role in paving the way for contemporary molecular biology. Philosophers have paid even less attention to these models but, when attended, the discussion centers on the more general aspects of representing and modeling (e.g. Giere, 2012), such as the scientists’ struggle with visualizing three-dimensionality by a two dimensional media (e.g. de Chadarevian and Hopwood, 2004, Francoeur, 1997, Gooding, 2006)). More generally, in the SEP entry on Models in Science, Frigg and Hartmann write about physical models that they “[…] do not give rise to any ontological difficulties over and above the well-known quibbles in connection with objects, which metaphysicians deal with.” (Frigg & Hartmann, 2012, Section 2.1). From this latter perspective, there seems to be little more to physical models of molecular structures than a means to represent more accessibly the three-dimensional structure of a given molecule.

The trouble with this view is that it does not account for the actual practice of using physical models as research tools nor for the manner by which new scientific knowledge is produced when doing so. When a modeler aims to solve a molecule’s structure with the aid of such physical models, she explores different combinations of model parts, makes measurements, often disassembling and reassembling the models built. These interactive manipulations exploit the mechanical properties of the models, properties which are not reducible to matters of visualization. Moreover, the use of these physical models has often replaced the deployment of mathematical calculations in molecular modeling contexts. This introduces a pragmatic dimension that cannot be ignored: when compared with geometrical drawings and mathematical calculations, physical models appear to be costly (in time, energy and money) and cumbersome replacements for clean paper work. I argue here that mechanical molecular models are not just static representations, equivalent to flat geometrical and mathematical calculations with a three-dimensional twist; they have something more that makes them non-trivially different from their inscriptional counterparts.

The main claim of this paper is that mechanical molecular models (henceforth, ‘M-models3) were used as research tools that, through their mechanical properties, augment and extend the modeler’s cognitive capacities and performances. Moreover, I argue that their component parts were designed, built and used to serve such cognitive functions. By an intelligent use of M-Models’ material properties, the molecular architect’s manipulations of the model parts enhanced her cognitive performances by facilitating the modeling task. This shows that, contrary to Frigg and Hartmann’s summary, there is more to the ontology of physical models than what has been led to believe by current philosophical investigations. Recasting M-models as cognitive augmentations opens the way for a new horizon of research in the philosophy of science about the scientific uses of physical models.

The following discussion can only be partial due to the immense diversity in the design and application of M-models. My discussion will be limited to ball-and-stick models and CPK space-filling models, and to the context of informed “trial-and-error” research strategies.4 Most of the history of the development and integration of M-models as scientific research tools will also be ignored.5 The present paper is organized as follow: Section 2 sets the stage by describing molecular modeling activities and the representational capabilities of M-models. In Section 3, I argue that the very materiality of physical models is what interests molecular architects, since it allows them to embody the geometrical properties of molecular structures directly. Moreover, the materiality of M-models provides mechanical properties that can be exploited both representationally and as constraints on model building. These material affordances and constraints are central in allowing M-models to serve as cognitive augmentations, since the effective cognitive use of M-models arises from the interaction between the modeler and her model.

Section snippets

Molecular architecture epistemology

“I soon was taught that Pauling’s accomplishment was a product of common sense, not the result of complicated mathematical reasoning. Equations occasionally crept into his argument, but in most cases words would have sufficed. […] the essential trick, instead, was to ask which atoms like to sit next to each other. In place of pencil and paper, the main working tools were a set of molecular models superficially resembling the toys of preschool children.” (Watson, 1980, p. 50)

Molecular modeling

Physical models

Physical models, such as plastic organs, animal models, Watson and Crick’s metal plated model of DNA, etc., are physical objects serving as representations of something else. There are many kinds of such models used in scientific research, differing greatly with respect to their representational capabilities, but also by the part they play in scientific investigations. Although physical models share a set of important similarities with abstract models (e.g. Bohr’s atomic model), the most

Conclusion

In this paper I have argued that an informed use of M-models allows these material props to serve as cognitive augmentations which facilitate the molecular modeling tasks biochemists and molecular biologists confront. Mechanical molecular models are research tools that bolster the molecular architect’s cognitive performances. Instead of relying on mathematical tools or solely on internal cognitive capacities, the architect manipulates these material props in such a way as to become more

Acknowledgements

This paper could not have been completed without the help of Éric Francoeur who generously shared with me his research notes. I would also like to thank Jean-Pierre Marquis, Michael Trestman and two anonymous referees for helpful comments and advice on an earlier version of this paper. This paper was written with the financial support of the Fonds de recherche du Québec—Société et culture while being hosted by the Konrad Lorenz Institute for Evolution and Cognition Research.

References (35)

  • J.W. Apsimon et al.

    The measurement of angles and distances in molecular models III. A general device

    Canadian Journal of Chemistry

    (1968)
  • D. Baird

    Thing knowledge: A philosophy of scientific instruments

    (2004)
  • R.K. Coll

    The role of models, mental models and analogies in chemistry teaching

  • R.B. Corey et al.

    Molecular models of amino acids, peptides, and proteins

    The Review of Scientific Instruments

    (1953)
  • E. Francoeur

    The forgotten tools: The design and use of molecular models

    Social Studies of Science

    (1997)
  • E. Francoeur

    The forgotten tool: A socio-historical analysis of the development and use of mechanical molecular models in chemistry and allied disciplines

    (1998)
  • E. Francoeur

    Beyond dematerialization and inscription

    Hyle

    (2000)
  • E. Francoeur

    Molecular models and the articulation of structural constraints in chemistry

  • E. Francoeur et al.

    From model kits to interactive computer graphics

  • Frigg, R., & Hartmann, S. (2012). Models in science. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy...
  • R.N. Giere

    Representing with physical models

  • D.C. Gooding

    Visual cognition: Where cognition and culture meet

    Philosophy of Science

    (2006)
  • D.C. Gooding

    Visualizing scientific inference

    Topics in Cognitive Science

    (2010)
  • P.W. Humphreys

    Extending ourselves

    (2004)
  • L.E. Kay

    The molecular vision of life: Caltech, the Rockfeller foundation, and the rise of the new biology

    (1993)
  • U. Klein

    Techniques of modelling and paper-tools in classical chemistry

  • Cited by (9)

    View all citing articles on Scopus
    View full text