Skip to main content

Governing Without a Fundamental Direction of Time: Minimal Primitivism About Laws of Nature

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover Rethinking the Concept of Law of Nature

Abstract

The Great Divide in metaphysical debates about laws of nature is between Humeans, who think that laws merely describe the distribution of matter, and non-Humeans, who think that laws govern it. The metaphysics can place demands on the proper formulations of physical theories. It is sometimes assumed that the governing view requires a fundamental/intrinsic direction of time: to govern, laws must be dynamical, producing later states of the world from earlier ones, in accord with the fundamental direction of time in the universe. In this paper, we propose a minimal primitivism about laws of nature (MinP) according to which there is no such requirement. On our view, laws govern by constraining the physical possibilities. Our view captures the essence of the governing view without taking on extraneous commitments about the direction of time or dynamic production. Moreover, as a version of primitivism, our view requires no reduction/analysis of laws in terms of universals, powers, or dispositions. Our view accommodates several potential candidates for fundamental laws, including the principle of least action, the Past Hypothesis, the Einstein equation of general relativity, and even controversial examples found in the Wheeler-Feynman theory of electrodynamics and retrocausal theories of quantum mechanics. By understanding governing as constraining, non-Humeans who accept MinP have the same freedom to contemplate a wide variety of candidate fundamental laws as Humeans do.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In this paper, we use “fundamental laws” and “laws” interchangeably unless noted otherwise.

  2. 2.

    This is an oversimplification as there are some non-Humeans, such as Aristotelian Reductionists, who do not think that laws govern. See Sect. 2.3.

  3. 3.

    Throughout this paper, for simplicity, we assume that spacetime is fundamental. This assumption is not essential to MinP. One can consider non-spatio-temporal worlds governed by minimal primitivist laws. For those worlds, one can understand MinP as suggesting that laws constrain the physical possibilities of the world, whatever non-spatio-temporal structure it may have. Indeed, if one regards time itself as emergent, one may find it natural to understand governing in an atemporal and direction-less sense.

  4. 4.

    Causal fundamentalism does not imply that everyday causality is metaphysically fundamental. For example, Maudlin’s notion of dynamic production is different from everyday causality (Maudlin 2007, ch.5). For some recent works on causal fundamentalism, physics, and everyday causality, see Blanchard (2016) and Weaver (2019).

  5. 5.

    This survey is by no means exhaustive of the rich literature on laws. For example, against the view that there are fundamental laws that are universally true, Cartwright (1994a) advocates a patchwork view of laws where they are, at most, true ceteris paribus. Van Fraassen (1989) advocates a view where there are no laws of nature. See Carroll (2020), Hildebrand (2020), Bhogal (2020) for more detailed surveys.

  6. 6.

    Whether contemporary Humean position in the metaphysics of science represents the historical Hume has been debated. See for example Strawson (2015).

  7. 7.

    For example, the regularity that all uranium spheres are less than one mile in diameter may be a law or a consequence of some law, but the regularity that all gold spheres are less than one mile in diameter is not a law or a consequence of a law.

  8. 8.

    Another issue concerning theoretical virtues is how we should use them to compare different systems. As noted earlier, simplicity is language relative. Cohen and Callender (2009) suggest that the comparisons should be relativized to languages. Their relativized account (called the Better Best System Account) perhaps can be used to support Fodor (1974)’s vision of the autonomy of the special sciences (e.g. biology, psychology, economics) from fundamental physics.

  9. 9.

    For an overview of Plato’s theory of forms, see Kraut (2017).

  10. 10.

    In the literature it is sometimes called the DTA account of laws or the Universalist account of laws. Calling it Platonic reductionism may be controversial. But see the discussion in (Carroll 1994, appendix A1).

  11. 11.

    We note that this example about F = ma does not exactly fit in Armstrong’s schema of “All F’s are G.” See (Armstrong 1983, ch.7) for a proposal for accommodating “functional laws.”

  12. 12.

    In a famous passage, Lewis (1983) raises this objection: “Whatever N may be, I cannot see how it could be absolutely impossible to have N(F,G) and Fa without Ga…The mystery is somewhat hidden by Armstrong’s terminology. He uses ‘necessitates’ as a name for the lawmaking universal N; and who would be surprised to hear that if F ‘necessitates’ G and a has F, then a must have G? But I say that N deserves the name of ‘necessitation’ only if, somehow, it really can enter into the requisite necessary connections. It can’t enter into them just by bearing a name, any more than one can have mighty biceps just by being called ‘Armstrong’ ” (p. 366).

  13. 13.

    For an overview of the metaphysics of dispositions, see Choi and Fara (2021).

  14. 14.

    Some, such as Bird (2007), go further and claim that all perfectly natural properties in Lewis (1986)’s sense or all sparse universals in Armstrong (1983)’s sense have dispositional essences.

  15. 15.

    Many defenders of this view suggest that even though it has roots in Aristotle, it is not committed to many aspects of Aristotelianism.

  16. 16.

    In contrast, Vetter (2015) is open to a temporally symmetric metaphysics but assumes temporal asymmetry in her account of dispositions (which she calls potentialities).

  17. 17.

    See Laudisa (2015) for a nice development of Maudlinian Primitivism. Carroll (1994) is often called a primitivist about laws, though recently Carroll (2018) distances his view from that of Maudlin and suggests a non-Humean reductive analysis of laws in terms of causation/explanation.

  18. 18.

    This reading of Maudlin is supported by the earlier passages as well as this one: “It was perhaps already clear when I wrote ‘A Modest Proposal…’ that the issue of time and the issue of natural laws were deeply intertwined: I noted in that essay that the fundamental laws of nature appear to be laws of temporal evolution: they specify how the state of the universe will, or might, evolve from a given initial state” (emphasis original, p. 172).

  19. 19.

    Bhogal (2017) proposes a “minimal anti-Humeanism” on which laws are ungrounded (true) universal generalizations. It is compatible with primitivism, but it is less minimalist than MinP. For example, on Bhogal’s view, laws cannot be singular facts about particular times or places. However, Bhogal (p. 447, fn.1) seems open to relax the requirement that laws have to be universal generalizations. It would be interesting to see how to extend Bhogal’s view to do so. In an arXiv preprint posted shortly after our paper, Adlam (2021) independently proposes an account that is, in certain aspects, similar to MinP; she also suggests we take seriously laws that do not have a time-evolution form. However, her account is not committed to primitivism and seems more at home in a structural realist framework. Moreover, simplicity does not seem essential to her account of nomic explanations.

  20. 20.

    For those metaphysically inclined, here are some formal details. Consider w, the complete history of a possible world describable in terms of matter in spacetime. Let Ω w be the non-empty set of worlds that are physically possible (from the perspective of w). It is a priori that w ∈ Ω w. Consider fact L, which may be Newton’s equation of motion with Newtonian gravitation. Let Ω L be the set of models generated by L. Now, suppose L governs w. Then the following is true:

    Equivalence :

    Ω L = Ω w

    Equivalence makes precise the idea that on MinP governing laws limit the physical possibilities. Since w ∈ Ω w, it follows that:

    Constraint :

    w ∈ Ω L

    If we let w = α, the actual world, then Constraint makes precise the idea that, on MinP, laws constrain the actual world. For MinP, we postulate that the above notions and derivations make sense. A natural idea is to reduce or analyze physical possibilities and necessities in terms of fundamental laws and a notion of mathematical consistency. This makes physical possibilities a derivative notion rather than a fundamental one. However, we do not insist on it here. A few epistemological remarks: the fact that Ω L = Ω w is knowable a posteriori; consequently, the fact that w ∈ Ω L is also knowable a posteriori. A careful reader might raise a consistency worry here: what if a single world (history) w is compatible with two different laws L and L′ with non-empty overlap in their solution spaces, such that \(w\in \varOmega ^L \cap \varOmega ^{L'}\)? The worry is handled by the earlier postulates. Having \(w\in \varOmega ^{L'}\) is not sufficient for L′ to be the governing law or for \(\varOmega ^{L'}\) to be the set of physical possibilities. MinP assumes that, from the perspective each world, there is a single set of physical possibilities, given by the governing law(s). Hence, for w, if Ω L and \( \varOmega ^{L'}\) are different sets, then at most one of them is equivalent to Ω w. Moreover, since Ω w is non-empty, the laws that govern w must be consistent with each other.

  21. 21.

    If one prefers the representation where the set of physical possibilities contains each possibility exactly once, one can derive a quotient set \(\varOmega _{\alpha }^\ast \) from Ω α with the equivalence relation given by the time-reversal map.

  22. 22.

    It is an interesting question, on MinP, what more is required and how to understand the equivalence of physical laws. Perhaps their equivalence is related to simplicity and explanations. In any case, we do not provide such an account as it is orthogonal to our main concerns in the paper. For a survey of the related topic of theoretical equivalence, see Weatherall (2019a, 2019b).

  23. 23.

    Humeans face a similar issue, as their account raises the worry as to why the fundamental Humean mosaic is so nice that it can be summarized in a simple way after all.

  24. 24.

    This type of explanation, sometimes called “constraint explanation,” has been explored in the causation literature by Ben-Menahem (2018) and non-causal explanation literature by Lange (2016). Their accounts, with suitable modifications, may apply here. See Hildebrand (2013) for a critical discussion of primitive laws and explanations.

  25. 25.

    Christopher Dorst raised a similar point in personal communication. See also Dorst (2021).

  26. 26.

    Making a similar point, Callender (2017, p. 139) writes: “[The] ten vacuum Einstein field equations separate into six “evolution” equations G ij = 0 and four “constraint equations,” G 00 = 0 and G 0i = 0, with i = 1,  2,  3. The latter impose nomic conditions across a spacelike slice. To decree that four of the ten equations that constitute Einstein’s field equations are not nomic without good reason is unacceptable.”

  27. 27.

    However, see Roberts (2008) for a Humean account of laws based on a contextualist semantics that may alleviate this worry.

  28. 28.

    See also Gordon Belot’s paper on ratbag idealism in this volume.

  29. 29.

    However, Bird (2007) talks about laws supervening on dispositions and allows that laws can still govern in a weaker sense.

  30. 30.

    In a recent book, Vetter (2015) is open to the idea that there can be past-directed dispositions but still suggests that there is a temporal asymmetry: past-directed dispositions are trivial.

  31. 31.

    In personal communication, Maudlin suggests that he now regards (3) as expressing a metaphysical analysis or a definition of ρ in terms of the divergence of E.

References

  • Adlam, E. (2021). Laws of nature as constraints. Manuscript: arXiv 2109.13836.

    Google Scholar 

  • Albert, D. Z. (2000). Time and chance. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. M. (1983). What is a law of nature? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Arnowitt, R., Deser, S., & Misner, C. W. (1962). The dynamics of general relativity. In L. Witten (Ed.), Gravitation: An introduction to current research (pp. 227–264). Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bacciagaluppi, G. (2005). A conceptual introduction to Nelson’s mechanics. In A. E. Rosolino Buccheri & M. Saniga (Eds.), Endophysics, Time, Quantum And The Subjective: Proceedings of the ZiF Interdisciplinary Research Workshop, Bielefeld, Germany, 17–22 January 2005 (pp. 367–388). World Scientific.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beebee, H. (2000). The non-governing conception of laws of nature. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 61, 571–594.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ben-Menahem, Y. (2018). Causation in science. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bhogal, H. (2017). Minimal anti-Humeanism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 95(3), 447–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bhogal, H. (2020). Humeanism about laws of nature. Philosophy Compass, 15(8), e12696.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2007). Nature’s metaphysics: Laws and properties. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Blanchard, T. (2016). Physics and causation. Philosophy Compass, 11(5), 256–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callender, C. (2004). Measures, explanations and the past: Should ‘special’ initial conditions be explained? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 55(2), 195–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callender, C. (2017). What makes time special? Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, J. W. (1994). Laws of nature. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, J. W. (2018). Becoming Humean. In W. Ott & L. Patton (Eds.), Laws of nature (pp. 122–138). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, J. W. (2020). Laws of nature. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, Winter 2020 edition.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1983). How the laws of physics lie. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1994a). Fundamentalism vs. the patchwork of laws. In Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (vol. 94, pp. 279–292). JSTOR.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1994b). Nature’s capacities and their measurement. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chen, E. K. (2020). The past hypothesis and the nature of physical laws. In B. Loewer, W. E. & B. Weslake (Eds.), Time’s arrows and the probability structure of the world. Harvard University Press, forthcoming.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chen, E. K. (2022). Fundamental nomic vagueness. The Philosophical Review, 131(1).

    Google Scholar 

  • Choi, S., & Fara, M. (2021). Dispositions. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, Spring 2021 edition.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J., & Callender, C. (2009). A better best system account of lawhood. Philosophical Studies, 145(1), 1–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deckert, D.-A. (2010). Electrodynamic absorber theory: A mathematical study. PhD Thesis, Ludwig Maximilian University of Munich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Demarest, H. (2017). Powerful properties, powerless laws. In J. D. Jacobs (Ed.), Causal powers (pp. 38–53). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Demarest, H. (2019). Mentaculus laws and metaphysics. Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology, 23(3), 387–399.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Demarest, H. (2021). Powers, best systems, and explanation. Manuscript.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dorst, C. (2021). Productive laws in relativistic spacetimes. Manuscript.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1977). Laws of nature. Philosophy of Science, 44, 248–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dürr, D., Goldstein, S., & Zanghì, N. (1992). Quantum equilibrium and the origin of absolute uncertainty. Journal of Statistical Physics, 67(5–6), 843–907.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (2001). Scientific essentialism. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (2014). The philosophy of nature: A guide to the new essentialism. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1974). Special sciences (or: The disunity of science as a working hypothesis). Synthese, 28, 97–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friederich, S., & Evans, P. W. (2019). Retrocausality in quantum mechanics. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, summer 2019 edition.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghirardi, G. (2018). Collapse theories. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, fall 2018 edition.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghirardi, G., Rimini, A., & Weber, T. (1986). Unified dynamics for microscopic and macroscopic systems. Physical Review D, 34(2), 470.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, S. (2001). Boltzmann’s approach to statistical mechanics. In J. Bricmont, D. Dürr, M. C. Galavotti, G. Ghirardi, F. Petruccione, & N. Zanghì (Eds.), Chance in physics (pp. 39–54). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, S. (2012). Typicality and notions of probability in physics. In Probability in physics (pp. 59–71). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, S. (2017). Bohmian mechanics. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, summer 2017 edition.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, S., & Tumulka, R. (2003). Opposite arrows of time can reconcile relativity and nonlocality. Classical and Quantum Gravity, 20(3), 557.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henderson, L. (2020). The problem of induction. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, Spring 2020 edition.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hicks, M. T., & Schaffer, J. (2017). Derivative properties in fundamental laws. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 68(2), 411–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hildebrand, T. (2013). Can primitive laws explain? Philosophers’ Imprint.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hildebrand, T. (2020). Non-Humean theories of natural necessity. Philosophy Compass, 15(5), e12662.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hildebrand, T., & Metcalf, T. (2021). The nomological argument for the existence of God. Noûs.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoefer, C. (2019). Chance in the world: A Humean guide to objective chance. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Khlentzos, D. (2021). Challenges to metaphysical realism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, Spring 2021 edition.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kimpton-Nye, S. (2017). Humean laws in an unHumean world. Journal of the American Philosophical Association,3(2), 129–147.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kraut, R. (2017). Plato. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, Fall 2017 edition.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2009). Laws and lawmakers: Science, metaphysics, and the laws of nature. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2016). Because without Cause: Non-casual explanations in science and mathematics. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Laudisa, F. (2015). Laws are not descriptions. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 29(3), 251–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lazarovici, D. (2018). Against fields. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 8(2), 145–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1980). A subjectivist’s guide to objective chance. In R. C. Jeffrey (Ed.), Studies in inductive logic and probability (Vol. 2, pp. 263–93). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1983). New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61, 343–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). Philosophical papers II. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1994). Humean supervenience debugged. Mind, 103, 473–490.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loewer, B. (2001). Determinism and chance. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 32(4), 609–620.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loewer, B. (2012). Two accounts of laws and time. Philosophical Studies, 160(1), 115–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loewer, B. (2021a). The package deal account of laws and properties (PDA). Synthese, 199(1), 1065–1089.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loewer, B. (2021b). What breathes fire into the equations. Manuscript.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin, T. (2007). The metaphysics within physics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S. (2004). Laws in nature. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, E. (1966). Derivation of the Schrödinger equation from Newtonian mechanics. Physical Review, 150(4), 1079.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, R. (1974). The role of aesthetics in pure and applied mathematical research. Bulletin of Mathematical Analysis and Applications, 10, 266–271.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, R. (1979). Singularities and time-asymmetry. In S. Hawking, & W. Israel (Eds.), General relativity (pp. 581–638). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, R. (1989). The emperor’s new mind: Concerning computers, minds, and the laws of physics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, J. T. (2008). The law-governed universe. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2016). It is the business of laws to govern. Dialectica, 70(4), 577–588.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (2015). ‘Humeanism’. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 1(1), 96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sutherland, R. I. (2008). Causally symmetric Bohm model. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 39(4), 782–805.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tooley, M. (1977). The nature of laws. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 7(4), 667–698.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tooley, M. (1997). Time, tense and causation. Oxford University Press, Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. C. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vetter, B. (2015). Potentiality: From dispositions to modality. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weatherall, J. O. (2019a). Part 1: Theoretical equivalence in physics. Philosophy Compass, 14(5), e12592.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weatherall, J. O. (2019b). Part 2: Theoretical equivalence in physics. Philosophy Compass, 14(5), e12591.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weaver, C. G. (2019). Fundamental causation: Physics, metaphysics, and the deep structure of the world. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, S. (1992). Dreams of a final theory: The search for the fundamental laws of nature. New York: Pantheon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, J. A., & Feynman, R. P. (1945). Interaction with the absorber as the mechanism of radiation. Reviews of Modern Physics, 17(2–3), 157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, J. A., & Feynman, R. P. (1949). Classical electrodynamics in terms of direct interparticle action. Reviews of Modern Physics, 21(3), 425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wigner, E. (1985). Events, laws of nature, and invariance principles. In A. Zichichi (Ed.), How Far Are We from the Gauge Forces–Proceedings of the 21st Course of the International School of Subnuclear Physics, Aug 3–14, 1983 (pp. 699–708). Plenum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wigner, E. P. (1964). Symmetry and conservation laws. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 51(5), 956–965.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, M. (1987). What is a law of nature? (Book review). The Philosophical Review, 96(3), 435–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

For helpful discussions, we thank David Albert, Jeff Barrett, Yemima Ben-Menahem, Craig Callender, Claudio Calosi, Lorenzo Cocco, Maaneli Derakhshani, Christopher Dorst, Joshua Eisenthal, Nina Emery, Veronica Gomez, Mara Harrell, Tyler Hildebrand, Christopher Hitchcock, Mario Hubert, Jenann Ismael, Marc Lange, Federico Laudisa, Dustin Lazarovici, Baptiste Le Bihan, Barry Loewer, Tim Maudlin, Giovanni Merlo, Kerry McKenzie, Jill North, Elias Okon, Ezra Rubenstein, David Schroeren, Charles Sebens, Ted Sider, Shelly Yiran Shi, Isaac Wilhelm, Ken Wharton, Christian Wüthrich, Nino Zanghì, audiences at California Institute of Technology, University of Geneva, Rutgers University, Metro Area Philosophers of Science, 2021 Annual Meeting of the California Quantum Interpretation Network, and participants in the graduate seminar “Rethinking Laws of Nature” at the University of California San Diego in spring 2021. EKC received research assistance from Shelly Yiran Shi and was supported by an Academic Senate Grant from the University of California San Diego.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Eddy Keming Chen .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Chen, E.K., Goldstein, S. (2022). Governing Without a Fundamental Direction of Time: Minimal Primitivism About Laws of Nature. In: Ben-Menahem, Y. (eds) Rethinking the Concept of Law of Nature . Jerusalem Studies in Philosophy and History of Science. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-96775-8_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics