Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-sxzjt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T14:53:35.964Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Error Is in the Gap: Synthesizing Accounts for Societal Values in Science

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

Kevin Elliott and others separate two common arguments for the legitimacy of societal values in scientific reasoning as the gap and the error arguments (respectively, the arguments from underdetermination and from inductive risk). This article poses two questions: How are these two arguments related, and what can we learn from their interrelation? I contend that we can better understand the error argument as nested within the gap because the error is a limited case of the gap with narrower features. Furthermore, this nestedness provides philosophers with conceptual tools for analyzing more robustly how values pervade science.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I am grateful for advice and encouragement from Lisa Lloyd and Jutta Schickore; for thought-provoking discussions with Josua Aponte-Serrano, Evan Arnet, Jordi Cat, Kevin Elliott, Kate Grauvogel, Amit Hagar, Nora Hangel, Bennett Holman, Becca Jackson, Ryan Ketcham, Monica Morrison, and Nick Zautra; and for critical comments from two anonymous reviewers. An earlier version of this article was presented at Indiana University for the 2017 Hanson Prize Lecture, and I thank the audience for their questions and criticism. This material is based upon work supported by the National Science Foundation Graduate Research Fellowship Program under grant no. 1342962. Any opinions, findings, and conclusions or recommendations expressed in this material are those of the author and do not necessarily reflect the views of the National Science Foundation.

References

Anderson, Elizabeth. 2004. “Uses of Value Judgments in Science: A General Argument, with Lessons from a Case Study of Feminist Research on Divorce.” Hypatia 19 (1): 124..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Betz, Gregor. 2013. “In Defence of the Value Free Ideal.” European Journal for Philosophy of Science 3 (2): 207–20..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Biddle, Justin. 2013. “State of the Field: Transient Underdetermination and Values in Science.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science A 44 (1): 124–33..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Biddle, Justin 2015. “Values in Science.” In Ethics, Science, Technology, and Engineering, ed. Holbrook, J. Britt. Farmington Hills, MI: Macmillan Reference.Google Scholar
Biddle, Justin 2016. “Inductive Risk, Epistemic Risk, and Overdiagnosis of Disease.” Perspectives on Science 24 (2): 192205..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brigandt, Ingo. 2015. “Social Values Influence the Adequacy Conditions of Scientific Theories: Beyond Inductive Risk.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 45 (3): 326–56..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, Matthew J. 2013. “Values in Science beyond Underdetermination and Inductive Risk.” Philosophy of Science 80 (5): 829–39..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, Matthew J., and Havstad, Joyce C. 2017. “The Disconnect Problem, Scientific Authority, and Climate Policy.” Perspectives on Science 25 (1): 6794..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carrier, Martin. 2011. “Underdetermination as an Epistemological Test Tube: Expounding Hidden Values of the Scientific Community.” Synthese 180 (2): 189204..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy. 2011. “A Philosopher’s View of the Long Road from RCTs to Effectiveness.” Lancet 377 (9775): 14001401..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy, Cat, Jordi, Fleck, Lola, and Uebel, Thomas. 1996. Otto Neurath: Philosophy between Science and Politics. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cat, Jordi, Chang, Hasok, and Cartwright, Nancy. 1991. “Otto Neurath: Unification as the Way to Socialism.” In Einheit Der Wissenschaften, ed. Mittelstraß, Jürgen, 91110. New York: de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Churchman, C. West. 1948. Theory of Experimental Inference. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Churchman, C. West 1956. “Science and Decision Making.” Philosophy of Science 23 (3): 247–49..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cranor, Carl F. 1993. Regulating Toxic Substances: A Philosophy of Science and the Law. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dewey, John. 1939. “Theory of Valuation.” International Encyclopedia of Unified Science 2 (4): 166..Google Scholar
Douglas, Heather. 2000. “Inductive Risk and Values in Science.” Philosophy of Science 67 (4): 559–79..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Douglas, Heather 2009. Science, Policy, and the Value-Free Ideal. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Douglas, Heather 2016. “Values in Science.” In Oxford Handbook in the Philosophy of Science, ed. Humphreys, Paul. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Elliott, Kevin. 2011. Is a Little Pollution Good for You? Incorporating Societal Values in Environmental Research. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elliott, Kevin, and McKaughan, Daniel J. 2014. “Nonepistemic Values and the Multiple Goals of Science.” Philosophy of Science 81 (1): 121..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elliott, Kevin, and McKaughan, Daniel J. 2017. A Tapestry of Values: An Introduction to Values in Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giere, Ronald N. 2003. “A New Program for Philosophy of Science?Philosophy of Science 70 (1): 1526..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldenberg, Maya J. 2015. “How Can Feminist Theories of Evidence Assist Clinical Reasoning and Decision-Making?Social Epistemology 29 (1): 330..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harding, Sandra. 1991. Whose Science? Whose Knowledge? Thinking from Women’s Lives. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Hempel, Carl G. 1965. “Science and Human Values.” In Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science, 8196. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Hicks, Daniel J. 2014. “A New Direction for Science and Values.” Synthese 191 (14): 32719f5..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howard, Don. 2003. “Two Left Turns Make a Right.” In Logical Empiricism in North America, Vol. 18, ed. Gary L. Hardcastle and Alan W. Richardson, 25–93. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Howard, Don 2006. “Lost Wanderers in the Forest of Knowledge: Some Thoughts on the Discovery-Justification Distinction.” In Revisiting Discovery and Justification, ed. Schickore, Jutta and Steinle, Friedrich, 322. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Intemann, Kristen. 2005. “Feminism, Underdetermination, and Values in Science.” Philosophy of Science 72 (5): 1001–12..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Intemann, Kristen 2015. “Distinguishing between Legitimate and Illegitimate Values in Climate Modeling.” European Journal for Philosophy of Science 5 (2): 217–32..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jeffrey, Richard C. 1956. “Valuation and Acceptance of Scientific Hypotheses.” Philosophy of Science 23 (3): 237–46..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jukola, Saana. 2015. “Longino’s Theory of Objectivity and Commercialized Research.” In Empirical Philosophy of Science: Introducing Qualitative Methods into Philosophy of Science, ed. Wagenknecht, Susann, Nersessian, Nancy J., and Andersen, Hanne, 127–43. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Kourany, Janet A. 2003a. “A Philosophy of Science for the Twenty-First Century.” Philosophy of Science 70 (1): 114..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kourany, Janet A. 2003b. “A Philosophy of Science for the Twenty-First Century? Reply to Giere.” Philosophy of Science 70 (1): 2226..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kourany, Janet A. 2010. Philosophy of Science after Feminism. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. 1977. “Objectivity, Value Judgment, and Theory Choice.” In The Essential Tension, 320–39. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, Larry. 1984. Science and Values: The Aims of Science and Their Role in Scientific Debate. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Levi, Isaac. 1960. “Must the Scientist Make Value Judgments?Journal of Philosophy 57 (11): 345–57..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lloyd, Elisabeth A. 2005. The Case of the Female Orgasm: Bias in the Science of Evolution. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lloyd, Elisabeth A., and Oreskes, Naomi. 2018. “Climate Change Attribution: When Is It Appropriate to Accept New Methods?Earth’s Future 6 (3): 311–25..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lloyd, Elisabeth A., and Schweizer, Vanessa J. 2014. “Objectivity and a Comparison of Methodological Scenario Approaches for Climate Change Research.” Synthese 191 (10): 2049–88..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Longino, Helen E. 1990. Science as Social Knowledge. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Longino, Helen E. 1996. “Cognitive and Non-cognitive Values in Science: Rethinking the Dichotomy.” In Feminism, Science, and the Philosophy of Science, ed. Nelson, L. H. and Nelson, J., 3958. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mann, Michael E., Lloyd, Elisabeth A., and Oreskes, Naomi. 2017. “Assessing Climate Change Impacts on Extreme Weather Events: The Case for an Alternative (Bayesian) Approach.” Climatic Change 144 (2): 131–42..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMullin, Ernan. 1982. “Values in Science.” In PSA 1982: Proceedings of the 1982 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, Vol. 2, ed. Peter D. Asquith and Thomas Nickles, 3–28. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association.Google Scholar
Melo-Martin, Inmaculada de, and Intemann, Kristen. 2016. “The Risk of Using Inductive Risk to Challenge the Value-Free Ideal.” Philosophy of Science 83 (4): 500520..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morrison, Monica. 2018. “Influences on Climate Modeling Methodologies.” PhD diss., Indiana University.Google Scholar
Neurath, Otto. 1913/1983. “The Lost Wanderers of Descartes and the Auxiliary Motive (On the Psychology of Decision).” In Philosophical Papers, 1913–1946, ed. and trans. Cohen, Robert Sonné and Neurath, Marie, 112. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Neurath, Otto. 1928/1973. Empiricism and Sociology. ed. and trans. Neurath, Marie and Cohen, Robert S. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Okruhlik, Kathleen. 2004. “Logical Empiricism, Feminism, and Neurath’s Auxiliary Motive.” Hypatia 19 (1): 4872..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Osimani, Barbara, and Mignini, Fiorenzo. 2015. “Causal Assessment of Pharmaceutical Treatments: Why Standards of Evidence Should Not Be the Same for Benefits and Harms.” Drug Safety 38 (1): 111..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reisch, George A. 2005. How the Cold War Transformed Philosophy of Science: To the Icy Slopes of Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rooney, Phyllis. 1992. “On Values in Science: Is the Epistemic/Non-epistemic Distinction Useful?” In PSA 1992: Proceedings of the 1992 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, Vol. 1, ed. David L. Hull and Micky Forbes, 13–22. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association.Google Scholar
Rudner, Richard. 1953. “The Scientist qua Scientist Makes Value Judgments.” Philosophy of Science 20 (1): 16..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shrader-Frechette, Kristin S., and McCoy, Earl D. 1993. Method in Ecology: Strategies for Conservation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stanford, Kyle. 2016. “Underdetermination of Scientific Theory.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Zalta, Edward N. Stanford, CA: Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/scientific-underdetermination/.Google Scholar
Steele, Katie. 2012. “The Scientist qua Policy Advisor Makes Value Judgments.” Philosophy of Science 79 (5): 893904..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stegenga, Jacob. 2016. “Hollow Hunt for Harms.” Perspectives on Science 24 (5): 481504..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Uebel, Thomas E. 2005. “Political Philosophy of Science in Logical Empiricism: The Left Vienna Circle.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science A 36 (4): 754–73..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilholt, Torsten. 2009. “Bias and Values in Scientific Research.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science A 40 (1): 92101..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Winsberg, Eric. 2012. “Values and Uncertainties in the Predictions of Global Climate Models.” Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 22 (2): 111–37..CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Zietsch, Brendan P., and Santtila, Pekka. 2013. “No Direct Relationship between Human Female Orgasm Rate and Number of Offspring.” Animal Behaviour 86 (2): 253–55..CrossRefGoogle Scholar