Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-pftt2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-27T08:08:17.226Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

COULD KNOWLEDGE-TALK BE LARGELY NON-LITERAL?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 May 2017

Abstract

Much work in epistemology, old and new, is devoted to explaining – or explaining away – the appeal of skeptical arguments (that is, arguments designed to impugn most, if not all, of our claims to know), as well as the fact that it also often seems as if we use knowledge-attributing sentences to express truths. More recently, philosophers have sought to explain other kinds of variability in our use of knowledge-attributing sentences besides, such as the kinds of variability that occur as a result of changing what is at stake or the salience of alternative possibilities, as in scenarios such as Keith DeRose's “bank cases.” These cases, and others like them, pose a dilemma very much like that posed by skeptical arguments. For they appear to suggest that we are wrong about something. Either we speak falsely when we attribute knowledge in the situations under consideration, or we speak falsely when we deny it. Or so it would seem. This paper argues that an alternative approach to explaining the relevant variability in our use of knowledge-attributing sentences – namely, a fictionalist one – merits serious consideration.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2017 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Blome-Tillman, M. 2009. ‘Knowledge and Presuppositions.’ Mind, 118: 241–94.Google Scholar
Blome-Tillman, M. 2014. Knowledge and Presuppositions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Brown, J. 2006. ‘Contextualism and Warranted Assertibility Manoeuvres.’ Philosophical Studies 130: 407–35.Google Scholar
Burgess, J. and Rosen, G. 1997. A Subject with No Object. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Camp, E. 2006a. ‘Contextualism, Metaphor, and What is Said.’ Mind and Language, 21: 280309.Google Scholar
Camp, E. 2006b. ‘Metaphor and That Certain ‘Je ne Sais Quoi’'.’ Philosophical Studies, 129: 125.Google Scholar
Camp, E. 2008. ‘Showing, Telling and Seeing. Metaphor and ‘Poetic’ Language.’ Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication, 3: 124.Google Scholar
Camp, E. 2009. ‘Two Varieties of Literary Imagination: Metaphor, Fiction, and Thought Experiments.’ In Wettstein, H. (ed.), Midwest Studies in Philosophy: Poetry and Philosophy XXXIII, pp. 107–30. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Camp, E. 2013. ‘Insinuation, Inexplicitness, and the Conversational Record’ (draft of 9/9/13 for Rutgers Semantics Workshop).Google Scholar
Chung, J. Forthcoming. ‘Skeptical Arguments, Conceptual Metaphors, and Cross-Cultural Challenges.’Google Scholar
Cohen, S. 1999. ‘Contextualism, Skepticism, and the Structure of Reasons.’ Philosophical Perspectives, 13: 5789.Google Scholar
Cohen, S. 2000a. ‘Contextualism and Skepticism.’ Philosophical Issues, 10: 94107.Google Scholar
Cohen, S. 2000b. ‘Replies.’ Noûs, 34 (S1): 132–9.Google Scholar
Craig, E. 1990. Knowledge and the State of Nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Davis, W. 2007. ‘Knowledge Claims and Context: Loose Use.’ Philosophical Studies, 132: 395438.Google Scholar
Davis, W. 2015. ‘Knowledge Claims and Context: Belief.’ Philosophical Studies, 172: 399432.Google Scholar
DeRose, K. 1995. ‘Solving the Skeptical Problem.’ Philosophical Review, 104: 152.Google Scholar
DeRose, K. 2009. The Case for Contextualism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dorr, C. 2005. ‘There are no Abstract Objects.’ https://files.nyu.edu/cd50/public/papers/NoAbstractObjects.pdf.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. 1970. ‘Epistemic Operators.’ Journal of Philosophy, 67: 1007–23.Google Scholar
Dutant, J. 2007. ‘The Case for Infallibilism.’ In Penco, C., Vignolo, M., Ottonelli, V. and Amoretti, C. (eds), Proceedings of the 4th Latin Meeting in Analytic Philosophy, pp. 5984. Genoa: University of Genoa.Google Scholar
Dutant, J. 2015. ‘The Legend of the Justified True Belief Analysis.’ Philosophical Perspectives, 29: 95145.Google Scholar
Eklund, M. 2015. ‘Fictionalism.’ In Zalta, E. N. (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2015/entries/fictionalism/.Google Scholar
Fantl, J. and McGrath, M. 2009. Knowledge in an Uncertain World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. 1976. ‘Discrimination and Perceptual Knowledge.’ Journal of Philosophy, 73: 771–91.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. 1979. ‘What Is Justified Belief?’ In Pappas, G. (ed.), Justification and Knowledge, pp. 125. Dordrecht: Reidel. Reprinted in Goldman, A. 1992. Liaisons: Philosophy Meets the Cognitive and Social Sciences. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Hawthorne, J. 2000. ‘Reply to Cohen.’ Noûs, 34: 117–20.Google Scholar
Hawthorne, J. 2004. Knowledge and Lotteries. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Klein, P. 1981. Certainty: A Refutation of Scepticism. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Klein, P. 1995. ‘Skepticism and Closure: Why the Evil Genius Argument Fails.’ Philosophical Topics, 23: 213–36.Google Scholar
Lehrer, K. 2000. Theory of Knowledge, 2nd edition. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1996. ‘Elusive Knowledge.’ Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74: 549–67.Google Scholar
MacFarlane, J. 2005. ‘The Assessment Sensitivity of Knowledge Attributions.’ In Gendler, T.S. and Hawthorne, J. (eds), Oxford Studies in Epistemology 1, pp. 197233. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
MacFarlane, J. 2011. ‘Relativism and Knowledge Attributions.’ In Pritchard, D. and Bernecker, S. (eds), The Routledge Companion to Epistemology, pp. 536–44. New York, NY: Routledge.Google Scholar
Machery, E. 2016. ‘Is There a Core Folk Epistemology?’ In International Conference on Ethno-Epistemology: Culture, Language, and Methodology, 3–5 June 2016, Kanazawa, Japan.Google Scholar
McGrath, M. 2015. ‘Two Purposes of Knowledge Attribution and the Contextualism Debate.’ In Henderson, D. and Greco, J. (eds), Epistemic Evaluation: Point and Purpose in Epistemology, pp. 138–57. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. 1986. A View from Nowhere. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nozick, R. 1981. Philosophical Explanations. Cambridge. MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Prades, J. 2000. ‘Scepticism, Contextualism, and Closure.’ Philosophical Issues, 10: 121–31.Google Scholar
Pritchard, D. 2005. ‘Contextualism, Skepticism, and Warranted Assertibility Manoeuvres.’ In Keim-Campbell, J., O'Rourke, M. and Silverstein, H. (eds), Knowledge and Skepticism, pp. 85104. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Pryor, J. 2000. ‘The Skeptic and the Dogmatist.’ Noûs, 34: 517–49.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1981. Reason, Truth, and History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pynn, G. 2015. ‘Pragmatic Contextualism.’ Metaphilosophy, 46: 2651.Google Scholar
Rysiew, P. 2001. ‘The Context-Sensitivity of Knowledge Attributions.’ Noûs, 35: 477514.Google Scholar
Rysiew, P. 2007. ‘Speaking of Knowing.’ Noûs, 41: 627–62.Google Scholar
Schaffer, J. 2004a. ‘From Contextualism to Contrastivism.’ Philosophical Studies, 119: 73103.Google Scholar
Schaffer, J. 2004b. ‘Skepticism, Contextualism, and Discrimination.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 69: 138–55.Google Scholar
Schaffer, J. and Szabo, Z. 2014. ‘Epistemic Comparativism: A Contextualist Semantics for Knowledge Ascriptions.’ Philosophical Studies, 2: 153.Google Scholar
Soames, S. 2002. Beyond Rigidity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sosa, E. 1994. ‘Philosophical Scepticism and Epistemic Circularity.’ Aristotelian Society Suppl. 68, 263–90.Google Scholar
Speaks, J. (2017) ‘Theories of Meaning.’ In Zalta, E.N. (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/meaning/.Google Scholar
Stanley, J. 2005. Knowledge and Practical Interests. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Stine, G. 1976. ‘Skepticism, Relevant Alternatives, and Deductive Closure.’ Philosophical Studies, 29: 249–61.Google Scholar
Stoutenburg, G. Forthcoming. ‘Strict Moderate Invariantism and Knowledge-Denials.’ Philosophical Studies.Google Scholar
Stroud, B. 1984. The Significance of Philosophical Skepticism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Stroud, B. 2011. ‘Critical Study of Mark Eli Kalderon (ed.) Fictionalism in Metaphysics.’ Noûs, 45: 375–85.Google Scholar
Szabó, Z. 2001. ‘Fictionalism and Moore's Paradox.’ Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 31: 293307.Google Scholar
Unger, P. 1971. ‘A Defense of Skepticism.’ Philosophical Review, 80: 198218.Google Scholar
Unger, P. 1975. Ignorance. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Unger, P. 1984. Philosophical Relativity. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Unger, P. 1986. ‘The Cone Model of Knowledge.’ Philosophical Topics, 14: 125–78.Google Scholar
Vogel, J. 1990a. ‘Cartesian Skepticism and Inference to the Best Explanation.’ Journal of Philosophy, 87: 658–66.Google Scholar
Vogel, J. 1990b. ‘Are there Counterexamples to the Closure Principle?’ In Roth, M. and Ross, G. (eds), Doubting: Contemporary Perspectives on Skepticism, pp. 1327. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
Walton, K. 1993. ‘Metaphor and Prop Oriented Make-Believe.’ European Journal of Philosophy, 1: 3957.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. 2000. Knowledge and Its Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wright, C. 2004. ‘Warrant for Nothing (and Foundations for Free)?Aristotelian Society Suppl., 78: 167212.Google Scholar
Yablo, S. 1998. ‘Does Ontology Rest on a Mistake?Aristotelian Society Suppl., 72: 229–6.Google Scholar
Yablo, S. 2000. ‘A Paradox of Existence.’ www.mit.edu/~yablo/apex.html.Google Scholar
Yablo, S. 2001. ‘Go Figure: A Path Through Fictionalism.’ Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 25: 72102.Google Scholar